This is a modern-English version of A Modern Utopia, originally written by Wells, H. G. (Herbert George). It has been thoroughly updated, including changes to sentence structure, words, spelling, and grammar—to ensure clarity for contemporary readers, while preserving the original spirit and nuance. If you click on a paragraph, you will see the original text that we modified, and you can toggle between the two versions.

Scroll to the bottom of this page and you will find a free ePUB download link for this book.

A MODERN UTOPIA
BY H. G. WELLS


A NOTE TO THE READER

This book is in all probability the last of a series of writings, of which—disregarding certain earlier disconnected essays—my Anticipations was the beginning. Originally I intended Anticipations to be my sole digression from my art or trade (or what you will) of an imaginative writer. I wrote that book in order to clear up the muddle in my own mind about innumerable social and political questions, questions I could not keep out of my work, which it distressed me to touch upon in a stupid haphazard way, and which no one, so far as I knew, had handled in a manner to satisfy my needs. But Anticipations did not achieve its end. I have a slow constructive hesitating sort of mind, and when I emerged from that undertaking I found I had still most of my questions to state and solve. In Mankind in the Making, therefore, I tried to review the social organisation in a different way, to consider it as an educational process instead of dealing with it as a thing with a future history, and if I made this second book even less satisfactory from a literary standpoint than the former (and this is my opinion), I blundered, I think, more edifyingly—at least from the point of view of my own instruction. I ventured upon several themes with a greater frankness than I had used in Anticipations, and came out of that second effort guilty of much rash writing, but with a considerable development of formed opinion. In many matters I had shaped out at last a certain personal certitude, upon which I feel I shall go for the rest of my days. In this present book I have tried to settle accounts with a number of issues left over or opened up by its two predecessors, to correct them in some particulars, and to give the general picture of a Utopia that has grown up in my mind during the course of these speculations as a state of affairs at once possible and more desirable than the world in which I live. But this book has brought me back to imaginative writing again. In its two predecessors the treatment of social organisation had been purely objective; here my intention has been a little wider and deeper, in that I have tried to present not simply an ideal, but an ideal in reaction with two personalities. Moreover, since this may be the last book of the kind I shall ever publish, I have written into it as well as I can the heretical metaphysical scepticism upon which all my thinking rests, and I have inserted certain sections reflecting upon the established methods of sociological and economic science....

This book is likely the final one in a series of writings, starting with my Anticipations, if we ignore some earlier unrelated essays. I originally planned for Anticipations to be my only departure from my craft as an imaginative writer. I wrote that book to clarify the confusion in my mind about countless social and political issues—topics I couldn't avoid in my work, which bothered me to address in a careless way, and which no one had handled in a way that met my needs. However, Anticipations didn’t fulfill its purpose. I have a slow, careful mind, and after completing that project, I realized I still had many questions left to ask and answer. In Mankind in the Making, I attempted to examine social organization differently, viewing it as an educational process rather than something with a defined future. While I believe this second book is even less satisfying in terms of literary quality than the first, I think I made more enlightening mistakes—at least from my own learning perspective. I tackled several topics with more honesty than I had in Anticipations, and although I ended up writing a lot of risky material, I also developed a clearer personal belief system that I think will guide me for the rest of my life. In this current book, I aimed to address several issues left unresolved or raised by the previous two, to correct certain details, and to present an overall vision of a Utopia that has formed in my mind throughout these reflections—a reality that is both achievable and preferable to the world I live in. But this book has drawn me back to imaginative writing. In its two predecessors, my approach to social organization was completely objective; here, I've aimed to be a bit broader and deeper by presenting not just an ideal, but an ideal interacting with two personalities. Furthermore, since this might be the last book of this nature that I publish, I've tried to incorporate the heretical metaphysical skepticism that underpins all my thinking, and I’ve included certain sections that reflect on established methods of sociological and economic science....

The last four words will not attract the butterfly reader, I know. I have done my best to make the whole of this book as lucid and entertaining as its matter permits, because I want it read by as many people as possible, but I do not promise anything but rage and confusion to him who proposes to glance through my pages just to see if I agree with him, or to begin in the middle, or to read without a constantly alert attention. If you are not already a little interested and open-minded with regard to social and political questions, and a little exercised in self-examination, you will find neither interest nor pleasure here. If your mind is “made up” upon such issues your time will be wasted on these pages. And even if you are a willing reader you may require a little patience for the peculiar method I have this time adopted.

The last four words won’t attract the casual reader, I know. I’ve done my best to make this entire book as clear and entertaining as the content allows because I want as many people as possible to read it, but I can’t promise anything but frustration and confusion to anyone who just flips through my pages to see if I agree with them, or starts in the middle, or reads without paying close attention. If you’re not already at least a little interested and open-minded about social and political issues, and a bit reflective, you won’t find any interest or enjoyment here. If your views are already “set” on these topics, you’ll just waste your time on these pages. Even if you’re a willing reader, you might need a bit of patience for the unique approach I’ve taken this time.

That method assumes an air of haphazard, but it is not so careless as it seems. I believe it to be—even now that I am through with the book—the best way to a sort of lucid vagueness which has always been my intention in this matter. I tried over several beginnings of a Utopian book before I adopted this. I rejected from the outset the form of the argumentative essay, the form which appeals most readily to what is called the “serious” reader, the reader who is often no more than the solemnly impatient parasite of great questions. He likes everything in hard, heavy lines, black and white, yes and no, because he does not understand how much there is that cannot be presented at all in that way; wherever there is any effect of obliquity, of incommensurables, wherever there is any levity or humour or difficulty of multiplex presentation, he refuses attention. Mentally he seems to be built up upon an invincible assumption that the Spirit of Creation cannot count beyond two, he deals only in alternatives. Such readers I have resolved not to attempt to please here. Even if I presented all my tri-clinic crystals as systems of cubes―! Indeed I felt it would not be worth doing. But having rejected the “serious” essay as a form, I was still greatly exercised, I spent some vacillating months, over the scheme of this book. I tried first a recognised method of viewing questions from divergent points that has always attracted me and which I have never succeeded in using, the discussion novel, after the fashion of Peacock's (and Mr. Mallock's) development of the ancient dialogue; but this encumbered me with unnecessary characters and the inevitable complication of intrigue among them, and I abandoned it. After that I tried to cast the thing into a shape resembling a little the double personality of Boswell's Johnson, a sort of interplay between monologue and commentator; but that too, although it got nearer to the quality I sought, finally failed. Then I hesitated over what one might call “hard narrative.” It will be evident to the experienced reader that by omitting certain speculative and metaphysical elements and by elaborating incident, this book might have been reduced to a straightforward story. But I did not want to omit as much on this occasion. I do not see why I should always pander to the vulgar appetite for stark stories. And in short, I made it this. I explain all this in order to make it clear to the reader that, however queer this book appears at the first examination, it is the outcome of trial and deliberation, it is intended to be as it is. I am aiming throughout at a sort of shot-silk texture between philosophical discussion on the one hand and imaginative narrative on the other.

That method might seem random, but it’s not as careless as it looks. Even now that I’ve finished the book, I believe it’s the best way to achieve the kind of clear ambiguity I intended from the start. I went through several drafts of a Utopian book before settling on this one. I immediately ruled out the argumentative essay format, which tends to appeal to what’s often called the “serious” reader. This reader is typically just a solemnly impatient consumer of big questions. They prefer everything laid out in strict black and white, yes or no, because they don’t grasp how much can’t be conveyed that way. When things get a bit crooked, complicated, or even humorous, they tune out. Mentally, they seem to operate under the flawed belief that the Spirit of Creation can only handle two options, sticking exclusively to binary choices. I decided not to try to please such readers here, even if I rewrote all my complex ideas as simple systems of cubes. Honestly, I felt that wouldn’t be worth it. After dismissing the “serious” essay format, I still grappled with how to structure this book for several frustrating months. Initially, I tried a recognized method of exploring topics from different perspectives that I’ve always been drawn to but never managed to effectively use: the discussion novel, inspired by the ancient dialogues in the style of Peacock (and Mr. Mallock); however, that approached became too bogged down with unnecessary characters and their inevitable plots, so I dropped it. Then I considered creating a shape similar to Boswell’s Johnson, mixing monologues with commentary; but that too, while closer to what I was looking for, ultimately didn’t work. Next, I wavered on what could be called “hard narrative.” Experienced readers will see that by skipping some speculative and philosophical elements and focusing more on incidents, this book could have easily become a straightforward tale. But I didn’t want to cut so much this time. I don’t see why I should always cater to the basic craving for plain stories. So in the end, I made it like this. I’m sharing all of this to clarify for the reader that, no matter how odd this book may seem at first glance, it is the result of careful thought and intention; it’s meant to be this way. I’m striving for a kind of blended texture between philosophical discussion and imaginative storytelling throughout.

H. G. WELLS.

H.G. Wells.

CONTENTS

  • The Owner of the Voice
  • Chapter the First—Topographical
  • Chapter the Second—Concerning Freedoms
  • Chapter the Third—Utopian Economics
  • Chapter the Fourth—The Voice of Nature
  • Chapter the Fifth—Failure in a Modern Utopia
  • Chapter the Sixth—Women in a Modern Utopia
  • Chapter the Seventh—A Few Utopian Impressions
  • Chapter the Eighth—My Utopian Self
  • Chapter the Ninth—The Samurai
  • Chapter the Tenth—Race in Utopia
  • Chapter the Eleventh—The Bubble Bursts
  • Appendix—Scepticism of the Instrument

A MODERN UTOPIA

THE OWNER OF THE VOICE

There are works, and this is one of them, that are best begun with a portrait of the author. And here, indeed, because of a very natural misunderstanding this is the only course to take. Throughout these papers sounds a note, a distinctive and personal note, a note that tends at times towards stridency; and all that is not, as these words are, in Italics, is in one Voice. Now, this Voice, and this is the peculiarity of the matter, is not to be taken as the Voice of the ostensible author who fathers these pages. You have to clear your mind of any preconceptions in that respect. The Owner of the Voice you must figure to yourself as a whitish plump man, a little under the middle size and age, with such blue eyes as many Irishmen have, and agile in his movements and with a slight tonsorial baldness—a penny might cover it—of the crown. His front is convex. He droops at times like most of us, but for the greater part he bears himself as valiantly as a sparrow. Occasionally his hand flies out with a fluttering gesture of illustration. And his Voice (which is our medium henceforth) is an unattractive tenor that becomes at times aggressive. Him you must imagine as sitting at a table reading a manuscript about Utopias, a manuscript he holds in two hands that are just a little fat at the wrist. The curtain rises upon him so. But afterwards, if the devices of this declining art of literature prevail, you will go with him through curious and interesting experiences. Yet, ever and again, you will find him back at that little table, the manuscript in his hand, and the expansion of his ratiocinations about Utopia conscientiously resumed. The entertainment before you is neither the set drama of the work of fiction you are accustomed to read, nor the set lecturing of the essay you are accustomed to evade, but a hybrid of these two. If you figure this owner of the Voice as sitting, a little nervously, a little modestly, on a stage, with table, glass of water and all complete, and myself as the intrusive chairman insisting with a bland ruthlessness upon his “few words” of introduction before he recedes into the wings, and if furthermore you figure a sheet behind our friend on which moving pictures intermittently appear, and if finally you suppose his subject to be the story of the adventure of his soul among Utopian inquiries, you will be prepared for some at least of the difficulties of this unworthy but unusual work.

There are certain works, and this is one of them, that are best started with a portrait of the author. And here, indeed, due to a common misunderstanding, this is the only way to proceed. Throughout these papers, there’s a distinctive and personal tone that sometimes becomes a bit harsh; and everything that isn't in Italics, like these words, is in one Voice. Now, this Voice, and this is the interesting part, shouldn't be seen as the Voice of the obvious author who created these pages. You need to clear your mind of any expectations in that regard. Picture the Owner of the Voice as a slightly chubby, somewhat short and middle-aged man, with blue eyes like many Irishmen have, agile in his movements and with a slight bald spot up top—a penny might cover it. His forehead curves out. He slouches at times like most of us, but mostly he carries himself as bravely as a sparrow. Occasionally, his hand gestures animatedly for emphasis. And his Voice (which will be our medium from now on) is an unattractive tenor that can sometimes come across as aggressive. Imagine him sitting at a table, reading a manuscript about Utopias, holding it in both hands that are a little chubby at the wrists. The curtain rises on him like that. But afterward, if the tricks of this declining art of literature succeed, you will accompany him through curious and interesting experiences. Yet, time and again, you’ll find him back at that little table, the manuscript in his hand, continuing his thoughtful exploration of Utopia. What you have before you is neither the conventional drama of fiction you’re used to reading, nor the structured lecturing of an essay you tend to avoid, but a blend of the two. If you visualize this Voice owner sitting a bit nervously, a bit modestly, on a stage with a table, a glass of water, and everything else complete, and me as the intrusive host insisting with polite insistence on his “few words” of introduction before he steps back into the shadows, and if you also picture a backdrop behind our friend upon which moving images appear intermittently, and finally if you assume his topic is the adventure of his soul with Utopian inquiries, you will be ready for at least some of the challenges of this unworthy yet unusual work.

But over against this writer here presented, there is also another earthly person in the book, who gathers himself together into a distinct personality only after a preliminary complication with the reader. This person is spoken of as the botanist, and he is a leaner, rather taller, graver and much less garrulous man. His face is weakly handsome and done in tones of grey, he is fairish and grey-eyed, and you would suspect him of dyspepsia. It is a justifiable suspicion. Men of this type, the chairman remarks with a sudden intrusion of exposition, are romantic with a shadow of meanness, they seek at once to conceal and shape their sensuous cravings beneath egregious sentimentalities, they get into mighty tangles and troubles with women, and he has had his troubles. You will hear of them, for that is the quality of his type. He gets no personal expression in this book, the Voice is always that other's, but you gather much of the matter and something of the manner of his interpolations from the asides and the tenour of the Voice.

But alongside this writer, there's another character in the book who only evolves into a distinct personality after a bit of a complex interaction with the reader. This character is referred to as the botanist, a leaner, taller, more serious, and much less talkative man. His face is weakly handsome and shaded in grey tones; he has fair skin and grey eyes, which might make you suspect he has digestive issues. That suspicion is understandable. Men like him, the chairman notes with a sudden bit of explanation, are romantic with a hint of unkindness; they try to hide and shape their desires under excessive sentimentalism, leading to complicated issues with women, and he has definitely had his share of problems. You'll hear about them because that's just how his kind is. He doesn’t express himself much in this book; the Voice always belongs to someone else, but you can pick up a lot of his thoughts and some of his style from the asides and the tone of the Voice.

So much by way of portraiture is necessary to present the explorers of the Modern Utopia, which will unfold itself as a background to these two enquiring figures. The image of a cinematograph entertainment is the one to grasp. There will be an effect of these two people going to and fro in front of the circle of a rather defective lantern, which sometimes jams and sometimes gets out of focus, but which does occasionally succeed in displaying on a screen a momentary moving picture of Utopian conditions. Occasionally the picture goes out altogether, the Voice argues and argues, and the footlights return, and then you find yourself listening again to the rather too plump little man at his table laboriously enunciating propositions, upon whom the curtain rises now.

To effectively portray the explorers of the Modern Utopia, we need to set the scene for these two curious characters. Think of it like a movie projector. You’ll see these two people moving back and forth in front of a somewhat faulty projector that sometimes gets stuck or blurs the image, but every now and then it manages to show a fleeting glimpse of Utopian life. Sometimes the image disappears completely, the debate continues, and then the lights come back on, bringing you back to the slightly stocky little man at his table, carefully spelling out his ideas, just as the curtain rises.

CHAPTER THE FIRST
Topographical

§ 1

The Utopia of a modern dreamer must needs differ in one fundamental aspect from the Nowheres and Utopias men planned before Darwin quickened the thought of the world. Those were all perfect and static States, a balance of happiness won for ever against the forces of unrest and disorder that inhere in things. One beheld a healthy and simple generation enjoying the fruits of the earth in an atmosphere of virtue and happiness, to be followed by other virtuous, happy, and entirely similar generations, until the Gods grew weary. Change and development were dammed back by invincible dams for ever. But the Modern Utopia must be not static but kinetic, must shape not as a permanent state but as a hopeful stage, leading to a long ascent of stages. Nowadays we do not resist and overcome the great stream of things, but rather float upon it. We build now not citadels, but ships of state. For one ordered arrangement of citizens rejoicing in an equality of happiness safe and assured to them and their children for ever, we have to plan “a flexible common compromise, in which a perpetually novel succession of individualities may converge most effectually upon a comprehensive onward development.” That is the first, most generalised difference between a Utopia based upon modern conceptions and all the Utopias that were written in the former time.

The Utopia of a modern dreamer must differ in one fundamental way from the Nowheres and Utopias that people envisioned before Darwin inspired the world's thinking. Those were all perfect and static states, where happiness was achieved forever against the forces of unrest and disorder inherent in life. You saw a healthy and simple generation enjoying the earth’s bounty in an atmosphere of virtue and happiness, followed by other virtuous, happy, and completely similar generations, until the Gods grew tired. Change and development were held back by unbreakable barriers forever. But the Modern Utopia must be kinetic, not static; it should shape not as a permanent state but as a hopeful stage, leading to a long ascent of stages. Nowadays, we don’t resist and conquer the great flow of things; we float along with it instead. We no longer build citadels but rather ships of state. Instead of one ordered group of citizens celebrating an assured equality of happiness for themselves and their children forever, we need to plan “a flexible common compromise, in which a perpetually novel succession of individualities may converge most effectively upon a comprehensive onward development.” That is the first, most general difference between a Utopia based on modern concepts and all the Utopias written in the past.

Our business here is to be Utopian, to make vivid and credible, if we can, first this facet and then that, of an imaginary whole and happy world. Our deliberate intention is to be not, indeed, impossible, but most distinctly impracticable, by every scale that reaches only between to-day and to-morrow. We are to turn our backs for a space upon the insistent examination of the thing that is, and face towards the freer air, the ampler spaces of the thing that perhaps might be, to the projection of a State or city “worth while,” to designing upon the sheet of our imaginations the picture of a life conceivably possible, and yet better worth living than our own. That is our present enterprise. We are going to lay down certain necessary starting propositions, and then we shall proceed to explore the sort of world these propositions give us....

Our goal here is to be Utopian, to vividly and credibly illustrate, if we can, this aspect and then that, of an imagined whole and happy world. Our clear intention is not to be impossible, but definitely impractical, by any measure that only looks from today to tomorrow. We need to turn away for a moment from the constant inspection of what is, and instead look toward the freer air, the bigger possibilities of what could be, to envision a State or city that is “worth it,” to design on the canvas of our imaginations a picture of a life that might be possible and yet better than our own. That is our current mission. We’re going to set down some essential starting points, and then we’ll explore the kind of world these ideas create for us....

It is no doubt an optimistic enterprise. But it is good for awhile to be free from the carping note that must needs be audible when we discuss our present imperfections, to release ourselves from practical difficulties and the tangle of ways and means. It is good to stop by the track for a space, put aside the knapsack, wipe the brows, and talk a little of the upper slopes of the mountain we think we are climbing, would but the trees let us see it.

It’s definitely an optimistic endeavor. But it feels nice for a moment to step away from the nagging criticism that always comes up when we talk about our current flaws, to free ourselves from practical challenges and the mess of options. It’s refreshing to pause for a while, set down the backpack, wipe our foreheads, and chat a bit about the higher peaks of the mountain we believe we’re climbing, if only the trees would let us see it.

There is to be no inquiry here of policy and method. This is to be a holiday from politics and movements and methods. But for all that, we must needs define certain limitations. Were we free to have our untrammelled desire, I suppose we should follow Morris to his Nowhere, we should change the nature of man and the nature of things together; we should make the whole race wise, tolerant, noble, perfect—wave our hands to a splendid anarchy, every man doing as it pleases him, and none pleased to do evil, in a world as good in its essential nature, as ripe and sunny, as the world before the Fall. But that golden age, that perfect world, comes out into the possibilities of space and time. In space and time the pervading Will to Live sustains for evermore a perpetuity of aggressions. Our proposal here is upon a more practical plane at least than that. We are to restrict ourselves first to the limitations of human possibility as we know them in the men and women of this world to-day, and then to all the inhumanity, all the insubordination of nature. We are to shape our state in a world of uncertain seasons, sudden catastrophes, antagonistic diseases, and inimical beasts and vermin, out of men and women with like passions, like uncertainties of mood and desire to our own. And, moreover, we are going to accept this world of conflict, to adopt no attitude of renunciation towards it, to face it in no ascetic spirit, but in the mood of the Western peoples, whose purpose is to survive and overcome. So much we adopt in common with those who deal not in Utopias, but in the world of Here and Now.

There won’t be any discussion about policies or methods here. This is supposed to be a break from politics, movements, and methods. However, we still need to set some limits. If we could freely pursue our desires, I guess we would follow Morris to his Nowhere, changing both human nature and the nature of things at the same time. We would make everyone wise, tolerant, noble, and perfect—waving goodbye to a glorious anarchy where everyone does what they want, and no one chooses to do evil, in a world as inherently good, ripe, and bright as the world before the Fall. But that golden age, that perfect world, exists beyond the limits of space and time. In space and time, the persistent Will to Live constantly creates ongoing conflicts. Our proposal here is at least more practical than that. We are going to limit ourselves first to the possibilities of humanity as we recognize them in the people of this world today, and then to all the cruelty and disobedience of nature. We need to shape our society in a world of unpredictable seasons, sudden disasters, opposing diseases, and hostile animals and pests, using men and women with similar passions, moods, and desires to our own. Moreover, we are going to accept this world of conflict; we won’t adopt an attitude of renunciation towards it, and we will face it not with an ascetic spirit, but with the mindset of Western people, whose goal is to survive and thrive. This is what we share in common with those who deal not in Utopias, but in the world of Here and Now.

Certain liberties, however, following the best Utopian precedents, we may take with existing fact. We assume that the tone of public thought may be entirely different from what it is in the present world. We permit ourselves a free hand with the mental conflict of life, within the possibilities of the human mind as we know it. We permit ourselves also a free hand with all the apparatus of existence that man has, so to speak, made for himself, with houses, roads, clothing, canals, machinery, with laws, boundaries, conventions, and traditions, with schools, with literature and religious organisation, with creeds and customs, with everything, in fact, that it lies within man's power to alter. That, indeed, is the cardinal assumption of all Utopian speculations old and new; the Republic and Laws of Plato, and More's Utopia, Howells' implicit Altruria, and Bellamy's future Boston, Comte's great Western Republic, Hertzka's Freeland, Cabet's Icaria, and Campanella's City of the Sun, are built, just as we shall build, upon that, upon the hypothesis of the complete emancipation of a community of men from tradition, from habits, from legal bonds, and that subtler servitude possessions entail. And much of the essential value of all such speculations lies in this assumption of emancipation, lies in that regard towards human freedom, in the undying interest of the human power of self-escape, the power to resist the causation of the past, and to evade, initiate, endeavour, and overcome.

Certain freedoms, however, following the best Utopian examples, we may take with existing facts. We assume that public opinion can be completely different from what it is in today’s world. We allow ourselves to explore the mental struggles of life, within the boundaries of the human mind as we understand it. We also give ourselves the freedom to examine all the tools of existence that humans have, so to speak, created for themselves: houses, roads, clothing, canals, machinery, laws, boundaries, conventions, and traditions, schools, literature and religious organizations, creeds and customs, and everything else that humans can change. This, in fact, is the fundamental assumption of all Utopian ideas, both old and new; Plato's Republic and Laws, More's Utopia, Howells' implicit Altruria, Bellamy's future Boston, Comte's great Western Republic, Hertzka's Freeland, Cabet's Icaria, and Campanella's City of the Sun, are all based on this idea, on the hypothesis of the complete liberation of a community of people from tradition, from habits, from legal constraints, and the subtler shackles that possessions bring. Much of the essential value of these ideas lies in this assumption of liberation, in the respect for human freedom, in the enduring interest of the human ability to escape, the capacity to resist the influences of the past, and to evade, initiate, strive, and overcome.

§ 2

There are very definite artistic limitations also.

There are some clear artistic limitations as well.

There must always be a certain effect of hardness and thinness about Utopian speculations. Their common fault is to be comprehensively jejune. That which is the blood and warmth and reality of life is largely absent; there are no individualities, but only generalised people. In almost every Utopia—except, perhaps, Morris's “News from Nowhere”—one sees handsome but characterless buildings, symmetrical and perfect cultivations, and a multitude of people, healthy, happy, beautifully dressed, but without any personal distinction whatever. Too often the prospect resembles the key to one of those large pictures of coronations, royal weddings, parliaments, conferences, and gatherings so popular in Victorian times, in which, instead of a face, each figure bears a neat oval with its index number legibly inscribed. This burthens us with an incurable effect of unreality, and I do not see how it is altogether to be escaped. It is a disadvantage that has to be accepted. Whatever institution has existed or exists, however irrational, however preposterous, has, by virtue of its contact with individualities, an effect of realness and rightness no untried thing may share. It has ripened, it has been christened with blood, it has been stained and mellowed by handling, it has been rounded and dented to the softened contours that we associate with life; it has been salted, maybe, in a brine of tears. But the thing that is merely proposed, the thing that is merely suggested, however rational, however necessary, seems strange and inhuman in its clear, hard, uncompromising lines, its unqualified angles and surfaces.

There’s always a certain hardness and thinness to Utopian ideas. Their common flaw is being completely simplistic. The elements that give life its warmth and reality are largely missing; instead of unique individuals, there are only generic people. In almost every Utopia—except, maybe, Morris's “News from Nowhere”—you see attractive but bland buildings, perfectly symmetrical landscapes, and a crowd of people who are healthy, happy, and well-dressed, yet lack any personal distinction. Too often, the scene looks like one of those large pictures of coronations, royal weddings, parliaments, conferences, and gatherings that were so popular in Victorian times, where instead of faces, each figure has a neat oval with a number clearly printed on it. This leaves us with an undeniable feeling of unreality, which seems unescapable. It's a drawback we have to accept. Any institution that has existed or exists, no matter how irrational or ridiculous, has, through its interaction with actual people, a sense of reality and authenticity that something untested can’t replicate. It has matured, it has been shaped by experience, it has been marked by struggle, it has taken on the soft curves we associate with life; it may have even been seasoned by tears. But something that’s only proposed, something that’s merely suggested, no matter how logical or necessary, feels strange and inhuman in its stark, rigid lines and uncompromising angles and surfaces.

There is no help for it, there it is! The Master suffers with the last and least of his successors. For all the humanity he wins to, through his dramatic device of dialogue, I doubt if anyone has ever been warmed to desire himself a citizen in the Republic of Plato; I doubt if anyone could stand a month of the relentless publicity of virtue planned by More.... No one wants to live in any community of intercourse really, save for the sake of the individualities he would meet there. The fertilising conflict of individualities is the ultimate meaning of the personal life, and all our Utopias no more than schemes for bettering that interplay. At least, that is how life shapes itself more and more to modern perceptions. Until you bring in individualities, nothing comes into being, and a Universe ceases when you shiver the mirror of the least of individual minds.

There’s no way around it, it is what it is! The Master shares in the struggles of his final and least influential successors. For all the people he connects with through his powerful use of dialogue, I doubt anyone has ever felt inspired to be a citizen in Plato’s Republic; I doubt anyone could tolerate a month of the unyielding promotion of virtue designed by More.... No one genuinely wants to be part of any community, except for the interesting individuals they would encounter there. The dynamic clash of individualities is the core essence of personal life, and all our Utopias are merely plans to enhance that interaction. At least, that’s how life increasingly aligns with contemporary views. Until you introduce individualities, nothing truly exists, and a Universe ends when you disrupt the smallest of individual minds.

§ 3

No less than a planet will serve the purpose of a modern Utopia. Time was when a mountain valley or an island seemed to promise sufficient isolation for a polity to maintain itself intact from outward force; the Republic of Plato stood armed ready for defensive war, and the New Atlantis and the Utopia of More in theory, like China and Japan through many centuries of effectual practice, held themselves isolated from intruders. Such late instances as Butler's satirical “Erewhon,” and Mr. Stead's queendom of inverted sexual conditions in Central Africa, found the Tibetan method of slaughtering the inquiring visitor a simple, sufficient rule. But the whole trend of modern thought is against the permanence of any such enclosures. We are acutely aware nowadays that, however subtly contrived a State may be, outside your boundary lines the epidemic, the breeding barbarian or the economic power, will gather its strength to overcome you. The swift march of invention is all for the invader. Now, perhaps you might still guard a rocky coast or a narrow pass; but what of that near to-morrow when the flying machine soars overhead, free to descend at this point or that? A state powerful enough to keep isolated under modern conditions would be powerful enough to rule the world, would be, indeed, if not actively ruling, yet passively acquiescent in all other human organisations, and so responsible for them altogether. World-state, therefore, it must be.

No less than a planet will serve the purpose of a modern Utopia. There was a time when a mountain valley or an island seemed to offer enough isolation for a society to stay intact from outside forces; Plato's Republic was ready for defensive war, and the New Atlantis and More's Utopia, theoretically, like China and Japan for many centuries in practice, kept themselves isolated from intruders. More recent examples like Butler's satirical “Erewhon,” and Mr. Stead's queendom with its reversed sexual conditions in Central Africa, found the Tibetan method of dispatching curious visitors to be a straightforward, sufficient rule. But the general trend of modern thought is against the permanence of such enclosures. We are sharply aware today that, no matter how cleverly designed a State may be, outside your borders the epidemic, the rising barbarian, or the economic power will gather strength to defeat you. The rapid pace of invention favors the invader. Perhaps you can still defend a rocky coast or a narrow pass; but what about the near future when flying machines can soar overhead, easily landing wherever they choose? A state powerful enough to remain isolated under modern conditions would be strong enough to rule the world; it would be, in fact, if not actively ruling, then passively complicit in all other human organizations, and thus responsible for them altogether. Therefore, it must be a world-state.

That leaves no room for a modern Utopia in Central Africa, or in South America, or round about the pole, those last refuges of ideality. The floating isle of La Cité Morellyste no longer avails. We need a planet. Lord Erskine, the author of a Utopia (“Armata”) that might have been inspired by Mr. Hewins, was the first of all Utopists to perceive this—he joined his twin planets pole to pole by a sort of umbilical cord. But the modern imagination, obsessed by physics, must travel further than that.

That leaves no space for a modern Utopia in Central Africa, South America, or near the poles, those last havens of idealism. The floating island of La Cité Morellyste is no longer useful. We need an entire planet. Lord Erskine, the author of a Utopia (“Armata”) that could have been inspired by Mr. Hewins, was the first Utopist to realize this—he connected his twin planets from pole to pole with a sort of umbilical cord. But today’s imagination, fixated on physics, has to reach further than that.

Out beyond Sirius, far in the deeps of space, beyond the flight of a cannon-ball flying for a billion years, beyond the range of unaided vision, blazes the star that is our Utopia's sun. To those who know where to look, with a good opera-glass aiding good eyes, it and three fellows that seem in a cluster with it—though they are incredible billions of miles nearer—make just the faintest speck of light. About it go planets, even as our planets, but weaving a different fate, and in its place among them is Utopia, with its sister mate, the Moon. It is a planet like our planet, the same continents, the same islands, the same oceans and seas, another Fuji-Yama is beautiful there dominating another Yokohama—and another Matterhorn overlooks the icy disorder of another Theodule. It is so like our planet that a terrestrial botanist might find his every species there, even to the meanest pondweed or the remotest Alpine blossom....

Out beyond Sirius, far into the depths of space, beyond the trajectory of a cannonball flying for a billion years, beyond the range of unaided vision, shines the star that is our Utopia's sun. For those who know where to look, with a good pair of binoculars helping good eyesight, it and three companions that appear clustered with it—though they are billions of miles closer—make just the faintest glimmer of light. Planets orbit around it, just as ours do, but weaving a different destiny, and among them is Utopia, accompanied by its counterpart, the Moon. It’s a planet like ours, with the same continents, the same islands, the same oceans and seas; another Fuji-Yama stands beautifully dominating another Yokohama—and another Matterhorn overlooks the icy chaos of another Theodule. It’s so similar to our planet that a terrestrial botanist might find every species there, even the simplest pondweed or the rarest Alpine flower...

Only when he had gathered that last and turned about to find his inn again, perhaps he would not find his inn!

Only when he had collected that last bit and turned around to find his inn again, he might not find it!

Suppose now that two of us were actually to turn about in just that fashion. Two, I think, for to face a strange planet, even though it be a wholly civilised one, without some other familiar backing, dashes the courage overmuch. Suppose that we were indeed so translated even as we stood. You figure us upon some high pass in the Alps, and though I—being one easily made giddy by stooping—am no botanist myself, if my companion were to have a specimen tin under his arm—so long as it is not painted that abominable popular Swiss apple green—I would make it no occasion for quarrel! We have tramped and botanised and come to a rest, and, sitting among rocks, we have eaten our lunch and finished our bottle of Yvorne, and fallen into a talk of Utopias, and said such things as I have been saying. I could figure it myself upon that little neck of the Lucendro Pass, upon the shoulder of the Piz Lucendro, for there once I lunched and talked very pleasantly, and we are looking down upon the Val Bedretto, and Villa and Fontana and Airolo try to hide from us under the mountain side—three-quarters of a mile they are vertically below. (Lantern.) With that absurd nearness of effect one gets in the Alps, we see the little train a dozen miles away, running down the Biaschina to Italy, and the Lukmanier Pass beyond Piora left of us, and the San Giacomo right, mere footpaths under our feet....

Let's imagine that two of us actually turned around in exactly that way. Two, I think, because facing a strange planet, even if it’s completely civilized, without some familiar support can be quite daunting. Imagine if we were suddenly transported just as we are. Picture us standing on a high pass in the Alps, and though I easily get dizzy from bending down and am not a botanist myself, if my companion had a specimen tin under his arm—provided it's not painted that awful popular Swiss apple green—I wouldn't make it a reason to argue! We've hiked and botanized and decided to take a break. Sitting among the rocks, we enjoyed our lunch, finished a bottle of Yvorne, and started discussing Utopias, saying things like I’ve just mentioned. I can picture it on that little ridge of the Lucendro Pass, on the shoulder of the Piz Lucendro, because that’s where I once had lunch and had a great conversation. We are looking down at Val Bedretto, and Villa and Fontana and Airolo are trying to hide from us beneath the mountainside—three-quarters of a mile directly below. With that silly sense of closeness you get in the Alps, we can see a little train a dozen miles away, traveling down the Biaschina to Italy, with the Lukmanier Pass beyond Piora to our left and the San Giacomo to our right, just footpaths beneath our feet...

And behold! in the twinkling of an eye we are in that other world!

And look! In the blink of an eye, we are in that other world!

We should scarcely note the change. Not a cloud would have gone from the sky. It might be the remote town below would take a different air, and my companion the botanist, with his educated observation, might almost see as much, and the train, perhaps, would be gone out of the picture, and the embanked straightness of the Ticino in the Ambri-Piotta meadows—that might be altered, but that would be all the visible change. Yet I have an idea that in some obscure manner we should come to feel at once a difference in things.

We would hardly notice the change. Not a cloud would have moved in the sky. The distant town below might have a different vibe, and my friend the botanist, with his trained eye, might notice that too. The train, maybe, would disappear from view, and the straight stretch of the Ticino in the Ambri-Piotta meadows— that might be different, but that would be the only visible change. Still, I have a feeling that somehow we would immediately sense a difference in things.

The botanist's glance would, under a subtle attraction, float back to Airolo. “It's queer,” he would say quite idly, “but I never noticed that building there to the right before.”

The botanist would, drawn by a subtle pull, look back at Airolo. “It's strange,” he would say casually, “but I never noticed that building on the right before.”

“Which building?”

"Which building is it?"

“That to the right—with a queer sort of thing―”

“That over there to the right—with a strange sort of thing—”

“I see now. Yes. Yes, it's certainly an odd-looking affair.... And big, you know! Handsome! I wonder―”

“I get it now. Yeah. Yeah, it’s definitely a strange-looking thing... And huge, you know! Stylish! I wonder―”

That would interrupt our Utopian speculations. We should both discover that the little towns below had changed—but how, we should not have marked them well enough to know. It would be indefinable, a change in the quality of their grouping, a change in the quality of their remote, small shapes.

That would disrupt our idealistic thoughts. We would both realize that the little towns below had changed—but we wouldn’t have noticed exactly how. It would be hard to define, a shift in how they’re arranged, a change in the quality of their distant, small forms.

I should flick a few crumbs from my knee, perhaps. “It's odd,” I should say, for the tenth or eleventh time, with a motion to rise, and we should get up and stretch ourselves, and, still a little puzzled, turn our faces towards the path that clambers down over the tumbled rocks and runs round by the still clear lake and down towards the Hospice of St. Gotthard—if perchance we could still find that path.

I should brush a few crumbs off my knee, maybe. “It's strange,” I should say, for the tenth or eleventh time, while moving to stand up, and we should get up and stretch, still a bit confused, turning our faces toward the trail that winds down over the scattered rocks and goes around the still clear lake and down toward the Hospice of St. Gotthard—if by chance we could still find that path.

Long before we got to that, before even we got to the great high road, we should have hints from the stone cabin in the nape of the pass—it would be gone or wonderfully changed—from the very goats upon the rocks, from the little hut by the rough bridge of stone, that a mighty difference had come to the world of men.

Long before we reached that point, even before we got to the main road, we would have clues from the stone cabin at the back of the pass—it would either be gone or transformed in some remarkable way—from the goats on the rocks, and from the small hut by the rugged stone bridge, that a significant change had happened in the world of people.

And presently, amazed and amazing, we should happen on a man—no Swiss—dressed in unfamiliar clothing and speaking an unfamiliar speech....

And soon, both amazed and amazing, we might come across a man—definitely not Swiss—wearing strange clothes and speaking in a language we don’t recognize....

§ 4

Before nightfall we should be drenched in wonders, but still we should have wonder left for the thing my companion, with his scientific training, would no doubt be the first to see. He would glance up, with that proprietary eye of the man who knows his constellations down to the little Greek letters. I imagine his exclamation. He would at first doubt his eyes. I should inquire the cause of his consternation, and it would be hard to explain. He would ask me with a certain singularity of manner for “Orion,” and I should not find him; for the Great Bear, and it would have vanished. “Where?” I should ask, and “where?” seeking among that scattered starriness, and slowly I should acquire the wonder that possessed him.

Before night falls, we should be amazed by wonders, but we should still have some wonder left for the thing my companion, with his scientific background, would definitely notice first. He would look up with that knowledgeable gaze of someone who knows his constellations inside and out. I can picture his exclamation. At first, he would doubt what he’s seeing. I would ask what’s wrong, and it would be hard to explain. He would ask me in a unique way for “Orion,” and I wouldn’t be able to find it; for the Great Bear, and it would have disappeared. “Where?” I would ask, and “where?” searching among that scattered starry sky, and slowly I would begin to feel the wonder that he felt.

Then, for the first time, perhaps, we should realise from this unfamiliar heaven that not the world had changed, but ourselves—that we had come into the uttermost deeps of space.

Then, for the first time, maybe we should realize from this strange sky that it wasn't the world that had changed, but us—that we had entered the very depths of space.

§ 5

We need suppose no linguistic impediments to intercourse. The whole world will surely have a common language, that is quite elementarily Utopian, and since we are free of the trammels of convincing story-telling, we may suppose that language to be sufficiently our own to understand. Indeed, should we be in Utopia at all, if we could not talk to everyone? That accursed bar of language, that hostile inscription in the foreigner's eyes, “deaf and dumb to you, sir, and so—your enemy,” is the very first of the defects and complications one has fled the earth to escape.

We shouldn't think there are any language barriers to communication. The whole world will definitely have a common language, which is quite idealistic, and since we’re not held back by the need for convincing storytelling, we can assume that language is familiar enough for us to understand. In fact, would we even be in a Utopia if we couldn’t talk to everyone? That frustrating barrier of language, that unfriendly look in a foreigner’s eyes saying “I can’t understand you, so I’m your enemy,” is the very first issue one tries to escape from by leaving the earth.

But what sort of language would we have the world speak, if we were told the miracle of Babel was presently to be reversed?

But what kind of language would we make the world speak if we were told that the miracle of Babel was about to be undone?

If I may take a daring image, a mediæval liberty, I would suppose that in this lonely place the Spirit of Creation spoke to us on this matter. “You are wise men,” that Spirit might say—and I, being a suspicious, touchy, over-earnest man for all my predisposition to plumpness, would instantly scent the irony (while my companion, I fancy, might even plume himself), “and to beget your wisdom is chiefly why the world was made. You are so good as to propose an acceleration of that tedious multitudinous evolution upon which I am engaged. I gather, a universal tongue would serve you there. While I sit here among these mountains—I have been filing away at them for this last aeon or so, just to attract your hotels, you know—will you be so kind―? A few hints―?”

If I can use a bold image, a medieval concept of freedom, I would guess that in this quiet place, the Spirit of Creation is talking to us about this. “You are wise people,” that Spirit might say—and I, being a suspicious, sensitive, overly serious person despite my tendency to be overweight, would immediately pick up on the sarcasm (while my friend, I imagine, might even take it as a compliment), “and creating your wisdom is mostly why the world was made. You kindly suggest speeding up that slow, complex evolution I'm involved in. I assume a universal language would help you with that. While I sit here among these mountains—I’ve been working on them for ages, just to attract your hotels, you know—could you be so kind? A few tips, perhaps?”

Then the Spirit of Creation might transiently smile, a smile that would be like the passing of a cloud. All the mountain wilderness about us would be radiantly lit. (You know those swift moments, when warmth and brightness drift by, in lonely and desolate places.)

Then the Spirit of Creation might briefly smile, a smile that would be as fleeting as a passing cloud. All the mountain wilderness around us would be brilliantly illuminated. (You know those quick moments when warmth and light come and go in lonely, desolate places.)

Yet, after all, why should two men be smiled into apathy by the Infinite? Here we are, with our knobby little heads, our eyes and hands and feet and stout hearts, and if not us or ours, still the endless multitudes about us and in our loins are to come at last to the World State and a greater fellowship and the universal tongue. Let us to the extent of our ability, if not answer that question, at any rate try to think ourselves within sight of the best thing possible. That, after all, is our purpose, to imagine our best and strive for it, and it is a worse folly and a worse sin than presumption, to abandon striving because the best of all our bests looks mean amidst the suns.

Yet, after all, why should two men be pushed into indifference by the Infinite? Here we are, with our oddly shaped heads, our eyes and hands and feet and strong hearts, and if not us or our kind, still the countless multitudes around us and within us are destined to reach the World State and a greater sense of community and a universal language. Let us, as much as we can, if not answer that question, at least try to envision ourselves within reach of the best possible outcome. That, after all, is our goal: to imagine our best and strive for it, and it’s a greater foolishness and a greater sin than arrogance to give up striving just because the best of our aspirations seems insignificant compared to the vastness of the universe.

Now you as a botanist would, I suppose, incline to something as they say, “scientific.” You wince under that most offensive epithet—and I am able to give you my intelligent sympathy—though “pseudo-scientific” and “quasi-scientific” are worse by far for the skin. You would begin to talk of scientific languages, of Esperanto, La Langue Bleue, New Latin, Volapuk, and Lord Lytton, of the philosophical language of Archbishop Whateley, Lady Welby's work upon Significs and the like. You would tell me of the remarkable precisions, the encyclopædic quality of chemical terminology, and at the word terminology I should insinuate a comment on that eminent American biologist, Professor Mark Baldwin, who has carried the language biological to such heights of expressive clearness as to be triumphantly and invincibly unreadable. (Which foreshadows the line of my defence.)

Now as a botanist, I guess you would lean toward something that’s considered “scientific.” You might cringe at that really annoying term—and I totally understand your frustration—though “pseudo-scientific” and “quasi-scientific” are even worse for the nerves. You’d probably start talking about scientific languages, like Esperanto, La Langue Bleue, New Latin, Volapük, and Lord Lytton, as well as the philosophical language of Archbishop Whateley and Lady Welby's work on Significs. You would mention the impressive precision and encyclopedic nature of chemical terminology, and when you say terminology, I would sneak in a comment about that famous American biologist, Professor Mark Baldwin, who has taken biological language to such extreme levels of clarity that it’s ultimately and unavoidably unreadable. (Which leads into my line of defense.)

You make your ideal clear, a scientific language you demand, without ambiguity, as precise as mathematical formulæ, and with every term in relations of exact logical consistency with every other. It will be a language with all the inflexions of verbs and nouns regular and all its constructions inevitable, each word clearly distinguishable from every other word in sound as well as spelling.

You clarify your ideal: a scientific language that you require, free of ambiguity, as precise as mathematical formulas, with every term logically consistent with one another. It will be a language where all verb and noun forms are regular and all constructions are inevitable, with each word clearly distinguishable from every other in both sound and spelling.

That, at any rate, is the sort of thing one hears demanded, and if only because the demand rests upon implications that reach far beyond the region of language, it is worth considering here. It implies, indeed, almost everything that we are endeavouring to repudiate in this particular work. It implies that the whole intellectual basis of mankind is established, that the rules of logic, the systems of counting and measurement, the general categories and schemes of resemblance and difference, are established for the human mind for ever—blank Comte-ism, in fact, of the blankest description. But, indeed, the science of logic and the whole framework of philosophical thought men have kept since the days of Plato and Aristotle, has no more essential permanence as a final expression of the human mind, than the Scottish Longer Catechism. Amidst the welter of modern thought, a philosophy long lost to men rises again into being, like some blind and almost formless embryo, that must presently develop sight, and form, and power, a philosophy in which this assumption is denied. [Footnote: The serious reader may refer at leisure to Sidgwick's Use of Words in Reasoning (particularly), and to Bosanquet's Essentials of Logic, Bradley's Principles of Logic, and Sigwart's Logik; the lighter minded may read and mark the temper of Professor Case in the British Encyclopædia, article Logic (Vol. XXX.). I have appended to his book a rude sketch of a philosophy upon new lines, originally read by me to the Oxford Phil. Soc. in 1903.]

That, at least, is the kind of demand you often hear, and because this demand carries implications that go far beyond just language, it's worth discussing here. It suggests, in fact, almost everything we’re trying to reject in this work. It assumes that the entire intellectual foundation of humanity is set in stone, that the rules of logic, the systems of counting and measurement, and the general categories and frameworks for similarities and differences are permanently established for the human mind—essentially, a very simplistic form of Comte-ism. However, the science of logic and the entire structure of philosophical thought that has been maintained since the days of Plato and Aristotle has no more lasting significance as the ultimate expression of the human mind than the Scottish Longer Catechism. In the turmoil of modern thought, a philosophy that had long been forgotten is re-emerging, like a blind and almost formless embryo, poised to develop sight, form, and strength—a philosophy that denies this assumption. [Footnote: The serious reader may refer at leisure to Sidgwick's Use of Words in Reasoning (particularly), and to Bosanquet's Essentials of Logic, Bradley's Principles of Logic, and Sigwart's Logik; the lighter-minded may read and note the perspective of Professor Case in the British Encyclopædia, article Logic (Vol. XXX.). I have appended to his book a rough outline of a philosophy along new lines, which I originally presented to the Oxford Phil. Soc. in 1903.]

All through this Utopian excursion, I must warn you, you shall feel the thrust and disturbance of that insurgent movement. In the reiterated use of “Unique,” you will, as it were, get the gleam of its integument; in the insistence upon individuality, and the individual difference as the significance of life, you will feel the texture of its shaping body. Nothing endures, nothing is precise and certain (except the mind of a pedant), perfection is the mere repudiation of that ineluctable marginal inexactitude which is the mysterious inmost quality of Being. Being, indeed!—there is no being, but a universal becoming of individualities, and Plato turned his back on truth when he turned towards his museum of specific ideals. Heraclitus, that lost and misinterpreted giant, may perhaps be coming to his own....

All throughout this Utopian journey, I must warn you, you will feel the push and chaos of that rebellious movement. In the repeated use of “Unique,” you will, in a way, see the surface of it; in the emphasis on individuality and the unique differences as the meaning of life, you will sense the substance of its shaping form. Nothing lasts, nothing is exact and certain (except the mind of a know-it-all), perfection is simply a rejection of that unavoidable slight inaccuracy that is the mysterious core of Being. Being, indeed!—there is no being, only a universal process of becoming unique individuals, and Plato lost sight of truth when he leaned toward his collection of specific ideals. Heraclitus, that overlooked and misunderstood giant, may finally be getting his due...

There is no abiding thing in what we know. We change from weaker to stronger lights, and each more powerful light pierces our hitherto opaque foundations and reveals fresh and different opacities below. We can never foretell which of our seemingly assured fundamentals the next change will not affect. What folly, then, to dream of mapping out our minds in however general terms, of providing for the endless mysteries of the future a terminology and an idiom! We follow the vein, we mine and accumulate our treasure, but who can tell which way the vein may trend? Language is the nourishment of the thought of man, that serves only as it undergoes metabolism, and becomes thought and lives, and in its very living passes away. You scientific people, with your fancy of a terrible exactitude in language, of indestructible foundations built, as that Wordsworthian doggerel on the title-page of Nature says, “for aye,” are marvellously without imagination!

Nothing we know is permanent. We shift from weaker to brighter understandings, and each new insight breaks through our previously unclear foundations, uncovering new and different uncertainties beneath. We can never predict which of our seemingly solid beliefs will be unaffected by the next change. How foolish it is to think we can map out our thoughts in broad terms or create a language for the endless mysteries of the future! We pursue our ideas, mine them, and accumulate our insights, but who can say where our understanding will lead next? Language is the fuel for human thought; it only matters when it undergoes transformation, becoming actual thoughts that live and, in that very life, fade away. You scientists, with your obsession for precise language and the idea of building unchangeable foundations, as that Wordsworthian verse on the cover of Nature suggests, “forever,” are remarkably lacking in imagination!

The language of Utopia will no doubt be one and indivisible; all mankind will, in the measure of their individual differences in quality, be brought into the same phase, into a common resonance of thought, but the language they will speak will still be a living tongue, an animated system of imperfections, which every individual man will infinitesimally modify. Through the universal freedom of exchange and movement, the developing change in its general spirit will be a world-wide change; that is the quality of its universality. I fancy it will be a coalesced language, a synthesis of many. Such a language as English is a coalesced language; it is a coalescence of Anglo-Saxon and Norman French and Scholar's Latin, welded into one speech more ample and more powerful and beautiful than either. The Utopian tongue might well present a more spacious coalescence, and hold in the frame of such an uninflected or slightly inflected idiom as English already presents, a profuse vocabulary into which have been cast a dozen once separate tongues, superposed and then welded together through bilingual and trilingual compromises. [Footnote: Vide an excellent article, La Langue Française en l'an 2003, par Leon Bollack, in La Revue, 15 Juillet, 1903.] In the past ingenious men have speculated on the inquiry, “Which language will survive?” The question was badly put. I think now that this wedding and survival of several in a common offspring is a far more probable thing.

The language of Utopia will definitely be unified; all people will, to the extent of their individual differences, come together in a shared understanding, resonating in thought, but the language they speak will still be a living tongue, a dynamic system of imperfections that every person will slightly modify. Through the universal freedom of exchange and movement, the evolving change in its overall spirit will be a global change; that’s the essence of its universality. I imagine it will be a blended language, a synthesis of many. A language like English is a blended language; it combines Anglo-Saxon, Norman French, and Scholars’ Latin into one speech that is richer, more powerful, and more beautiful than any of its components. The Utopian language could very well be an even broader blend, containing, within the structure of a mostly uninflected or slightly inflected form like English already has, a vast vocabulary that incorporates elements from a dozen once separate languages, layered and then fused together through bilingual and trilingual compromises. [Footnote: Vide an excellent article, La Langue Française en l'an 2003, by Leon Bollack, in La Revue, July 15, 1903.] In the past, clever people have speculated on the question, “Which language will survive?” That question was poorly phrased. I now believe that the merging and survival of several languages into a common one is a much more likely scenario.

§ 6

This talk of languages, however, is a digression. We were on our way along the faint path that runs round the rim of the Lake of Lucendro, and we were just upon the point of coming upon our first Utopian man. He was, I said, no Swiss. Yet he would have been a Swiss on mother Earth, and here he would have the same face, with some difference, maybe, in the expression; the same physique, though a little better developed, perhaps—the same complexion. He would have different habits, different traditions, different knowledge, different ideas, different clothing, and different appliances, but, except for all that, he would be the same man. We very distinctly provided at the outset that the modern Utopia must have people inherently the same as those in the world.

This discussion about languages is a bit off-topic. We were walking along the narrow path that circles the Lake of Lucendro, and we were just about to encounter our first Utopian person. I mentioned that he wasn’t Swiss. However, he would have been Swiss on Earth, and here he would have the same face, maybe with a slightly different expression; the same build, though perhaps a bit more developed; the same skin tone. He would have different habits, traditions, knowledge, ideas, clothing, and tools, but apart from all that, he would be the same person. We clearly stated at the beginning that the modern Utopia must include people who are inherently the same as those in the real world.

There is more, perhaps, in that than appears at the first suggestion.

There might be more to it than what it seems at first glance.

That proposition gives one characteristic difference between a modern Utopia and almost all its predecessors. It is to be a world Utopia, we have agreed, no less; and so we must needs face the fact that we are to have differences of race. Even the lower class of Plato's Republic was not specifically of different race. But this is a Utopia as wide as Christian charity, and white and black, brown, red and yellow, all tints of skin, all types of body and character, will be there. How we are to adjust their differences is a master question, and the matter is not even to be opened in this chapter. It will need a whole chapter even to glance at its issues. But here we underline that stipulation; every race of this planet earth is to be found in the strictest parallelism there, in numbers the same—only, as I say, with an entirely different set of traditions, ideals, ideas, and purposes, and so moving under those different skies to an altogether different destiny.

That idea highlights a key difference between a modern Utopia and almost all earlier versions. We've agreed it should be a world Utopia, so we need to acknowledge that there will be racial differences. Even the lower class in Plato's Republic wasn’t defined by different races. But this will be a Utopia as inclusive as Christian charity, where people of all skin colors—white, black, brown, red, and yellow—represent all variations of skin tone, body types, and personalities. How we manage these differences is a crucial question, and we won’t even touch on it in this chapter. It will require an entire chapter just to address some of the issues. For now, we emphasize that every race on this planet will exist in equal measure there, except that, as I mentioned, they will carry a completely different set of traditions, ideals, beliefs, and goals, and will thus navigate under those varying influences towards entirely different destinies.

There follows a curious development of this to anyone clearly impressed by the uniqueness and the unique significance of individualities. Races are no hard and fast things, no crowd of identically similar persons, but massed sub-races, and tribes and families, each after its kind unique, and these again are clusterings of still smaller uniques and so down to each several person. So that our first convention works out to this, that not only is every earthly mountain, river, plant, and beast in that parallel planet beyond Sirius also, but every man, woman, and child alive has a Utopian parallel. From now onward, of course, the fates of these two planets will diverge, men will die here whom wisdom will save there, and perhaps conversely here we shall save men; children will be born to them and not to us, to us and not to them, but this, this moment of reading, is the starting moment, and for the first and last occasion the populations of our planets are abreast.

There’s an interesting development for anyone who clearly understands the uniqueness and significance of individual identities. Races aren’t rigid categories, nor are they just a crowd of identical people; rather, they consist of mixed sub-races, tribes, and families, each unique in their own way, and these are also made up of even smaller unique individuals, down to each single person. So, our first conclusion is this: not only does every mountain, river, plant, and animal on that parallel planet beyond Sirius exist, but also every man, woman, and child alive has a Utopian counterpart. From this point on, of course, the fates of these two planets will diverge. People will die here who would be saved there by wisdom, and perhaps the opposite will happen as well; children will be born to them and not to us, and to us and not to them. But this moment of reading is the starting point, and for the first and last time, the populations of our planets are in sync.

We must in these days make some such supposition. The alternative is a Utopia of dolls in the likeness of angels—imaginary laws to fit incredible people, an unattractive undertaking.

We need to make some kind of assumption these days. The only other option is a Utopia filled with dolls that look like angels—made-up rules for unbelievable people, which is not appealing at all.

For example, we must assume there is a man such as I might have been, better informed, better disciplined, better employed, thinner and more active—and I wonder what he is doing!—and you, Sir or Madam, are in duplicate also, and all the men and women that you know and I. I doubt if we shall meet our doubles, or if it would be pleasant for us to do so; but as we come down from these lonely mountains to the roads and houses and living places of the Utopian world-state, we shall certainly find, here and there, faces that will remind us singularly of those who have lived under our eyes.

For example, we have to imagine a person who could have been me—more knowledgeable, more disciplined, better situated, leaner, and more energetic—and I can’t help but wonder what he's up to! And you, Sir or Madam, have your own double, as do all the men and women you know and I. I doubt we'll ever meet our doppelgängers, or if it would even be enjoyable; but as we descend from these quiet mountains into the roads, houses, and communities of this Utopian world-state, we will certainly come across, here and there, faces that strikingly remind us of those we've known.

There are some you never wish to meet again, you say, and some, I gather, you do. “And One―!”

There are some people you never want to see again, you say, and some, I guess, you do. “And One―!”

It is strange, but this figure of the botanist will not keep in place. It sprang up between us, dear reader, as a passing illustrative invention. I do not know what put him into my head, and for the moment, it fell in with my humour for a space to foist the man's personality upon you as yours and call you scientific—that most abusive word. But here he is, indisputably, with me in Utopia, and lapsing from our high speculative theme into halting but intimate confidences. He declares he has not come to Utopia to meet again with his sorrows.

It's odd, but this image of the botanist just won't stay put. It popped up between us, dear reader, as a passing idea. I’m not sure what made me think of him, and for a moment, it amused me to project his personality onto you and label you as scientific—that term that can be so misused. But there he is, undeniably, with me in Utopia, shifting from our lofty discussions to awkward but personal confessions. He says he hasn't come to Utopia to confront his sorrows again.

What sorrows?

What sorrows are those?

I protest, even warmly, that neither he nor his sorrows were in my intention.

I sincerely protest that I had no intention of involving him or his troubles.

He is a man, I should think, of thirty-nine, a man whose life has been neither tragedy nor a joyous adventure, a man with one of those faces that have gained interest rather than force or nobility from their commerce with life. He is something refined, with some knowledge, perhaps, of the minor pains and all the civil self-controls; he has read more than he has suffered, and suffered rather than done. He regards me with his blue-grey eye, from which all interest in this Utopia has faded.

He seems to be about thirty-nine, a guy whose life has been neither tragic nor a thrilling adventure, a man with one of those faces that reflect experience more than strength or nobility. He’s somewhat refined, possibly knowledgeable about the little pains of life and the importance of self-control; he has read more than he has experienced, and endured more than he has acted. He looks at me with his blue-grey eye, from which all interest in this Utopia has faded.

“It is a trouble,” he says, “that has come into my life only for a month or so—at least acutely again. I thought it was all over. There was someone―”

“It’s a hassle,” he says, “that’s only been in my life for about a month—at least it’s come back strongly. I thought it was all behind me. There was someone—”

It is an amazing story to hear upon a mountain crest in Utopia, this Hampstead affair, this story of a Frognal heart. “Frognal,” he says, is the place where they met, and it summons to my memory the word on a board at the corner of a flint-dressed new road, an estate development road, with a vista of villas up a hill. He had known her before he got his professorship, and neither her “people” nor his—he speaks that detestable middle-class dialect in which aunts and things with money and the right of intervention are called “people”!—approved of the affair. “She was, I think, rather easily swayed,” he says. “But that's not fair to her, perhaps. She thought too much of others. If they seemed distressed, or if they seemed to think a course right―” ...

It’s an incredible story to hear on a mountain peak in Utopia, this Hampstead situation, this story of a Frognal heart. “Frognal,” he says, is where they met, and it brings to mind the sign on a board at the corner of a newly paved road, an estate development road, with a view of villas up a hill. He had known her before he got his professorship, and neither her “people” nor his—he uses that annoying middle-class slang where aunts and wealthy relatives with a say are referred to as “people”!—approved of the relationship. “She was, I think, rather easily influenced,” he says. “But that’s not fair to her, perhaps. She cared too much about others. If they seemed upset, or if they seemed to believe a certain path was right―” ...

Have I come to Utopia to hear this sort of thing?

Have I come to Utopia to listen to this kind of stuff?

§ 7

It is necessary to turn the botanist's thoughts into a worthier channel. It is necessary to override these modest regrets, this intrusive, petty love story. Does he realise this is indeed Utopia? Turn your mind, I insist, to this Utopia of mine, and leave these earthly troubles to their proper planet. Do you realise just where the propositions necessary to a modern Utopia are taking us? Everyone on earth will have to be here;—themselves, but with a difference. Somewhere here in this world is, for example, Mr. Chamberlain, and the King is here (no doubt incognito), and all the Royal Academy, and Sandow, and Mr. Arnold White.

It's important to redirect the botanist's thoughts into something more meaningful. We need to get past these petty regrets and this distracting little love story. Does he understand that this is truly Utopia? Focus your mind, I insist, on my vision of Utopia, and leave these worldly troubles behind. Do you see where the ideas needed for a modern Utopia are leading us? Everyone on earth will need to be here—still themselves, but changed in some way. Somewhere in this world is, for instance, Mr. Chamberlain, and the King is here (likely incognito), along with all the members of the Royal Academy, Sandow, and Mr. Arnold White.

But these famous names do not appeal to him.

But these famous names don't interest him.

My mind goes from this prominent and typical personage to that, and for a time I forget my companion. I am distracted by the curious side issues this general proposition trails after it. There will be so-and-so, and so-and-so. The name and figure of Mr. Roosevelt jerks into focus, and obliterates an attempt to acclimatise the Emperor of the Germans. What, for instance, will Utopia do with Mr. Roosevelt? There drifts across my inner vision the image of a strenuous struggle with Utopian constables, the voice that has thrilled terrestrial millions in eloquent protest. The writ of arrest, drifting loose in the conflict, comes to my feet; I impale the scrap of paper, and read—but can it be?—“attempted disorganisation?... incitements to disarrange?... the balance of population?”

My thoughts shift from one well-known figure to another, and for a moment I forget my companion. I'm distracted by the interesting side issues that this broad idea brings up. There will be this person, and that person. The name and image of Mr. Roosevelt suddenly come to mind, pushing aside any thoughts about the Emperor of Germany. For example, what will Utopia do with Mr. Roosevelt? I imagine a fierce struggle with Utopian police, and I hear that voice that has inspired millions on Earth with its powerful protests. A loose arrest warrant floats through the chaos, landing at my feet; I grab the piece of paper and read—but could it really be?—“attempted disorganization?... incitements to disrupt?... the balance of population?”

The trend of my logic for once has led us into a facetious alley. One might indeed keep in this key, and write an agreeable little Utopia, that like the holy families of the mediæval artists (or Michael Angelo's Last Judgement) should compliment one's friends in various degrees. Or one might embark upon a speculative treatment of the entire Almanach de Gotha, something on the lines of Epistemon's vision of the damned great, when

The trend of my reasoning has, for a change, taken us down a humorous path. One could certainly stay in this tone and create a charming little Utopia, much like the holy families of medieval artists (or Michelangelo's Last Judgment), that would flatter friends in different ways. Alternatively, one could take a thoughtful approach to the whole Almanach de Gotha, similar to Epistemon's vision of the damned elite, when

“Xerxes was a crier of mustard.
Romulus was a salter and a patcher of patterns....”
“Xerxes was a mustard vendor.
Romulus was a salt merchant and a mender of patterns....”

That incomparable catalogue! That incomparable catalogue! Inspired by the Muse of Parody, we might go on to the pages of “Who's Who,” and even, with an eye to the obdurate republic, to “Who's Who in America,” and make the most delightful and extensive arrangements. Now where shall we put this most excellent man? And this?...

That amazing catalog! That amazing catalog! Inspired by the Muse of Parody, we could dive into the pages of "Who's Who" and even, keeping in mind the stubborn republic, "Who's Who in America," and create the most delightful and comprehensive arrangements. Now, where should we place this outstanding person? And this?...

But, indeed, it is doubtful if we shall meet any of these doubles during our Utopian journey, or know them when we meet them. I doubt if anyone will be making the best of both these worlds. The great men in this still unexplored Utopia may be but village Hampdens in our own, and earthly goatherds and obscure illiterates sit here in the seats of the mighty.

But honestly, it's uncertain whether we'll encounter any of these doubles on our ideal journey, or recognize them when we do. I doubt anyone will truly make the most of both worlds. The great figures in this still uncharted Utopia might just be local heroes in our world, while ordinary goatherds and unknown illiterates hold positions of power here.

That again opens agreeable vistas left of us and right.

That opens up pleasant views to our left and right again.

But my botanist obtrudes his personality again. His thoughts have travelled by a different route.

But my botanist pushes his personality into the conversation again. His thoughts have taken a different direction.

“I know,” he says, “that she will be happier here, and that they will value her better than she has been valued upon earth.”

“I know,” he says, “that she will be happier here, and that they will appreciate her more than she has been appreciated on earth.”

His interruption serves to turn me back from my momentary contemplation of those popular effigies inflated by old newspapers and windy report, the earthly great. He sets me thinking of more personal and intimate applications, of the human beings one knows with a certain approximation to real knowledge, of the actual common substance of life. He turns me to the thought of rivalries and tendernesses, of differences and disappointments. I am suddenly brought painfully against the things that might have been. What if instead of that Utopia of vacant ovals we meet relinquished loves here, and opportunities lost and faces as they might have looked to us?

His interruption pulls me away from my brief contemplation of those popular figures blown up by old newspapers and exaggerated stories, the people who are celebrated. He makes me think about more personal and intimate connections, the people you know with a genuine understanding of who they are, the real essence of life. He shifts my focus to rivalries and affections, to differences and letdowns. I'm suddenly confronted with the things that could have been. What if instead of that ideal world of empty shapes we encounter forsaken loves here, and missed chances and faces as they could have appeared to us?

I turn to my botanist almost reprovingly. “You know, she won't be quite the same lady here that you knew in Frognal,” I say, and wrest myself from a subject that is no longer agreeable by rising to my feet.

I look at my botanist with a hint of reproach. “You know, she won't be the same person here that you knew in Frognal,” I say, shifting away from a topic that's no longer pleasant by getting to my feet.

“And besides,” I say, standing above him, “the chances against our meeting her are a million to one.... And we loiter! This is not the business we have come upon, but a mere incidental kink in our larger plan. The fact remains, these people we have come to see are people with like infirmities to our own—and only the conditions are changed. Let us pursue the tenour of our inquiry.”

"And besides," I say, standing over him, "the odds of us running into her are a million to one... And we're just hanging around! This isn't what we came here for; it's just a random detour in our bigger plan. The truth is, these people we're here to see have similar issues as us—it's just the circumstances that are different. Let's stick to the purpose of our investigation."

With that I lead the way round the edge of the Lake of Lucendro towards our Utopian world.

With that, I led the way around the edge of Lake Lucendro toward our utopian world.

(You figure him doing it.)

(You imagine him doing it.)

Down the mountain we shall go and down the passes, and as the valleys open the world will open, Utopia, where men and women are happy and laws are wise, and where all that is tangled and confused in human affairs has been unravelled and made right.

Down the mountain we will go and down the passes, and as the valleys open up, the world will open up—Utopia, where men and women are happy, laws are wise, and where everything that is tangled and confused in human affairs has been resolved and made right.

CHAPTER THE SECOND
Concerning Freedoms

§ 1

Now what sort of question would first occur to two men descending upon the planet of a Modern Utopia? Probably grave solicitude about their personal freedom. Towards the Stranger, as I have already remarked, the Utopias of the past displayed their least amiable aspect. Would this new sort of Utopian State, spread to the dimensions of a world, be any less forbidding?

Now, what kind of question would first come to mind for two guys landing on a Modern Utopia? Most likely deep concern about their personal freedom. As I mentioned earlier, the Utopias of the past showed their least friendly side towards outsiders. Would this new kind of Utopian State, expanded to the size of a world, be any less intimidating?

We should take comfort in the thought that universal Toleration is certainly a modern idea, and it is upon modern ideas that this World State rests. But even suppose we are tolerated and admitted to this unavoidable citizenship, there will still remain a wide range of possibility.... I think we should try to work the problem out from an inquiry into first principles, and that we should follow the trend of our time and kind by taking up the question as one of “Man versus the State,” and discussing the compromise of Liberty.

We should find comfort in the idea that universal tolerance is definitely a modern concept, and it's on modern ideas that this World State is built. But even if we are tolerated and accepted into this inevitable citizenship, there will still be a lot of possibilities left... I believe we should tackle the problem by looking into the fundamental principles and that we should align with the direction of our time by framing the question as one of “Man versus the State,” and discussing the balance of liberty.

The idea of individual liberty is one that has grown in importance and grows with every development of modern thought. To the classical Utopists freedom was relatively trivial. Clearly they considered virtue and happiness as entirely separable from liberty, and as being altogether more important things. But the modern view, with its deepening insistence upon individuality and upon the significance of its uniqueness, steadily intensifies the value of freedom, until at last we begin to see liberty as the very substance of life, that indeed it is life, and that only the dead things, the choiceless things, live in absolute obedience to law. To have free play for one's individuality is, in the modern view, the subjective triumph of existence, as survival in creative work and offspring is its objective triumph. But for all men, since man is a social creature, the play of will must fall short of absolute freedom. Perfect human liberty is possible only to a despot who is absolutely and universally obeyed. Then to will would be to command and achieve, and within the limits of natural law we could at any moment do exactly as it pleased us to do. All other liberty is a compromise between our own freedom of will and the wills of those with whom we come in contact. In an organised state each one of us has a more or less elaborate code of what he may do to others and to himself, and what others may do to him. He limits others by his rights, and is limited by the rights of others, and by considerations affecting the welfare of the community as a whole.

The concept of individual freedom has become increasingly important and continues to gain significance with each advancement in modern thought. For the classical Utopists, freedom was somewhat insignificant. They clearly viewed virtue and happiness as completely separate from liberty, and they regarded those as far more important. In contrast, the modern perspective, with its growing emphasis on individuality and the importance of its uniqueness, steadily elevates the value of freedom. Eventually, we begin to perceive liberty as the very essence of life; in fact, it is life, and only the lifeless things—those without choice—fully obey the law. In today's view, allowing space for one’s individuality represents the subjective achievement of existence, while survival through creative work and offspring is its objective success. However, since humans are social beings, the expression of will cannot reach absolute freedom. Perfect human liberty is only achievable by a despot who is completely and universally obeyed. In that case, to will would mean to command and accomplish, and within the bounds of natural law, we could at any moment act exactly as we wished. All other forms of liberty are compromises between our own freedom of will and the wills of those we interact with. In an organized society, each person has a more or less detailed system of rules regarding what they can do to others and themselves, and what others can do to them. They limit others by their rights and are constrained by the rights of others and by considerations that affect the well-being of the community as a whole.

Individual liberty in a community is not, as mathematicians would say, always of the same sign. To ignore this is the essential fallacy of the cult called Individualism. But in truth, a general prohibition in a state may increase the sum of liberty, and a general permission may diminish it. It does not follow, as these people would have us believe, that a man is more free where there is least law and more restricted where there is most law. A socialism or a communism is not necessarily a slavery, and there is no freedom under Anarchy. Consider how much liberty we gain by the loss of the common liberty to kill. Thereby one may go to and fro in all the ordered parts of the earth, unencumbered by arms or armour, free of the fear of playful poison, whimsical barbers, or hotel trap-doors. Indeed, it means freedom from a thousand fears and precautions. Suppose there existed even the limited freedom to kill in vendetta, and think what would happen in our suburbs. Consider the inconvenience of two households in a modern suburb estranged and provided with modern weapons of precision, the inconvenience not only to each other, but to the neutral pedestrian, the practical loss of freedoms all about them. The butcher, if he came at all, would have to come round in an armoured cart....

Individual freedom in a community isn’t always straightforward, as mathematicians might put it. Ignoring this is the key mistake made by the group known as Individualism. In reality, a broad prohibition in a state can enhance overall liberty, while a broad permission can reduce it. It doesn't necessarily mean, as these individuals would claim, that a person is freer where there are fewer laws and more restricted where there are many laws. Socialism or communism isn’t automatically slavery, and there’s no freedom under Anarchy. Think about how much liberty we gain when we lose the common right to kill. This way, one can move freely throughout all structured areas of the world, unburdened by weapons or armor, safe from playful poison, quirky barbers, or hotel trapdoors. In fact, it means freedom from countless fears and precautions. Imagine if there were even a limited freedom to kill for revenge; just think about the chaos in our neighborhoods. Picture two households in a modern suburb at odds with each other, armed with modern precision weapons, and consider the trouble not only for themselves but for the innocent bystanders, leading to a practical loss of freedoms for everyone around them. The butcher, if he decided to show up, would have to come in an armored vehicle....

It follows, therefore, in a modern Utopia, which finds the final hope of the world in the evolving interplay of unique individualities, that the State will have effectually chipped away just all those spendthrift liberties that waste liberty, and not one liberty more, and so have attained the maximum general freedom.

It follows, then, in a modern Utopia that sees the ultimate hope for the world in the dynamic interaction of diverse individualities, that the State will have effectively reduced all those excessive freedoms that squander liberty, and not a single freedom more, thereby achieving the greatest overall freedom.

There are two distinct and contrasting methods of limiting liberty; the first is Prohibition, “thou shalt not,” and the second Command, “thou shalt.” There is, however, a sort of prohibition that takes the form of a conditional command, and this one needs to bear in mind. It says if you do so-and-so, you must also do so-and-so; if, for example, you go to sea with men you employ, you must go in a seaworthy vessel. But the pure command is unconditional; it says, whatever you have done or are doing or want to do, you are to do this, as when the social system, working through the base necessities of base parents and bad laws, sends a child of thirteen into a factory. Prohibition takes one definite thing from the indefinite liberty of a man, but it still leaves him an unbounded choice of actions. He remains free, and you have merely taken a bucketful from the sea of his freedom. But compulsion destroys freedom altogether. In this Utopia of ours there may be many prohibitions, but no indirect compulsions—if one may so contrive it—and few or no commands. As far as I see it now, in this present discussion, I think, indeed, there should be no positive compulsions at all in Utopia, at any rate for the adult Utopian—unless they fall upon him as penalties incurred.

There are two clear and opposing ways to limit freedom; the first is Prohibition, “you must not,” and the second is Command, “you must.” However, there's a type of prohibition that takes the form of a conditional command, and this is important to consider. It states that if you do one thing, you also have to do another; for example, if you go to sea with people you hire, you have to go in a seaworthy vessel. But a pure command is unconditional; it tells you that no matter what you've done, are doing, or want to do, you must do this, like when the social system, influenced by the basic needs of poor parents and bad laws, sends a thirteen-year-old child into a factory. Prohibition removes one specific thing from a person's overall freedom, but it still allows for a wide range of choices. The person remains free, and you've only taken a small part of their freedom. But compulsion takes away freedom entirely. In our Utopia, there can be many prohibitions, but no indirect compulsions—if we can manage it—and few or no commands. From what I see in this current discussion, I believe there shouldn’t be any positive compulsions at all in Utopia, at least for adult Utopians—unless they are penalties for actions taken.

§ 2

What prohibitions should we be under, we two Uitlanders in this Utopian world? We should certainly not be free to kill, assault, or threaten anyone we met, and in that we earth-trained men would not be likely to offend. And until we knew more exactly the Utopian idea of property we should be very chary of touching anything that might conceivably be appropriated. If it was not the property of individuals it might be the property of the State. But beyond that we might have our doubts. Are we right in wearing the strange costumes we do, in choosing the path that pleases us athwart this rock and turf, in coming striding with unfumigated rücksacks and snow-wet hobnails into what is conceivably an extremely neat and orderly world? We have passed our first Utopian now, with an answered vague gesture, and have noted, with secret satisfaction, there is no access of dismay; we have rounded a bend, and down the valley in the distance we get a glimpse of what appears to be a singularly well-kept road....

What rules should we, two outsiders, follow in this ideal world? We definitely shouldn't be allowed to kill, attack, or threaten anyone we come across, and as men used to life on Earth, we probably wouldn't do that anyway. Until we understand the Utopian concept of property better, we should be careful not to touch anything that might belong to someone else. If it doesn't belong to individuals, it could belong to the State. But beyond that, we might have our concerns. Are we right to wear these strange outfits, to choose the paths we like across this rocky ground, to walk boldly with our unwashed backpacks and wet boots into what seems like a very tidy and organized world? We've encountered our first Utopian resident, who gave us a vague gesture in response, and we noted, with a bit of satisfaction, that there was no visible alarm; we've turned a corner, and down the valley ahead, we see what looks like a particularly well-maintained road...

I submit that to the modern minded man it can be no sort of Utopia worth desiring that does not give the utmost freedom of going to and fro. Free movement is to many people one of the greatest of life's privileges—to go wherever the spirit moves them, to wander and see—and though they have every comfort, every security, every virtuous discipline, they will still be unhappy if that is denied them. Short of damage to things cherished and made, the Utopians will surely have this right, so we may expect no unclimbable walls and fences, nor the discovery of any laws we may transgress in coming down these mountain places.

I argue that for the modern-minded person, there’s no Utopia worth wanting that doesn’t allow complete freedom to move around. For many, the ability to travel freely is one of life’s greatest privileges—to go wherever they feel like, to explore and discover. Even if they have all the comforts, security, and good values in the world, they’ll still feel unhappy if that freedom is taken away. As long as cherished things aren’t harmed, those in Utopia will definitely have this right, so we shouldn’t expect to see any insurmountable walls or fences, nor any laws we might break while coming down from these mountain areas.

And yet, just as civil liberty itself is a compromise defended by prohibitions, so this particular sort of liberty must also have its qualifications. Carried to the absolute pitch the right of free movement ceases to be distinguishable from the right of free intrusion. We have already, in a comment on More's Utopia, hinted at an agreement with Aristotle's argument against communism, that it flings people into an intolerable continuity of contact. Schopenhauer carried out Aristotle in the vein of his own bitterness and with the truest of images when he likened human society to hedgehogs clustering for warmth, and unhappy when either too closely packed or too widely separated. Empedocles found no significance in life whatever except as an unsteady play of love and hate, of attraction and repulsion, of assimilation and the assertion of difference. So long as we ignore difference, so long as we ignore individuality, and that I hold has been the common sin of all Utopias hitherto, we can make absolute statements, prescribe communisms or individualisms, and all sorts of hard theoretic arrangements. But in the world of reality, which—to modernise Heraclitus and Empedocles—is nothing more nor less than the world of individuality, there are no absolute rights and wrongs, there are no qualitative questions at all, but only quantitative adjustments. Equally strong in the normal civilised man is the desire for freedom of movement and the desire for a certain privacy, for a corner definitely his, and we have to consider where the line of reconciliation comes.

And yet, just like civil liberty itself is a compromise supported by restrictions, this specific kind of liberty must also have its limitations. Taken to its extreme, the right to free movement becomes indistinguishable from the right to free intrusion. We've already touched on an agreement with Aristotle's argument against communism in a comment on More's Utopia, which suggests that it forces people into an unbearable constant interaction. Schopenhauer expanded on Aristotle with his own bitterness and used a vivid image when he compared human society to hedgehogs huddling together for warmth, feeling uncomfortable when they are either too close or too far apart. Empedocles saw no real meaning in life except as a constant play of love and hate, attraction and repulsion, assimilation and the assertion of difference. As long as we overlook difference and individuality—which I believe has been the common flaw of all past Utopias—we can make absolute statements, advocate for communism or individualism, and create all sorts of rigid theoretical frameworks. But in the real world, which—to modernize Heraclitus and Empedocles—is nothing more or less than the world of individuality, there are no absolute rights or wrongs, no qualitative issues at all, only quantitative adjustments. The desire for freedom of movement and the desire for a certain amount of privacy, for a space that is definitively one’s own, are equally strong in a normal civilized person, and we need to figure out where the balance lies.

The desire for absolute personal privacy is perhaps never a very strong or persistent craving. In the great majority of human beings, the gregarious instinct is sufficiently powerful to render any but the most temporary isolations not simply disagreeable, but painful. The savage has all the privacy he needs within the compass of his skull; like dogs and timid women, he prefers ill-treatment to desertion, and it is only a scarce and complex modern type that finds comfort and refreshment in quite lonely places and quite solitary occupations. Yet such there are, men who can neither sleep well nor think well, nor attain to a full perception of beautiful objects, who do not savour the best of existence until they are securely alone, and for the sake of these even it would be reasonable to draw some limits to the general right of free movement. But their particular need is only a special and exceptional aspect of an almost universal claim to privacy among modern people, not so much for the sake of isolation as for congenial companionship. We want to go apart from the great crowd, not so much to be alone as to be with those who appeal to us particularly and to whom we particularly appeal; we want to form households and societies with them, to give our individualities play in intercourse with them, and in the appointments and furnishings of that intercourse. We want gardens and enclosures and exclusive freedoms for our like and our choice, just as spacious as we can get them—and it is only the multitudinous uncongenial, anxious also for similar developments in some opposite direction, that checks this expansive movement of personal selection and necessitates a compromise on privacy.

The desire for total personal privacy is probably never a strong or lasting craving. For most people, the instinct to socialize is strong enough that any isolation beyond a short period becomes not just uncomfortable, but painful. The primitive person has all the privacy they need within their own mind; like dogs and shy women, they prefer mistreatment to being alone, and it's only a rare and complex modern individual who finds comfort and refreshment in truly lonely places and solitary activities. Yet such individuals do exist—people who can’t sleep well, think clearly, or fully appreciate beautiful things unless they’re securely alone. For the sake of these individuals, it would make sense to set some boundaries on the general right to move freely. However, their specific need is just a unique and exceptional part of a nearly universal demand for privacy among modern people, not so much for isolation as for enjoyable companionship. We want to separate from the large crowd, not just to be alone but to be with those who resonate with us and to whom we resonate; we want to create households and communities with them, to express our individuality in our interactions and in the arrangements of those interactions. We desire gardens and private spaces and exclusive freedoms for those like us and those we choose, as expansive as we can make them—and it’s only the many incompatible individuals, also seeking similar freedoms in a different direction, that limits this broad movement toward personal choice and makes it necessary to compromise on privacy.

Glancing back from our Utopian mountain side down which this discourse marches, to the confusions of old earth, we may remark that the need and desire for privacies there is exceptionally great at the present time, that it was less in the past, that in the future it may be less again, and that under the Utopian conditions to which we shall come when presently we strike yonder road, it may be reduced to quite manageable dimensions. But this is to be effected not by the suppression of individualities to some common pattern, [Footnote: More's Utopia. “Whoso will may go in, for there is nothing within the houses that is private or anie man's owne.”] but by the broadening of public charity and the general amelioration of mind and manners. It is not by assimilation, that is to say, but by understanding that the modern Utopia achieves itself. The ideal community of man's past was one with a common belief, with common customs and common ceremonies, common manners and common formulæ; men of the same society dressed in the same fashion, each according to his defined and understood grade, behaved in the same fashion, loved, worshipped, and died in the same fashion. They did or felt little that did not find a sympathetic publicity. The natural disposition of all peoples, white, black, or brown, a natural disposition that education seeks to destroy, is to insist upon uniformity, to make publicity extremely unsympathetic to even the most harmless departures from the code. To be dressed “odd,” to behave “oddly,” to eat in a different manner or of different food, to commit, indeed, any breach of the established convention is to give offence and to incur hostility among unsophisticated men. But the disposition of the more original and enterprising minds at all times has been to make such innovations.

Looking back from our ideal mountain view, down at the chaos of the old world, we can note that the need and desire for personal space is especially strong right now, that it was less so in the past, that it might be even less in the future, and that under the ideal conditions we’ll reach when we take that road ahead, it could become more manageable. But this won’t happen by forcing everyone into a common mold, [Footnote: More's Utopia. “Anyone can enter, as there is nothing inside the houses that is private or anyone’s own.”] but by expanding public kindness and improving people’s minds and behaviors. The modern utopia develops not through conformity, but through understanding. The ideal community of the past shared common beliefs, customs, ceremonies, manners, and norms; people of the same society dressed alike, each according to their recognized and accepted status, behaved similarly, and loved, worshipped, and died in the same way. They did or felt little that didn’t receive public acknowledgment. The natural inclination of all groups—whether white, black, or brown—an inclination that education aims to eliminate, is to demand uniformity and make public scrutiny harsh towards even the most innocent deviations from the norm. Dressing “differently,” acting “strangely,” eating in unusual ways or different foods, or breaking established conventions is seen as offensive and can lead to hostility among less sophisticated individuals. However, those with more original and adventurous minds have always sought to make these kinds of changes.

This is particularly in evidence in this present age. The almost cataclysmal development of new machinery, the discovery of new materials, and the appearance of new social possibilities through the organised pursuit of material science, has given enormous and unprecedented facilities to the spirit of innovation. The old local order has been broken up or is now being broken up all over the earth, and everywhere societies deliquesce, everywhere men are afloat amidst the wreckage of their flooded conventions, and still tremendously unaware of the thing that has happened. The old local orthodoxies of behaviour, of precedence, the old accepted amusements and employments, the old ritual of conduct in the important small things of the daily life and the old ritual of thought in the things that make discussion, are smashed up and scattered and mixed discordantly together, one use with another, and no world-wide culture of toleration, no courteous admission of differences, no wider understanding has yet replaced them. And so publicity in the modern earth has become confusedly unsympathetic for everyone. Classes are intolerable to classes and sets to sets, contact provokes aggressions, comparisons, persecutions and discomforts, and the subtler people are excessively tormented by a sense of observation, unsympathetic always and often hostile. To live without some sort of segregation from the general mass is impossible in exact proportion to one's individual distinction.

This is especially evident in today’s world. The rapid development of new technologies, the discovery of new materials, and the rise of new social opportunities through organized efforts in material science have provided immense and unprecedented support for innovation. The old local structures have been disrupted or are currently being dismantled all around the globe. Societies are dissolving, people are lost amidst the debris of outdated conventions, and most remain completely unaware of what has happened. The traditional norms of behavior, hierarchy, accepted pastimes and jobs, and the familiar routines of everyday life—along with the old ways of discussing important topics—are all shattered and chaotically mixed together. No global culture of tolerance, no respectful acknowledgment of differences, and no broader understanding has yet replaced these norms. As a result, public life in the modern world has become confused and unwelcoming for everyone. Social classes are intolerant of one another, groups clash, interactions lead to tensions, comparisons, persecution, and discomfort, and those who are more perceptive feel acutely strained by a constant sense of being observed, which is often unkind and sometimes hostile. Living without some form of separation from the masses is impossible, especially for those with a strong sense of individuality.

Of course things will be very different in Utopia. Utopia will be saturated with consideration. To us, clad as we are in mountain-soiled tweeds and with no money but British bank-notes negotiable only at a practically infinite distance, this must needs be a reassuring induction. And Utopian manners will not only be tolerant, but almost universally tolerable. Endless things will be understood perfectly and universally that on earth are understood only by a scattered few; baseness of bearing, grossness of manner, will be the distinctive mark of no section of the community whatever. The coarser reasons for privacy, therefore, will not exist here. And that savage sort of shyness, too, that makes so many half-educated people on earth recluse and defensive, that too the Utopians will have escaped by their more liberal breeding. In the cultivated State we are assuming it will be ever so much easier for people to eat in public, rest and amuse themselves in public, and even work in public. Our present need for privacy in many things marks, indeed, a phase of transition from an ease in public in the past due to homogeneity, to an ease in public in the future due to intelligence and good breeding, and in Utopia that transition will be complete. We must bear that in mind throughout the consideration of this question.

Of course, things will be very different in Utopia. Utopia will be filled with consideration. For us, dressed in mountain-soiled tweeds and with only British banknotes that can be exchanged at a practically impossible distance, this is a comforting thought. Utopian manners will not only be tolerant but also generally acceptable. Many things will be perfectly understood and appreciated that are only recognized by a few on Earth; rudeness and bad behavior won't define any group in the community. Therefore, the common reasons for privacy won't exist here. The awkward kind of shyness that makes so many partially educated people on Earth withdrawn and defensive will also be absent in Utopia due to their more open upbringing. In the cultivated society we're imagining, it will be much easier for people to eat, relax, have fun, and even work in public. Our current need for privacy in many areas indicates a shift from a past where public ease came from similarity to a future where it comes from intelligence and good manners, and in Utopia, that shift will be complete. We should keep that in mind as we think about this issue.

Yet, after this allowance has been made, there still remains a considerable claim for privacy in Utopia. The room, or apartments, or home, or mansion, whatever it may be a man or woman maintains, must be private, and under his or her complete dominion; it seems harsh and intrusive to forbid a central garden plot or peristyle, such as one sees in Pompeii, within the house walls, and it is almost as difficult to deny a little private territory beyond the house. Yet if we concede that, it is clear that without some further provision we concede the possibility that the poorer townsman (if there are to be rich and poor in the world) will be forced to walk through endless miles of high fenced villa gardens before he may expand in his little scrap of reserved open country. Such is already the poor Londoner's miserable fate.... Our Utopia will have, of course, faultless roads and beautifully arranged inter-urban communications, swift trains or motor services or what not, to diffuse its population, and without some anticipatory provisions, the prospect of the residential areas becoming a vast area of defensively walled villa Edens is all too possible.

Yet even after making this allowance, there’s still a significant need for privacy in Utopia. The room, apartment, home, or mansion that a person has must be private and completely under their control; it seems harsh and intrusive to prohibit a central garden or colonnade, like those found in Pompeii, within the house, and it's nearly as hard to deny a small private space outside the house. However, if we agree to that, it's clear that without further measures, we risk allowing the poorer townsfolk (assuming there will always be rich and poor in the world) to wander through endless high-walled villa gardens before they can enjoy their small piece of reserved open land. This is already the unfortunate reality for many in London.... Our Utopia will, of course, have perfect roads and beautifully designed transport systems, fast trains or buses or whatever else is needed to spread out its population, but without some foresight, the likelihood of residential areas turning into a vast expanse of defensively walled villa paradises is all too real.

This is a quantitative question, be it remembered, and not to be dismissed by any statement of principle. Our Utopians will meet it, I presume, by detailed regulations, very probably varying locally with local conditions. Privacy beyond the house might be made a privilege to be paid for in proportion to the area occupied, and the tax on these licences of privacy might increase as the square of the area affected. A maximum fraction of private enclosure for each urban and suburban square mile could be fixed. A distinction could be drawn between an absolutely private garden and a garden private and closed only for a day or a couple of days a week, and at other times open to the well-behaved public. Who, in a really civilised community, would grudge that measure of invasion? Walls could be taxed by height and length, and the enclosure of really natural beauties, of rapids, cascades, gorges, viewpoints, and so forth made impossible. So a reasonable compromise between the vital and conflicting claims of the freedom of movement and the freedom of seclusion might be attained....

This is a numerical question, remember, and it shouldn’t be brushed aside by any theoretical statement. I assume our Utopians will approach it with specific regulations, likely varying based on local conditions. Privacy beyond the home could become a privilege that people pay for based on the space they occupy, and the fee for these privacy permits could increase with the square of the area affected. A maximum percentage of private land could be established for each urban and suburban square mile. We could differentiate between a fully private garden and a garden that is private and closed for a day or two a week, but open at other times to well-behaved visitors. Who, in a truly civilized community, would begrudge that level of intrusion? Walls could be taxed based on their height and length, and the enclosure of truly natural attractions, like rapids, waterfalls, gorges, viewpoints, and so forth, could be prohibited. Thus, a reasonable compromise between the crucial but conflicting needs for freedom of movement and freedom of privacy might be achieved....

And as we argue thus we draw nearer and nearer to the road that goes up and over the Gotthard crest and down the Val Tremola towards Italy.

And as we argue this way, we draw closer and closer to the road that goes up and over the Gotthard pass and down the Val Tremola toward Italy.

What sort of road would that be?

What kind of road would that be?

§ 3

Freedom of movement in a Utopia planned under modern conditions must involve something more than unrestricted pedestrian wanderings, and the very proposition of a world-state speaking one common tongue carries with it the idea of a world population travelled and travelling to an extent quite beyond anything our native earth has seen. It is now our terrestrial experience that whenever economic and political developments set a class free to travel, that class at once begins to travel; in England, for example, above the five or six hundred pounds a year level, it is hard to find anyone who is not habitually migratory, who has not been frequently, as people say, “abroad.” In the Modern Utopia travel must be in the common texture of life. To go into fresh climates and fresh scenery, to meet a different complexion of humanity and a different type of home and food and apparatus, to mark unfamiliar trees and plants and flowers and beasts, to climb mountains, to see the snowy night of the North and the blaze of the tropical midday, to follow great rivers, to taste loneliness in desert places, to traverse the gloom of tropical forests and to cross the high seas, will be an essential part of the reward and adventure of life, even for the commonest people.... This is a bright and pleasant particular in which a modern Utopia must differ again, and differ diametrically, from its predecessors.

Freedom of movement in a Utopia designed for modern times has to mean more than just unrestricted walking around. The very idea of a world-state with one common language suggests a global population traveling far beyond anything we’ve ever seen on Earth. From our experience, whenever economic and political changes allow a certain class to travel, that class immediately starts to explore; for instance, in England, it's rare to find anyone earning over five or six hundred pounds a year who isn’t frequently on the move or hasn’t traveled “abroad.” In the Modern Utopia, travel needs to be woven into the fabric of everyday life. Experiencing new climates and landscapes, meeting different types of people, discovering various homes, foods, and cultures, observing unfamiliar trees, plants, flowers, and animals, climbing mountains, witnessing the icy nights of the North and the bright heat of tropical midday, following majestic rivers, experiencing solitude in desolate places, navigating the shadowy depths of tropical forests, and crossing the vast oceans will be essential parts of the rewards and adventures of life, even for the everyday person... This is a bright and enjoyable aspect in which a modern Utopia must significantly differ from its earlier versions.

We may conclude from what has been done in places upon our earth that the whole Utopian world will be open and accessible and as safe for the wayfarer as France or England is to-day. The peace of the world will be established for ever, and everywhere, except in remote and desolate places, there will be convenient inns, at least as convenient and trustworthy as those of Switzerland to-day; the touring clubs and hotel associations that have tariffed that country and France so effectually will have had their fine Utopian equivalents, and the whole world will be habituated to the coming and going of strangers. The greater part of the world will be as secure and cheaply and easily accessible to everyone as is Zermatt or Lucerne to a Western European of the middle-class at the present time.

We can conclude from what’s been done in various places on our planet that the entire Utopian world will be open, accessible, and as safe for travelers as France or England is today. World peace will be established permanently, and everywhere, except in remote and desolate areas, there will be convenient inns, at least as reliable and comfortable as those in Switzerland today. The touring clubs and hotel associations that have effectively set prices in that country and France will have their excellent Utopian counterparts, and the whole world will be accustomed to the comings and goings of strangers. Most of the world will be as safe and easy to access for everyone as Zermatt or Lucerne is for a middle-class Western European today.

On this account alone no places will be so congested as these two are now on earth. With freedom to go everywhere, with easy access everywhere, with no dread of difficulties about language, coinage, custom, or law, why should everyone continue to go to just a few special places? Such congestions are merely the measure of the general inaccessibility and insecurity and costliness of contemporary life, an awkward transitory phase in the first beginnings of the travel age of mankind.

For this reason alone, no places will be as crowded as these two are now on earth. With the freedom to travel anywhere, with easy access everywhere, and without the fear of language barriers, currency issues, customs, or laws, why should everyone keep flocking to just a few specific locations? These crowds are simply a reflection of how generally hard to reach, unsafe, and expensive modern life is—an awkward phase in the early days of human travel.

No doubt the Utopian will travel in many ways. It is unlikely there will be any smoke-disgorging steam railway trains in Utopia, they are already doomed on earth, already threatened with that obsolescence that will endear them to the Ruskins of to-morrow, but a thin spider's web of inconspicuous special routes will cover the land of the world, pierce the mountain masses and tunnel under the seas. These may be double railways or monorails or what not—we are no engineers to judge between such devices—but by means of them the Utopian will travel about the earth from one chief point to another at a speed of two or three hundred miles or more an hour. That will abolish the greater distances.... One figures these main communications as something after the manner of corridor trains, smooth-running and roomy, open from end to end, with cars in which one may sit and read, cars in which one may take refreshment, cars into which the news of the day comes printing itself from the wires beside the track; cars in which one may have privacy and sleep if one is so disposed, bath-room cars, library cars; a train as comfortable as a good club. There will be no distinctions of class in such a train, because in a civilised world there would be no offence between one kind of man and another, and for the good of the whole world such travelling will be as cheap as it can be, and well within the reach of any but the almost criminally poor.

The Utopian will likely travel in many different ways. It's improbable that there will be any smoke-belching steam trains in Utopia, as they are already becoming outdated on Earth, and will soon be loved by future Ruskins. Instead, a web of inconspicuous special routes will spread across the land, cutting through mountains and tunneling beneath seas. These could be double railways, monorails, or other innovations—we're not engineers to evaluate those—but through these systems, the Utopian will travel across the globe from one major location to another at speeds of two or three hundred miles an hour or more. This will eliminate long distances... One could imagine these main routes resembling corridor trains, smooth and spacious, open at both ends, with cars for sitting and reading, cars for dining, and cars where the day’s news is printed from wires next to the tracks; cars for privacy and sleeping if one chooses, bathroom cars, library cars; a train as comfortable as a good club. There would be no class distinctions on such a train because, in a civilized world, there would be no conflict between different types of people, and to benefit the whole world, such travel would be as affordable as possible, accessible to all but the severely impoverished.

Such great tramways as this will be used when the Utopians wish to travel fast and far; thereby you will glide all over the land surface of the planet; and feeding them and distributing from them, innumerable minor systems, clean little electric tramways I picture them, will spread out over the land in finer reticulations, growing close and dense in the urban regions and thinning as the population thins. And running beside these lighter railways, and spreading beyond their range, will be the smooth minor high roads such as this one we now approach, upon which independent vehicles, motor cars, cycles, and what not, will go. I doubt if we shall see any horses upon this fine, smooth, clean road; I doubt if there will be many horses on the high roads of Utopia, and, indeed, if they will use draught horses at all upon that planet. Why should they? Where the world gives turf or sand, or along special tracts, the horse will perhaps be ridden for exercise and pleasure, but that will be all the use for him; and as for the other beasts of burthen, on the remoter mountain tracks the mule will no doubt still be a picturesque survival, in the desert men will still find a use for the camel, and the elephant may linger to play a part in the pageant of the East. But the burthen of the minor traffic, if not the whole of it, will certainly be mechanical. This is what we shall see even while the road is still remote, swift and shapely motor-cars going past, cyclists, and in these agreeable mountain regions there will also be pedestrians upon their way. Cycle tracks will abound in Utopia, sometimes following beside the great high roads, but oftener taking their own more agreeable line amidst woods and crops and pastures; and there will be a rich variety of footpaths and minor ways. There will be many footpaths in Utopia. There will be pleasant ways over the scented needles of the mountain pinewoods, primrose-strewn tracks amidst the budding thickets of the lower country, paths running beside rushing streams, paths across the wide spaces of the corn land, and, above all, paths through the flowery garden spaces amidst which the houses in the towns will stand. And everywhere about the world, on road and path, by sea and land, the happy holiday Utopians will go.

Such amazing tramways as this will be used when the Utopians want to travel quickly and far; this way, you'll be able to glide across the entire land surface of the planet. Feeding off and distributing from these, countless smaller systems—clean little electric tramways, as I imagine them—will spread out over the land in finer networks, becoming closer and denser in urban areas and fading as the population size decreases. Alongside these lighter railways, and extending beyond their reach, will be smooth minor highways like this one we are approaching, where independent vehicles, cars, bikes, and more will travel. I doubt we will see many horses on this lovely, smooth, clean road; I think the high roads of Utopia will have very few horses, if any, used for work at all. Why would they? Where the Earth offers grass or dirt, or on specific routes, horses might be ridden for fun and exercise, but that would be their only purpose. As for other pack animals, mules will likely remain a picturesque presence on remote mountain paths, camels will still be needed in the desert, and elephants may continue to play a role in the pageantry of the East. But for the majority of light traffic, if not all of it, it will certainly be mechanical. This is what we will see even when the road is still distant: fast, sleek motor cars zooming by, cyclists, and in these pleasant mountain areas, there will also be pedestrians out and about. Cycle paths will be plentiful in Utopia, sometimes running alongside the main highways, but more often taking their own more enjoyable routes through forests, fields, and meadows; and there will be a rich variety of walking paths and smaller trails. Utopia will have many walking paths. There will be lovely routes over the fragrant pine needles of the mountain woods, primrose-covered paths winding through budding thickets of the lower countryside, paths alongside rushing streams, paths across expansive fields of grain, and most importantly, paths through flowery garden areas where houses in the towns will reside. And everywhere across the world, on roads and paths, by sea and land, the happy holiday Utopians will roam.

The population of Utopia will be a migratory population beyond any earthly precedent, not simply a travelling population, but migratory. The old Utopias were all localised, as localised as a parish councillor; but it is manifest that nowadays even quite ordinary people live over areas that would have made a kingdom in those former days, would have filled the Athenian of the Laws with incredulous astonishment. Except for the habits of the very rich during the Roman Empire, there was never the slightest precedent for this modern detachment from place. It is nothing to us that we go eighty or ninety miles from home to place of business, or take an hour's spin of fifty miles to our week-end golf; every summer it has become a fixed custom to travel wide and far. Only the clumsiness of communications limit us now, and every facilitation of locomotion widens not only our potential, but our habitual range. Not only this, but we change our habitations with a growing frequency and facility; to Sir Thomas More we should seem a breed of nomads. That old fixity was of necessity and not of choice, it was a mere phase in the development of civilisation, a trick of rooting man learnt for a time from his new-found friends, the corn and the vine and the hearth; the untamed spirit of the young has turned for ever to wandering and the sea. The soul of man has never yet in any land been willingly adscript to the glebe. Even Mr. Belloc, who preaches the happiness of a peasant proprietary, is so much wiser than his thoughts that he sails about the seas in a little yacht or goes afoot from Belgium to Rome. We are winning our freedom again once more, a freedom renewed and enlarged, and there is now neither necessity nor advantage in a permanent life servitude to this place or that. Men may settle down in our Modern Utopia for love and the family at last, but first and most abundantly they will see the world.

The population of Utopia will be a migratory group like never seen before, not just a traveling population, but truly migratory. The old Utopias were all localized, as specific as a parish councillor; but it's clear that nowadays even regular people cover areas that would have constituted a kingdom in the past, which would have left the Athenian of the Laws in disbelief. Except for the habits of the very wealthy during the Roman Empire, there was never any precedent for this modern detachment from location. It doesn’t faze us to travel eighty or ninety miles from home for work or to take an hour's drive for a fifty-mile trip to play golf on the weekend; every summer, it has become a tradition to travel widely and far. Only the awkwardness of travel limits us now, and every advance in transportation not only expands our potential but also our usual range. Moreover, we change our homes with increasing frequency and ease; to Sir Thomas More, we would seem like a group of nomads. That old stability was out of necessity, not choice; it was just a phase in the evolution of civilization, a way of settling that humans learned for a time from their newfound friends—the crops, the vines, and the hearth. The untamed spirit of the young has turned forever toward wandering and the sea. The human soul has never willingly been tied to the land in any region. Even Mr. Belloc, who promotes the joys of peasant ownership, is much smarter than his beliefs suggest, as he sails across the seas in a small yacht or walks from Belgium to Rome. We are reclaiming our freedom once again, a renewed and expanded freedom, and there is no longer any necessity or benefit to being permanently tied to one place or another. People might settle in our Modern Utopia for love and family eventually, but first and foremost, they will explore the world.

And with this loosening of the fetters of locality from the feet of men, necessarily there will be all sorts of fresh distributions of the factors of life. On our own poor haphazard earth, wherever men work, wherever there are things to be grown, minerals to be won, power to be used, there, regardless of all the joys and decencies of life, the households needs must cluster. But in Utopia there will be wide stretches of cheerless or unhealthy or toilsome or dangerous land with never a household; there will be regions of mining and smelting, black with the smoke of furnaces and gashed and desolated by mines, with a sort of weird inhospitable grandeur of industrial desolation, and the men will come thither and work for a spell and return to civilisation again, washing and changing their attire in the swift gliding train. And by way of compensation there will be beautiful regions of the earth specially set apart and favoured for children; in them the presence of children will remit taxation, while in other less wholesome places the presence of children will be taxed; the lower passes and fore hills of these very Alps, for example, will be populous with homes, serving the vast arable levels of Upper Italy.

And with this loosening of the local ties that bind people, there will inevitably be all kinds of new distributions of life's factors. On our uneven and chaotic planet, wherever people work, where things are grown, minerals are extracted, or energy is harnessed, households will cluster together, regardless of the joys and comforts of life. But in Utopia, there will be large areas of bleak, unhealthy, hard, or dangerous land with no households at all; there will be regions of mining and smelting, dark with the smoke from furnaces and scarred and ruined by mines, presenting a strange, unwelcoming beauty of industrial wasteland. Men will go there to work for a time and then return to civilization, changing and washing up on the fast-moving trains. As compensation, there will be beautiful areas of the earth set aside and favored for children; there, the presence of children will reduce taxes, while in other less healthy places, having children will come with a tax. The lower slopes and foothills of these very Alps, for example, will be filled with homes supporting the vast arable lands of Upper Italy.

So we shall see, as we come down by our little lake in the lap of Lucendro, and even before we reach the road, the first scattered chalets and households in which these migrant people live, the upper summer homes. With the coming of summer, as the snows on the high Alps recede, a tide of households and schools, teachers and doctors, and all such attendant services will flow up the mountain masses, and ebb again when the September snows return. It is essential to the modern ideal of life that the period of education and growth should be prolonged to as late a period as possible and puberty correspondingly retarded, and by wise regulation the statesmen of Utopia will constantly adjust and readjust regulations and taxation to diminish the proportion of children reared in hot and stimulating conditions. These high mountains will, in the bright sweet summer, be populous with youth. Even up towards this high place where the snow is scarce gone until July, these households will extend, and below, the whole long valley of Urseren will be a scattered summer town.

So, as we walk down by our little lake in the lap of Lucendro, we'll notice the first few scattered chalets and homes where these migrant families live—these are the upper summer residences. With summer's arrival, as the snow on the high Alps melts away, a wave of families, schools, teachers, doctors, and all sorts of essential services will make their way up the mountains and then retreat again when the September snows come back. It's crucial to the modern idea of life that the time for education and growth lasts as long as possible, and that puberty is delayed accordingly. The leaders of Utopia will continuously adjust regulations and taxes to reduce the number of children raised in hot and stimulating environments. During the bright, pleasant summer, these high mountains will be filled with young people. Even here, where the snow doesn't fully melt until July, these homes will spread out, and below, the entire long valley of Urseren will become a scattered summer town.

One figures one of the more urban highways, one of those along which the light railways of the second order run, such as that in the valley of Urseren, into which we should presently come. I figure it as one would see it at night, a band a hundred yards perhaps in width, the footpath on either side shaded with high trees and lit softly with orange glowlights; while down the centre the tramway of the road will go, with sometimes a nocturnal tram-car gliding, lit and gay but almost noiselessly, past. Lantern-lit cyclists will flit along the track like fireflies, and ever and again some humming motor-car will hurry by, to or from the Rhoneland or the Rhineland or Switzerland or Italy. Away on either side the lights of the little country homes up the mountain slopes will glow.

Picture one of the busier urban highways, one of those that runs alongside the smaller light railways, like the one in the Urseren valley, which we’ll soon encounter. I imagine it as it would be at night, a strip about a hundred yards wide, with sidewalks on either side shaded by tall trees and softly illuminated by orange glow lights; while down the center, the tramway will run, occasionally a night tram gliding by, lit up and cheerful but almost silent. Cyclists with lanterns will zip along the track like fireflies, and now and then a humming motor vehicle will speed past, heading to or from the Rhoneland, the Rhineland, Switzerland, or Italy. Off to either side, the lights from the little country homes on the mountain slopes will shine.

I figure it at night, because so it is we should see it first.

I think about it at night because that’s when we should see it first.

We should come out from our mountain valley into the minor road that runs down the lonely rock wilderness of the San Gotthard Pass, we should descend that nine miles of winding route, and so arrive towards twilight among the clustering homes and upland unenclosed gardens of Realp and Hospenthal and Andermatt. Between Realp and Andermatt, and down the Schoellenen gorge, the greater road would run. By the time we reached it, we should be in the way of understanding our adventure a little better. We should know already, when we saw those two familiar clusters of chalets and hotels replaced by a great dispersed multitude of houses—we should see their window lights, but little else—that we were the victims of some strange transition in space or time, and we should come down by dimly-seen buildings into the part that would answer to Hospenthal, wondering and perhaps a little afraid. We should come out into this great main roadway—this roadway like an urban avenue—and look up it and down, hesitating whether to go along the valley Furka-ward, or down by Andermatt through the gorge that leads to Göschenen....

We should leave our mountain valley and take the small road that leads through the desolate rock wilderness of the San Gotthard Pass. We would wind down the nine miles of twisting path and arrive around twilight among the clusters of homes and the open gardens of Realp, Hospenthal, and Andermatt. The main road would run between Realp and Andermatt, down the Schoellenen gorge. By the time we got there, we would start to understand our adventure a bit better. We would realize, when we saw those two familiar groups of chalets and hotels replaced by a sprawling collection of houses—we’d see their lights in the windows, but not much else—that we were experiencing some odd shift in space or time. We would come down past dimly lit buildings toward the area that represented Hospenthal, feeling a mix of wonder and perhaps a little fear. We would step out onto this wide main road—like an urban avenue—and look up and down, unsure whether to head towards the valley Furka-ward or down through Andermatt into the gorge leading to Göschenen....

People would pass us in the twilight, and then more people; we should see they walked well and wore a graceful, unfamiliar dress, but more we should not distinguish.

People would walk by us in the evening light, and then more people would follow; we could see they walked elegantly and wore a beautiful, unfamiliar style of clothing, but we couldn’t make out much more than that.

“Good-night!” they would say to us in clear, fine voices. Their dim faces would turn with a passing scrutiny towards us.

“Good night!” they would say to us in clear, distinct voices. Their faint faces would turn with a brief look towards us.

We should answer out of our perplexity: “Good-night!”—for by the conventions established in the beginning of this book, we are given the freedom of their tongue.

We should respond out of our confusion: “Goodnight!”—because according to the rules set at the start of this book, we have the freedom to speak in their language.

§ 4

Were this a story, I should tell at length how much we were helped by the good fortune of picking up a Utopian coin of gold, how at last we adventured into the Utopian inn and found it all marvellously easy. You see us the shyest and most watchful of guests; but of the food they put before us and the furnishings of the house, and all our entertainment, it will be better to speak later. We are in a migratory world, we know, one greatly accustomed to foreigners; our mountain clothes are not strange enough to attract acute attention, though ill-made and shabby, no doubt, by Utopian standards; we are dealt with as we might best wish to be dealt with, that is to say as rather untidy, inconspicuous men. We look about us and watch for hints and examples, and, indeed, get through with the thing. And after our queer, yet not unpleasant, dinner, in which we remark no meat figures, we go out of the house for a breath of air and for quiet counsel one with another, and there it is we discover those strange constellations overhead. It comes to us then, clear and full, that our imagination has realised itself; we dismiss quite finally a Rip-Van-Winkle fancy we have entertained, all the unfamiliarities of our descent from the mountain pass gather together into one fullness of conviction, and we know, we know, we are in Utopia.

If this were a story, I would go on and on about how lucky we were to find a Utopian gold coin, how we finally ventured into the Utopian inn and everything felt surprisingly easy. You see us as the shyest and most cautious guests; but when it comes to the food served to us, the furnishings of the place, and all our entertainment, it’s better to discuss that later. We are aware that we’re in a migratory world, one that is quite used to visitors; our mountain clothes aren’t unique enough to draw too much attention, even though they are likely seen as poorly made and shabby by Utopian standards. We’re treated exactly as we would hope to be treated, that is, as somewhat scruffy, inconspicuous men. We look around, observe for clues and examples, and honestly, we manage just fine. After our odd, yet not unpleasant, dinner, during which we notice there’s no meat on the menu, we step outside for a breath of fresh air and a moment of quiet conversation, and it’s there that we see those strange constellations above us. It becomes clear and undeniable that our imagination has come to life; we fully set aside a Rip-Van-Winkle fantasy we had entertained, all the unfamiliar experiences of our journey down from the mountain combine into a single, strong realization, and we know, we know, we are in Utopia.

We wander under the trees by the main road, watching the dim passers-by as though they were the phantoms of a dream. We say little to one another. We turn aside into a little pathway and come to a bridge over the turbulent Reuss, hurrying down towards the Devil's Bridge in the gorge below. Far away over the Furka ridge a pallid glow preludes the rising of the moon.

We stroll under the trees along the main road, observing the faint figures passing by as if they were ghosts from a dream. We hardly speak to each other. We veer off onto a small path and reach a bridge over the rushing Reuss, which speeds toward the Devil's Bridge in the gorge below. In the distance, over the Furka ridge, a pale light hints at the impending rise of the moon.

Two lovers pass us whispering, and we follow them with our eyes. This Utopia has certainly preserved the fundamental freedom, to love. And then a sweet-voiced bell from somewhere high up towards Oberalp chimes two-and-twenty times.

Two lovers walk by, whispering to each other, and we watch them intently. This Utopia has definitely maintained the essential freedom to love. Then, a soft bell rings from somewhere high up near Oberalp, chiming twenty-two times.

I break the silence. “That might mean ten o'clock,” I say.

I interrupt the quiet. “That could mean ten o'clock,” I say.

My companion leans upon the bridge and looks down into the dim river below. I become aware of the keen edge of the moon like a needle of incandescent silver creeping over the crest, and suddenly the river is alive with flashes.

My friend leans on the bridge and looks down into the dark river below. I notice the sharp edge of the moon, like a glowing silver needle, creeping over the top, and suddenly the river comes alive with glimmers.

He speaks, and astonishes me with the hidden course his thoughts have taken.

He speaks, and surprises me with the unexpected direction his thoughts have taken.

“We two were boy and girl lovers like that,” he says, and jerks a head at the receding Utopians. “I loved her first, and I do not think I have ever thought of loving anyone but her.”

“We were just like that, a boy and girl in love,” he says, nodding toward the fading Utopians. “I loved her first, and I don't think I've ever considered loving anyone else but her.”

It is a curiously human thing, and, upon my honour, not one I had designed, that when at last I stand in the twilight in the midst of a Utopian township, when my whole being should be taken up with speculative wonder, this man should be standing by my side, and lugging my attention persistently towards himself, towards his limited futile self. This thing perpetually happens to me, this intrusion of something small and irrelevant and alive, upon my great impressions. The time I first saw the Matterhorn, that Queen among the Alpine summits, I was distracted beyond appreciation by the tale of a man who could not eat sardines—always sardines did this with him and that; and my first wanderings along the brown streets of Pompeii, an experience I had anticipated with a strange intensity, was shot with the most stupidly intelligent discourse on vehicular tariffs in the chief capitals of Europe that it is possible to imagine. And now this man, on my first night in Utopia, talks and talks and talks of his poor little love affair.

It's a strangely human thing, and honestly, not something I planned, that when I finally find myself in the twilight of a perfect community, when I should be lost in wonder, this guy is standing next to me, constantly pulling my attention towards himself and his limited, pointless life. This keeps happening to me, this intrusion of something small, irrelevant, and alive upon my grand moments. The first time I saw the Matterhorn, that queen of Alpine peaks, I couldn't fully appreciate it because I was distracted by a story about a guy who couldn’t eat sardines—always sardines this and that. And during my first stroll through the brown streets of Pompeii, an experience I had looked forward to with intense anticipation, I was bombarded with the most annoyingly intellectual conversation about vehicle tolls in major European cities that you can imagine. And now, on my first night in Utopia, this guy just keeps going on and on about his pathetic little love life.

It shapes itself as the most trite and feeble of tragedies, one of those stories of effortless submission to chance and custom in which Mr. Hardy or George Gissing might have found a theme. I do but half listen at first—watching the black figures in the moonlit roadway pacing to and fro. Yet—I cannot trace how he conveys the subtle conviction to my mind—the woman he loves is beautiful.

It comes across as one of the most clichéd and weak tragedies, like those stories where people surrender to fate and societal norms that Mr. Hardy or George Gissing might have explored. At first, I barely pay attention—observing the dark figures moving back and forth on the moonlit road. Still—I can't quite pinpoint how he instills the quiet belief in me—that the woman he loves is beautiful.

They were boy and girl together, and afterwards they met again as fellow students in a world of comfortable discretions. He seems to have taken the decorums of life with a confiding good faith, to have been shy and innocent in a suppressed sort of way, and of a mental type not made for worldly successes; but he must have dreamt about her and loved her well enough. How she felt for him I could never gather; it seemed to be all of that fleshless friendliness into which we train our girls. Then abruptly happened stresses. The man who became her husband appeared, with a very evident passion. He was a year or so older than either of them, and he had the habit and quality of achieving his ends; he was already successful, and with the promise of wealth, and I, at least, perceived, from my botanist's phrasing, that his desire was for her beauty.

They were a boy and a girl together, and later they met again as classmates in a world of comfortable boundaries. He seemed to approach the formalities of life with a trusting simplicity, appearing shy and innocent in a restrained way, and not the type to succeed in the world; but he must have dreamed about her and loved her enough. How she felt about him was something I could never figure out; it seemed to be all that unembodied friendliness we encourage in our girls. Then suddenly, things changed. The man who would become her husband showed up, clearly passionate. He was a year older than either of them and had the drive and skills to achieve what he wanted; he was already successful and promised wealth, and I could tell from my botanical perspective that his desire was for her beauty.

As my botanist talked I seemed to see the whole little drama, rather clearer than his words gave it me, the actors all absurdly in Hampstead middle-class raiment, meetings of a Sunday after church (the men in silk hats, frock coats, and tightly-rolled umbrellas), rare excursions into evening dress, the decorously vulgar fiction read in their homes, its ambling sentimentalities of thought, the amiably worldly mothers, the respectable fathers, the aunts, the “people”—his “people” and her “people”—the piano music and the song, and in this setting our friend, “quite clever” at botany and “going in” for it “as a profession,” and the girl, gratuitously beautiful; so I figured the arranged and orderly environment into which this claw of an elemental force had thrust itself to grip.

As my botanist spoke, I felt like I could see the whole little drama even more clearly than his words conveyed. The characters were all absurdly dressed in middle-class Hampstead style, meeting on Sundays after church (the men in top hats, frock coats, and neatly rolled umbrellas), with rare occasions for evening attire. They indulged in decorously tacky fiction at home, full of meandering sentimental thoughts, the pleasantly worldly mothers, the respectable fathers, the aunts, the “people”—his “people” and her “people”—the piano music and the songs. In this setting, our friend, “quite smart” in botany and pursuing it “as a career,” and the girl, stunningly beautiful; I envisioned the organized and structured environment into which this claw of a primal force had intruded to seize hold.

The stranger who had come in got what he wanted; the girl considered that she thought she had never loved the botanist, had had only friendship for him—though little she knew of the meaning of those fine words—they parted a little incoherently and in tears, and it had not occurred to the young man to imagine she was not going off to conventional life in some other of the endless Frognals he imagined as the cellular tissue of the world.

The stranger who came in got what he wanted; the girl realized she never truly loved the botanist, only felt friendship for him—even though she hardly understood the meaning of those beautiful words—they parted a bit awkwardly and in tears, and it didn’t cross the young man’s mind that she wasn’t headed off to a conventional life in one of the countless Frognals he pictured as the fabric of the world.

But she wasn't.

But she wasn't.

He had kept her photograph and her memory sweet, and if ever he had strayed from the severest constancy, it seemed only in the end to strengthen with the stuff of experience, to enhance by comparative disappointment his imagination of what she might have meant to him.... Then eight years afterwards they met again.

He had held onto her photo and her memory fondly, and if he ever veered from unwavering loyalty, it seemed only to end up reinforcing his feelings with the weight of experience, to make his imagination of what she could have meant to him even stronger through comparative disappointment... Then, eight years later, they met again.

By the time he gets to this part of his story we have, at my initiative, left the bridge and are walking towards the Utopian guest house. The Utopian guest house! His voice rises and falls, and sometimes he holds my arm. My attention comes and goes. “Good-night,” two sweet-voiced Utopians cry to us in their universal tongue, and I answer them “Good-night.”

By the time he gets to this part of his story, we have, at my suggestion, left the bridge and are walking towards the Utopian guest house. The Utopian guest house! His voice goes up and down, and sometimes he holds my arm. My focus comes and goes. “Good night,” two sweet-voiced Utopians call to us in their universal language, and I reply with “Good night.”

“You see,” he persists, “I saw her only a week ago. It was in Lucerne, while I was waiting for you to come on from England. I talked to her three or four times altogether. And her face—the change in her! I can't get it out of my head—night or day. The miserable waste of her....”

“You see,” he goes on, “I saw her just a week ago. It was in Lucerne, while I was waiting for you to arrive from England. I talked to her three or four times in total. And her face—the change in her! I can't stop thinking about it—night or day. The terrible waste of her....”

Before us, through the tall pine stems, shine the lights of our Utopian inn.

Before us, through the tall pine trunks, glow the lights of our ideal inn.

He talks vaguely of ill-usage. “The husband is vain, boastful, dishonest to the very confines of the law, and a drunkard. There are scenes and insults―”

He speaks vaguely about mistreatment. “The husband is arrogant, braggy, dishonest to the very limits of the law, and an alcoholic. There are arguments and insults―”

“She told you?”

"Did she tell you?"

“Not much, but someone else did. He brings other women almost into her presence to spite her.”

“Not much, but someone else did. He brings other women nearly into her view just to annoy her.”

“And it's going on?” I interrupt.

“And it’s still happening?” I cut in.

“Yes. Now.”

“Yes. Now.”

“Need it go on?”

“Does it need to continue?”

“What do you mean?”

"What do you mean?"

“Lady in trouble,” I say. “Knight at hand. Why not stop this dismal grizzling and carry her off?” (You figure the heroic sweep of the arm that belongs to the Voice.) I positively forget for the moment that we are in Utopia at all.

“Lady in trouble,” I say. “Knight ready to help. Why not stop this sad whining and take her away?” (You can picture the dramatic gesture that goes with the Voice.) I completely forget for a moment that we are in Utopia at all.

“You mean?”

"What do you mean?"

“Take her away from him! What's all this emotion of yours worth if it isn't equal to that!”

“Take her away from him! What’s all these feelings of yours worth if they don’t match that!”

Positively he seems aghast at me.

He definitely looks shocked at me.

“Do you mean elope with her?”

“Are you saying to run away with her?”

“It seems a most suitable case.”

“It seems like a very appropriate case.”

For a space he is silent, and we go on through the trees. A Utopian tram-car passes and I see his face, poor bitted wretch! looking pinched and scared in its trailing glow of light.

For a moment, he stays quiet, and we walk on through the trees. A futuristic tram passes by, and I see his face, the poor miserable guy! He looks strained and frightened in its fading light.

“That's all very well in a novel,” he says. “But how could I go back to my laboratory, mixed classes with young ladies, you know, after a thing like that? How could we live and where could we live? We might have a house in London, but who would call upon us?... Besides, you don't know her. She is not the sort of woman.... Don't think I'm timid or conventional. Don't think I don't feel.... Feel! You don't know what it is to feel in a case of this sort....”

“That's all fine in a book,” he says. “But how could I go back to my lab, hanging out with young women, you know, after something like that? How would we support ourselves and where would we even live? We might have a place in London, but who would come to visit us?… Besides, you don’t really know her. She’s not that kind of woman… Don’t assume I’m scared or old-fashioned. Don’t think I don’t feel… Feel! You have no idea what it’s like to feel this way in a situation like this…”

He halts and then flies out viciously: “Ugh! There are times when I could strangle him with my hands.”

He stops and then bursts out angrily: “Ugh! There are moments when I could just strangle him with my bare hands.”

Which is nonsense.

That's nonsense.

He flings out his lean botanising hands in an impotent gesture.

He throws out his thin, plant-searching hands in a powerless gesture.

“My dear Man!” I say, and say no more.

"My dear man!" I say, and leave it at that.

For a moment I forget we are in Utopia altogether.

For a moment, I completely forget that we are in Utopia.

§ 5

Let us come back to Utopia. We were speaking of travel.

Let’s return to Utopia. We were talking about travel.

Besides roadways and railways and tramways, for those who go to and fro in the earth the Modern Utopians will have very many other ways of travelling. There will be rivers, for example, with a vast variety of boats; canals with diverse sorts of haulage; there will be lakes and lagoons; and when one comes at last to the borders of the land, the pleasure craft will be there, coming and going, and the swift great passenger vessels, very big and steady, doing thirty knots an hour or more, will trace long wakes as they go dwindling out athwart the restless vastness of the sea.

Besides roads, railways, and trams, the Modern Utopians will have plenty of other ways to travel. There will be rivers, for instance, with a wide range of boats; canals with different types of transport; there will be lakes and lagoons; and when you finally reach the edge of the land, there will be pleasure boats coming and going. The large, steady passenger ships, traveling at thirty knots an hour or more, will leave long wakes as they fade into the vast, restless sea.

They will be just beginning to fly in Utopia. We owe much to M. Santos Dumont; the world is immeasurably more disposed to believe this wonder is coming, and coming nearly, than it was five years ago. But unless we are to suppose Utopian scientific knowledge far in advance of ours—and though that supposition was not proscribed in our initial undertaking, it would be inconvenient for us and not quite in the vein of the rest of our premises—they, too, will only be in the same experimental stage as ourselves. In Utopia, however, they will conduct research by the army corps while we conduct it—we don't conduct it! We let it happen. Fools make researches and wise men exploit them—that is our earthly way of dealing with the question, and we thank Heaven for an assumed abundance of financially impotent and sufficiently ingenious fools.

They will just be starting to fly in Utopia. We owe a lot to M. Santos Dumont; the world is much more inclined to believe that this wonder is coming, and coming soon, than it was five years ago. But unless we assume that Utopian scientific knowledge is far ahead of ours—and while that assumption wasn’t ruled out in our initial discussion, it would be inconvenient for us and not quite in line with the rest of our ideas—they will also be in the same experimental stage as we are. In Utopia, however, they will conduct research by the army corps while we don’t conduct it at all! We let it happen. Fools conduct research and wise men take advantage of it—that is our earthly way of handling the situation, and we thank Heaven for an assumed abundance of financially unproductive yet clever fools.

In Utopia, a great multitude of selected men, chosen volunteers, will be collaborating upon this new step in man's struggle with the elements. Bacon's visionary House of Saloman [Footnote: In The New Atlantis.] will be a thing realised, and it will be humming with this business. Every university in the world will be urgently working for priority in this aspect of the problem or that. Reports of experiments, as full and as prompt as the telegraphic reports of cricket in our more sportive atmosphere, will go about the world. All this will be passing, as it were, behind the act drop of our first experience, behind this first picture of the urbanised Urseren valley. The literature of the subject will be growing and developing with the easy swiftness of an eagle's swoop as we come down the hillside; unseen in that twilight, unthought of by us until this moment, a thousand men at a thousand glowing desks, a busy specialist press, will be perpetually sifting, criticising, condensing, and clearing the ground for further speculation. Those who are concerned with the problems of public locomotion will be following these aeronautic investigations with a keen and enterprising interest, and so will the physiologist and the sociologist. That Utopian research will, I say, go like an eagle's swoop in comparison with the blind-man's fumbling of our terrestrial way. Even before our own brief Utopian journey is out, we may get a glimpse of the swift ripening of all this activity that will be in progress at our coming. To-morrow, perhaps, or in a day or so, some silent, distant thing will come gliding into view over the mountains, will turn and soar and pass again beyond our astonished sight....

In Utopia, a large group of selected individuals, chosen volunteers, will work together on this new stage of humanity's challenge against the elements. Bacon's visionary House of Solomon [Footnote: In The New Atlantis.] will become a reality, buzzing with activity. Every university across the globe will be racing to take the lead on various aspects of the problem. Experiment reports, as detailed and as prompt as the telegraphic updates on cricket in our more playful culture, will circulate worldwide. All this will be happening behind the scenes of our first experience, behind this initial image of the urbanized Urseren valley. The literature on the subject will be expanding and evolving with the swift ease of an eagle's dive as we descend the hillside; hidden in that twilight, unrecognized by us until now, a thousand people at a thousand glowing desks, alongside a busy specialist press, will constantly be analyzing, critiquing, condensing, and paving the way for further exploration. Those focused on public transportation issues will eagerly follow these aviation studies, as will physiologists and sociologists alike. That Utopian research will progress like the swift flight of an eagle compared to our clumsy attempts here on Earth. Even before our brief Utopian journey concludes, we may catch a glimpse of the rapid development of all this activity that will unfold in our future. Tomorrow, perhaps, or in a day or so, something silent and distant will glide into view over the mountains, will turn, soar, and vanish again beyond our astonished sight...

§ 6

But my friend and his great trouble turn my mind from these questions of locomotion and the freedoms that cluster about them. In spite of myself I find myself framing his case. He is a lover, the most conventional of Anglican lovers, with a heart that has had its training, I should think, in the clean but limited schoolroom of Mrs. Henry Wood....

But my friend and his big problems distract me from these thoughts about travel and the freedoms that come with it. Despite my efforts, I can’t help but think about his situation. He is a lover, the most typical of Anglican lovers, with a heart that I believe has been shaped in the neat but narrow classroom of Mrs. Henry Wood....

In Utopia I think they will fly with stronger pinions, it will not be in the superficialities of life merely that movement will be wide and free, they will mount higher and swoop more steeply than he in his cage can believe. What will their range be, their prohibitions? what jars to our preconceptions will he and I receive here?

In Utopia, I believe they will soar with stronger wings; it won't just be in the trivialities of life that their movement will be broad and unrestricted. They will rise higher and dive more sharply than he in his cage can ever imagine. What will their limitations be, their restrictions? What challenges to our expectations will he and I encounter here?

My mind flows with the free, thin flow that it has at the end of an eventful day, and as we walk along in silence towards our inn I rove from issue to issue, I find myself ranging amidst the fundamental things of the individual life and all the perplexity of desires and passions. I turn my questionings to the most difficult of all sets of compromises, those mitigations of spontaneous freedom that constitute the marriage laws, the mystery of balancing justice against the good of the future, amidst these violent and elusive passions. Where falls the balance of freedoms here? I pass for a time from Utopianising altogether, to ask the question that, after all, Schopenhauer failed completely to answer, why sometimes in the case of hurtful, pointless, and destructive things we want so vehemently....

My mind drifts with that light, free feeling it has at the end of a busy day, and as we walk silently toward our inn, I bounce from one thought to another. I find myself exploring the fundamental aspects of individual life and all the confusion of desires and emotions. I direct my questions to the toughest compromises of all—those limitations on our natural freedom that make up the marriage laws, the complicated balance between fairness and what’s best for the future amid these intense and fleeting passions. Where is the balance of freedoms in this situation? I temporarily step away from idealistic thinking to tackle the question that Schopenhauer completely failed to answer: why do we desire hurtful, pointless, and destructive things so passionately at times?

I come back from this unavailing glance into the deeps to the general question of freedoms in this new relation. I find myself far adrift from the case of the Frognal botanist, and asking how far a modern Utopia will deal with personal morals.

I return from this unproductive look into the depths to the broader question of freedoms in this new relationship. I feel completely lost compared to the situation of the Frognal botanist, and I’m wondering how much a modern Utopia will address personal morals.

As Plato demonstrated long ago, the principles of the relation of State control to personal morals may be best discussed in the case of intoxication, the most isolated and least complicated of all this group of problems. But Plato's treatment of this issue as a question of who may or may not have the use of wine, though suitable enough in considering a small State in which everybody was the effectual inspector of everybody, is entirely beside the mark under modern conditions, in which we are to have an extraordinarily higher standard of individual privacy and an amplitude and quantity of migration inconceivable to the Academic imagination. We may accept his principle and put this particular freedom (of the use of wine) among the distinctive privileges of maturity, and still find all that a modern would think of as the Drink Question untouched.

As Plato showed long ago, the relationship between government control and personal morals can be best discussed in terms of intoxication, the simplest and least complicated of these issues. However, Plato's approach to this topic, which focuses on who should or shouldn't use wine, may have made sense in the context of a small state where everyone effectively watches everyone else. But this perspective misses the mark today, where we uphold a much greater standard of individual privacy and experience levels of migration that are unimaginable to Plato's academic view. We can accept his principle and consider this specific freedom (the use of wine) as one of the unique privileges of adulthood, while still leaving the modern Drink Question unaddressed.

That question in Utopia will differ perhaps in the proportion of its factors, but in no other respect, from what it is upon earth. The same desirable ends will be sought, the maintenance of public order and decency, the reduction of inducements to form this bad and wasteful habit to their lowest possible minimum, and the complete protection of the immature. But the modern Utopians, having systematised their sociology, will have given some attention to the psychology of minor officials, a matter altogether too much neglected by the social reformer on earth. They will not put into the hands of a common policeman powers direct and indirect that would be dangerous to the public in the hands of a judge. And they will have avoided the immeasurable error of making their control of the drink traffic a source of public revenue. Privacies they will not invade, but they will certainly restrict the public consumption of intoxicants to specified licensed places and the sale of them to unmistakable adults, and they will make the temptation of the young a grave offence. In so migratory a population as the Modern Utopian, the licensing of inns and bars would be under the same control as the railways and high roads. Inns exist for the stranger and not for the locality, and we shall meet with nothing there to correspond with our terrestrial absurdity of Local Option.

That question in Utopia will likely vary in the proportions of its factors, but in no other way will it differ from what it is on Earth. The same desirable goals will be pursued: maintaining public order and decency, minimizing the incentives to develop these harmful and wasteful habits as much as possible, and fully protecting the young. However, the modern Utopians, having organized their sociology, will pay attention to the psychology of minor officials, something that social reformers on Earth tend to overlook. They won’t give a regular police officer powers—either direct or indirect—that would be risky if given to a judge. They will also avoid the significant mistake of making their control over the alcohol trade a source of public income. They won’t invade private lives, but they will certainly limit the public consumption of alcohol to specific licensed venues and ensure that it’s sold only to clearly identifiable adults, making it a serious offense to tempt the youth. In a population as mobile as the Modern Utopians, the licensing of inns and bars would be controlled in the same way as railways and major roads. Inns are meant for travelers, not for the local community, and we won’t encounter anything resembling our ridiculous Local Option.

The Utopians will certainly control this trade, and as certainly punish personal excesses. Public drunkenness (as distinguished from the mere elation that follows a generous but controlled use of wine) will be an offence against public decency, and will be dealt with in some very drastic manner. It will, of course, be an aggravation of, and not an excuse for, crime.

The Utopians will definitely regulate this trade and will also punish personal excesses. Public drunkenness (unlike the simple joy that comes from moderate wine consumption) will be considered an offense against public decency and will be addressed in a harsh way. It will, of course, be seen as an aggravation, not a justification, for criminal behavior.

But I doubt whether the State will go beyond that. Whether an adult shall use wine or beer or spirits, or not, seems to me entirely a matter for his doctor and his own private conscience. I doubt if we explorers shall meet any drunken men, and I doubt not we shall meet many who have never availed themselves of their adult freedom in this respect. The conditions of physical happiness will be better understood in Utopia, it will be worth while to be well there, and the intelligent citizen will watch himself closely. Half and more of the drunkenness of earth is an attempt to lighten dull days and hopelessly sordid and disagreeable lives, and in Utopia they do not suffer these things. Assuredly Utopia will be temperate, not only drinking, but eating with the soundest discretion. Yet I do not think wine and good ale will be altogether wanting there, nor good, mellow whisky, nor, upon occasion, the engaging various liqueur. I do not think so. My botanist, who abstains altogether, is of another opinion. We differ here and leave the question to the earnest reader. I have the utmost respect for all Teetotalers, Prohibitionists, and Haters and Persecutors of Innkeepers, their energy of reform awakens responsive notes in me, and to their species I look for a large part of the urgent repair of our earth; yet for all that―

But I doubt the State will let things go further than that. Whether an adult chooses to drink wine, beer, or spirits seems to me to be entirely a decision for their doctor and their own personal conscience. I doubt that we explorers will encounter many drunk people, and I’m sure we will meet plenty who have never taken advantage of their adult freedom in this way. The conditions for physical happiness will be better understood in Utopia; it will be worthwhile to be healthy there, and the thoughtful citizen will monitor their behavior closely. A lot of the drunkenness seen on Earth is a way to escape dull days and hopelessly miserable lives, and in Utopia, people don’t experience these issues. Utopia will certainly be moderate, not just in drinking, but also in eating, with careful discretion. However, I don’t think there will be a complete absence of wine and good beer, nor good, smooth whiskey, or occasionally, appealing liqueurs. I believe this. My botanist friend, who totally abstains, disagrees. We part ways on this issue and leave the question open for the thoughtful reader. I have great respect for all teetotalers, prohibitionists, and those who dislike and persecute innkeepers; their reformative energy resonates with me, and I see them as a key part of the necessary healing of our world; yet despite all that―

There is Burgundy, for example, a bottle of soft and kindly Burgundy, taken to make a sunshine on one's lunch when four strenuous hours of toil have left one on the further side of appetite. Or ale, a foaming tankard of ale, ten miles of sturdy tramping in the sleet and slush as a prelude, and then good bread and good butter and a ripe hollow Stilton and celery and ale—ale with a certain quantitative freedom. Or, again, where is the sin in a glass of tawny port three or four times, or it may be five, a year, when the walnuts come round in their season? If you drink no port, then what are walnuts for? Such things I hold for the reward of vast intervals of abstinence; they justify your wide, immaculate margin, which is else a mere unmeaning blankness on the page of palate God has given you! I write of these things as a fleshly man, confessedly and knowingly fleshly, and more than usually aware of my liability to err; I know myself for a gross creature more given to sedentary world-mending than to brisk activities, and not one-tenth as active as the dullest newspaper boy in London. Yet still I have my uses, uses that vanish in monotony, and still I must ask why should we bury the talent of these bright sensations altogether? Under no circumstances can I think of my Utopians maintaining their fine order of life on ginger ale and lemonade and the ale that is Kops'. Those terrible Temperance Drinks, solutions of qualified sugar mixed with vast volumes of gas, as, for example, soda, seltzer, lemonade, and fire-extincteurs hand grenades—minerals, they call such stuff in England—fill a man with wind and self-righteousness. Indeed they do! Coffee destroys brain and kidney, a fact now universally recognised and advertised throughout America; and tea, except for a kind of green tea best used with discretion in punch, tans the entrails and turns honest stomachs into leather bags. Rather would I be Metchnikoffed [Footnote: See The Nature of Man, by Professor Elie Metchnikoff.] at once and have a clean, good stomach of German silver. No! If we are to have no ale in Utopia, give me the one clean temperance drink that is worthy to set beside wine, and that is simple water. Best it is when not quite pure and with a trace of organic matter, for then it tastes and sparkles....

There’s Burgundy, for instance, a bottle of smooth and gentle Burgundy, enjoyed to bring some warmth to your lunch after four exhausting hours of work have left you beyond hungry. Or ale, a frothy tankard of ale, following ten miles of solid walking in the sleet and slush, and then having good bread and good butter with a ripe, hollow Stilton and celery and ale—ale with a certain generous spirit. Or, again, what’s wrong with having a glass of tawny port three or four times, or maybe even five, a year when walnuts are in season? If you don’t drink port, then what’s the point of walnuts? I believe such pleasures are the reward for long stretches of moderation; they validate your wide, pristine margin, which would otherwise just be an empty space on the palate God has gifted you! I write about these things as a flesh-and-blood person, fully aware of my humanity and my tendency to slip up; I recognize I’m quite a corporeal being, more inclined to fix the world while sitting down than to engage in active pursuits, and not even a fraction as energetic as the dullest newspaper boy in London. Yet I still have my purpose, a purpose that fades in monotony, and I wonder why we should completely suppress the joy of these delightful sensations? Under no circumstances can I imagine my Utopians sustaining their refined way of life on ginger ale and lemonade and Kops’ ale. Those dreadful Temperance Drinks, solutions of flavored sugar mixed with vast amounts of fizz, like soda, seltzer, lemonade, and fire-extinguishers hand grenades—minerals, they call this stuff in England—fill a person with gas and self-righteousness. Indeed they do! Coffee damages brain and kidneys, a fact now widely recognized and advertised across America; and tea, unless it’s a kind of green tea best used sparingly in punch, toughens the insides and turns honest stomachs into leather bags. I’d rather be Metchnikoffed [Footnote: See The Nature of Man, by Professor Elie Metchnikoff.] right away and have a pristine, good stomach made of German silver. No! If we can't have ale in Utopia, give me the one clean temperance drink that’s worthy to stand alongside wine, and that’s simple water. It’s best when not completely pure and has a hint of organic matter, because then it has flavor and sparkle...

My botanist would still argue.

My botanist would still dispute.

Thank Heaven this is my book, and that the ultimate decision rests with me. It is open to him to write his own Utopia and arrange that everybody shall do nothing except by the consent of the savants of the Republic, either in his eating, drinking, dressing or lodging, even as Cabet proposed. It is open to him to try a News from Nowhere Utopia with the wine left out. I have my short way with him here quite effectually. I turn in the entrance of our inn to the civil but by no means obsequious landlord, and with a careful ambiguity of manner for the thing may be considered an outrage, and I try to make it possible the idea is a jest—put my test demand....

Thank goodness this is my book, and the final choice is mine. He can create his own perfect society and dictate that everyone can only act with the approval of the experts in the Republic, whether it’s about what they eat, drink, wear, or where they live, just like Cabet suggested. He can attempt a News from Nowhere style utopia without the wine. I have an effective way to deal with him here. I turn to the polite but not overly servile landlord at our inn, and with a careful hint of ambiguity in my manner—since this could be seen as disrespectful—I try to suggest that my request is a joke and put forward my test demand....

“You see, my dear Teetotaler?—he sets before me tray and glass and...” Here follows the necessary experiment and a deep sigh.... “Yes, a bottle of quite excellent light beer! So there are also cakes and ale in Utopia! Let us in this saner and more beautiful world drink perdition to all earthly excesses. Let us drink more particularly to the coming of the day when men beyond there will learn to distinguish between qualitative and quantitative questions, to temper good intentions with good intelligence, and righteousness with wisdom. One of the darkest evils of our world is surely the unteachable wildness of the Good.”

“You see, my dear Teetotaler?—he places a tray and glass in front of me and...” Here comes the necessary experiment and a deep sigh.... “Yes, a bottle of truly excellent light beer! So there are actually cakes and ale in Utopia! Let’s raise a glass in this clearer and more beautiful world to condemning all earthly excesses. Let’s specifically toast to the day when people over there will learn to tell the difference between quality and quantity, to balance good intentions with good sense, and righteousness with wisdom. One of the darkest problems in our world is definitely the unteachable wildness of the Good.”

§ 7

So presently to bed and to sleep, but not at once to sleep. At first my brain, like a dog in unfamiliar quarters, must turn itself round for a time or so before it lies down. This strange mystery of a world of which I have seen so little as yet—a mountain slope, a twilit road, a traffic of ambiguous vehicles and dim shapes, the window lights of many homes—fills me with curiosities. Figures and incidents come and go, the people we have passed, our landlord, quietly attentive and yet, I feel, with the keenest curiosity peeping from his eyes, the unfamiliar forms of the house parts and furnishings, the unfamiliar courses of the meal. Outside this little bedroom is a world, a whole unimagined world. A thousand million things lie outside in the darkness beyond this lit inn of ours, unthought-of possibilities, overlooked considerations, surprises, riddles, incommensurables, a whole monstrous intricate universe of consequences that I have to do my best to unravel. I attempt impossible recapitulations and mingle the weird quality of dream stuff with my thoughts.

So now to bed and to sleep, but not right away. At first, my mind, like a dog in a strange place, needs to take some time to settle down before it can rest. This strange mystery of a world, which I've seen so little of so far—a mountain slope, a dimly lit road, a mix of unusual vehicles and shadowy shapes, the lights from many homes—fills me with curiosity. People and events come and go: the faces we’ve passed, our landlord, who seems quietly attentive but I sense has a keen curiosity peeking from his eyes, the unfamiliar shapes of the furniture and the new ways we’ve eaten our meals. Just outside this small bedroom is a world, an entire unimagined world. A million things are out there in the darkness beyond our cozy inn, with countless possibilities, overlooked details, surprises, puzzles, and a vast, complex universe of consequences that I need to try to make sense of. I attempt impossible rewinds and mix the strange quality of dreams with my thoughts.

Athwart all this tumult of my memory goes this queer figure of my unanticipated companion, so obsessed by himself and his own egotistical love that this sudden change to another world seems only a change of scene for his gnawing, uninvigorating passion. It occurs to me that she also must have an equivalent in Utopia, and then that idea and all ideas grow thin and vague, and are dissolved at last in the rising tide of sleep....

Amid all this chaos in my mind, there's this strange figure of my unexpected companion, so consumed by himself and his selfish love that this abrupt shift to another world feels just like a change of scenery for his draining, unfulfilling passion. It strikes me that she must also have someone similar in Utopia, but then that thought and all others fade away, eventually dissolving in the rising tide of sleep....

CHAPTER THE THIRD
Utopian Economics

§ 1

These modern Utopians with the universally diffused good manners, the universal education, the fine freedoms we shall ascribe to them, their world unity, world language, world-wide travellings, world-wide freedom of sale and purchase, will remain mere dreamstuff, incredible even by twilight, until we have shown that at that level the community will still sustain itself. At any rate, the common liberty of the Utopians will not embrace the common liberty to be unserviceable, the most perfect economy of organisation still leaves the fact untouched that all order and security in a State rests on the certainty of getting work done. How will the work of this planet be done? What will be the economics of a modern Utopia?

These modern Utopians, with their widely shared good manners, universal education, and the wonderful freedoms we attribute to them—like global unity, a common language, international travel, and free trade—will remain nothing more than a dream, unbelievable even at dusk, unless we prove that the community can still support itself at that level. In any case, the shared liberty of the Utopians won't include the freedom to be unproductive; even the best organizational economy doesn't change the fact that all order and security in a state relies on the assurance that work gets done. How will the work of this planet be accomplished? What will the economy of a modern Utopia look like?

Now in the first place, a state so vast and complex as this world Utopia, and with so migratory a people, will need some handy symbol to check the distribution of services and commodities. Almost certainly they will need to have money. They will have money, and it is not inconceivable that, for all his sorrowful thoughts, our botanist, with his trained observation, his habit of looking at little things upon the ground, would be the one to see and pick up the coin that has fallen from some wayfarer's pocket. (This, in our first hour or so before we reach the inn in the Urseren Thal.) You figure us upon the high Gotthard road, heads together over the little disk that contrives to tell us so much of this strange world.

Now, first of all, a state as vast and complex as this world Utopia, combined with such a constantly moving population, will need a practical symbol to manage the distribution of services and goods. They will definitely need money. They will have money, and it’s not hard to imagine that, despite his heavy thoughts, our botanist, with his sharp observations and tendency to focus on the small details around him, would be the one to notice and pick up the coin that has fallen from a traveler's pocket. (This happens in our first hour or so before we reach the inn in the Urseren Thal.) Picture us on the high Gotthard road, leaning in together over the little coin that manages to reveal so much about this strange world.

It is, I imagine, of gold, and it will be a convenient accident if it is sufficient to make us solvent for a day or so, until we are a little more informed of the economic system into which we have come. It is, moreover, of a fair round size, and the inscription declares it one Lion, equal to “twaindy” bronze Crosses. Unless the ratio of metals is very different here, this latter must be a token coin, and therefore legal tender for but a small amount. (That would be pain and pleasure to Mr. Wordsworth Donisthorpe if he were to chance to join us, for once he planned a Utopian coinage, [Footnote: A System of Measures, by Wordsworth Donisthorpe.] and the words Lion and Cross are his. But a token coinage and “legal tender” he cannot abide. They make him argue.) And being in Utopia, that unfamiliar “twaindy” suggests at once we have come upon that most Utopian of all things, a duodecimal system of counting.

I imagine it’s made of gold, and it’ll be a lucky break if it’s enough to keep us afloat for a day or two while we learn more about the economic system we’ve entered. It’s also a nice round size, and the inscription says it’s one Lion, equal to “twaindy” bronze Crosses. Unless the metal ratios are very different here, the latter must be a token coin, so it’s only good for small amounts. (That would be both a pain and a pleasure for Mr. Wordsworth Donisthorpe if he happens to join us, because he once designed a Utopian currency, [Footnote: A System of Measures, by Wordsworth Donisthorpe.] and the terms Lion and Cross are his. But he can’t stand token currency and “legal tender.” They make him argue.) And being in Utopia, that unfamiliar “twaindy” immediately suggests we’ve stumbled upon one of the most Utopian concepts of all, a duodecimal counting system.

My author's privilege of details serves me here. This Lion is distinctly a beautiful coin, admirably made, with its value in fine, clear letters circling the obverse side, and a head thereon—of Newton, as I live! One detects American influence here. Each year, as we shall find, each denomination of coins celebrates a centenary. The reverse shows the universal goddess of the Utopian coinage—Peace, as a beautiful woman, reading with a child out of a great book, and behind them are stars, and an hour-glass, halfway run. Very human these Utopians, after all, and not by any means above the obvious in their symbolism!

My author's knack for details comes into play here. This Lion is clearly a beautiful coin, expertly made, with its value in bold, clear letters around the front, and a portrait of none other than Newton! You can definitely see American influence in this. Each year, as we will see, every type of coin marks a hundred years. The back features the universal goddess of the Utopian coins—Peace, depicted as a lovely woman reading with a child from a large book, and behind them are stars and an hourglass, halfway through. These Utopians are very relatable, after all, and definitely not shy about their symbolism!

So for the first time we learn definitely of the World State, and we get our first clear hint, too, that there is an end to Kings. But our coin raises other issues also. It would seem that this Utopia has no simple community of goods, that there is, at any rate, a restriction upon what one may take, a need for evidences of equivalent value, a limitation to human credit.

So, for the first time, we definitely learn about the World State, and we also get our first clear indication that kings are no more. However, our currency brings up other concerns as well. It appears that this Utopia doesn't have a straightforward sharing of goods; there seems to be a limitation on what one can take, a requirement for proof of equivalent value, and a restriction on human credit.

It dates—so much of this present Utopia of ours dates. Those former Utopists were bitterly against gold. You will recall the undignified use Sir Thomas More would have us put it to, and how there was no money at all in the Republic of Plato, and in that later community for which he wrote his Laws an iron coinage of austere appearance and doubtful efficacy.... It may be these great gentlemen were a little hasty with a complicated difficulty, and not a little unjust to a highly respectable element.

It dates—so much of our current Utopia dates back. Those earlier Utopians were strongly opposed to gold. You might remember how Sir Thomas More wanted us to use it in an undignified way, and how there was no money at all in Plato's Republic, while in that later society he described in his Laws, there was an iron currency that looked harsh and was questionable in its effectiveness.... Perhaps these great thinkers were a bit too quick to judge a complex issue and somewhat unfair to a very respectable component.

Gold is abused and made into vessels of dishonour, and abolished from ideal society as though it were the cause instead of the instrument of human baseness; but, indeed, there is nothing bad in gold. Making gold into vessels of dishonour and banishing it from the State is punishing the hatchet for the murderer's crime. Money, did you but use it right, is a good thing in life, a necessary thing in civilised human life, as complicated, indeed, for its purposes, but as natural a growth as the bones in a man's wrist, and I do not see how one can imagine anything at all worthy of being called a civilisation without it. It is the water of the body social, it distributes and receives, and renders growth and assimilation and movement and recovery possible. It is the reconciliation of human interdependence with liberty. What other device will give a man so great a freedom with so strong an inducement to effort? The economic history of the world, where it is not the history of the theory of property, is very largely the record of the abuse, not so much of money as of credit devices to supplement money, to amplify the scope of this most precious invention; and no device of labour credits [Footnote: Edward Bellamy's Looking Backward, Ch. IX.] or free demand of commodities from a central store [Footnote: More's Utopia and Cabet's Icaria.] or the like has ever been suggested that does not give ten thousand times more scope for that inherent moral dross in man that must be reckoned with in any sane Utopia we may design and plan.... Heaven knows where progress may not end, but at any rate this developing State, into which we two men have fallen, this Twentieth Century Utopia, has still not passed beyond money and the use of coins.

Gold is misused and turned into objects of shame, and it's removed from ideal society as if it were the cause of human wrongdoing rather than just a tool; but, in reality, there's nothing wrong with gold. Turning gold into vessels of dishonor and banishing it from the State is like blaming the hatchet for the murderer's crime. Money, when used properly, is a good thing in life, a necessary part of civilized society—it's as complex for its purposes as the bones in a person's wrist, yet just as natural. I don't see how you can imagine anything worthy of being called a civilization without it. It functions like the lifeblood of society, distributing and receiving resources, enabling growth, adaptation, movement, and recovery. It harmonizes human interdependence with freedom. What other tool can offer a person such freedom while also strongly motivating them to put in effort? The economic history of the world, aside from the theory of property, largely records the misuse of not just money but also credit methods to enhance the power of this invaluable invention; and no system of labor credits or free demand for goods from a central store has ever been proposed that doesn't amplify the fundamental moral issues within humanity that need addressing in any realistic Utopia we might create.... Who knows where progress may lead, but at least this evolving State we've entered, this Twentieth Century Utopia, still relies on money and the use of coins.

§ 2

Now if this Utopian world is to be in some degree parallel to contemporary thought, it must have been concerned, it may be still concerned, with many unsettled problems of currency, and with the problems that centre about a standard of value. Gold is perhaps of all material substances the best adapted to the monetary purpose, but even at that best it falls far short of an imaginable ideal. It undergoes spasmodic and irregular cheapening through new discoveries of gold, and at any time it may undergo very extensive and sudden and disastrous depreciation through the discovery of some way of transmuting less valuable elements. The liability to such depreciations introduces an undesirable speculative element into the relations of debtor and creditor. When, on the one hand, there is for a time a check in the increase of the available stores of gold, or an increase in the energy applied to social purposes, or a checking of the public security that would impede the free exchange of credit and necessitate a more frequent production of gold in evidence, then there comes an undue appreciation of money as against the general commodities of life, and an automatic impoverishment of the citizens in general as against the creditor class. The common people are mortgaged into the bondage of debt. And on the other hand an unexpected spate of gold production, the discovery of a single nugget as big as St. Paul's, let us say—a quite possible thing—would result in a sort of jail delivery of debtors and a financial earthquake.

Now, if this Utopian world is meant to align somewhat with modern ideas, it must deal with many ongoing issues related to currency and the challenges surrounding a standard of value. Gold is arguably the most suitable material for money, but even at its best, it doesn’t match an ideal scenario. It experiences sudden and unpredictable devaluations due to new gold discoveries, and at any moment, it could face significant and abrupt drops in value if a method to transform less valuable materials is found. This risk of devaluation adds an undesirable speculative aspect to the relationships between debtors and creditors. When, for example, there is a temporary halt in the growth of gold reserves, or when there’s an increase in efforts directed toward social needs, or a decline in public security that hinders the smooth exchange of credit and calls for more frequent gold production for backing, this leads to an excessive increase in money’s value compared to everyday goods, causing a systematic impoverishment of the general population relative to creditors. The average citizens find themselves trapped in debt. Conversely, an unexpected surge in gold production, like the discovery of a nugget the size of St. Paul's, which is entirely possible, could result in a massive release of debtors from their obligations and trigger a financial upheaval.

It has been suggested by an ingenious thinker that it is possible to use as a standard of monetary value no substance whatever, but instead, force, and that value might be measured in units of energy. An excellent development this, in theory, at any rate, of the general idea of the modern State as kinetic and not static; it throws the old idea of the social order and the new into the sharpest antithesis. The old order is presented as a system of institutions and classes ruled by men of substance; the new, of enterprises and interests led by men of power.

An insightful thinker has suggested that we don't need to use any physical substance as a standard for monetary value; instead, we could use force, measuring value in units of energy. This is an interesting development, in theory, that reflects the modern idea of the State being dynamic rather than static; it sharply contrasts the old and new concepts of social order. The old order is seen as a system of institutions and classes governed by wealthy individuals, while the new order focuses on businesses and interests led by those in power.

Now I glance at this matter in the most incidental manner, as a man may skim through a specialist's exposition in a popular magazine. You must figure me, therefore, finding from a casual periodical paper in our inn, with a certain surprise at not having anticipated as much, the Utopian self of that same ingenious person quite conspicuously a leader of thought, and engaged in organising the discussion of the currency changes Utopia has under consideration. The article, as it presents itself to me, contains a complete and lucid, though occasionally rather technical, explanation of his newest proposals. They have been published, it seems, for general criticism, and one gathers that in the modern Utopia the administration presents the most elaborately detailed schemes of any proposed alteration in law or custom, some time before any measure is taken to carry it into effect, and the possibilities of every detail are acutely criticised, flaws anticipated, side issues raised, and the whole minutely tested and fined down by a planetful of critics, before the actual process of legislation begins.

Now I see this issue in a very casual way, like someone skimming through a specialist's article in a popular magazine. So, picture me discovering, from a random article in our inn, with some surprise at having not seen this coming, that the visionary self of that clever person is clearly a thought leader, actively organizing a discussion about the currency changes that Utopia is considering. The article, as it appears to me, provides a complete and clear, though sometimes a bit technical, explanation of his latest proposals. They’ve been published, it seems, for public feedback, and it becomes clear that in this modern Utopia, the administration lays out the most thoroughly detailed plans for any proposed changes in law or custom well before any actions are taken to implement them. Each potential detail is sharply critiqued, flaws are anticipated, related issues are raised, and everything is meticulously examined and refined by an army of critics before the actual legislative process kicks off.

The explanation of these proposals involves an anticipatory glance at the local administration of a Modern Utopia. To anyone who has watched the development of technical science during the last decade or so, there will be no shock in the idea that a general consolidation of a great number of common public services over areas of considerable size is now not only practicable, but very desirable. In a little while heating and lighting and the supply of power for domestic and industrial purposes and for urban and inter-urban communications will all be managed electrically from common generating stations. And the trend of political and social speculation points decidedly to the conclusion that so soon as it passes out of the experimental stage, the supply of electrical energy, just like drainage and the supply of water, will fall to the local authority. Moreover, the local authority will be the universal landowner. Upon that point so extreme an individualist as Herbert Spencer was in agreement with the Socialist. In Utopia we conclude that, whatever other types of property may exist, all natural sources of force, and indeed all strictly natural products, coal, water power, and the like, are inalienably vested in the local authorities (which, in order to secure the maximum of convenience and administrative efficiency, will probably control areas as large sometimes as half England), they will generate electricity by water power, by combustion, by wind or tide or whatever other natural force is available, and this electricity will be devoted, some of it to the authority's lighting and other public works, some of it, as a subsidy, to the World-State authority which controls the high roads, the great railways, the inns and other apparatus of world communication, and the rest will pass on to private individuals or to distributing companies at a uniform fixed rate for private lighting and heating, for machinery and industrial applications of all sorts. Such an arrangement of affairs will necessarily involve a vast amount of book-keeping between the various authorities, the World-State government and the customers, and this book-keeping will naturally be done most conveniently in units of physical energy.

The explanation of these proposals looks ahead to how local administration would work in a Modern Utopia. For anyone who has observed the growth of technology over the past decade, it’s not surprising to think that merging many public services across large areas is both possible and very beneficial. Soon, heating, lighting, and the supply of power for homes, businesses, and urban and inter-urban transit will all be managed electrically from shared power plants. The trend in political and social thought strongly suggests that once it moves beyond the experimental phase, supplying electrical energy, similar to drainage and water supply, will fall to local authorities. Additionally, the local authority will become the primary landowner. In this regard, even a staunch individualist like Herbert Spencer agreed with Socialists. In our Utopia, we conclude that while other kinds of property might exist, all natural energy sources, including coal, water power, and similar resources, will be permanently held by local authorities (which will likely manage areas as large as half of England for maximum convenience and administrative efficiency). They will produce electricity using water power, combustion, wind, tide, or any other available natural resource, and this electricity will be used: some for the authority’s lighting and public infrastructure, some as a subsidy for the World-State authority that oversees highways, major railways, inns, and other communication networks, and the remainder will be sold to private individuals or distribution companies at a steady fixed rate for personal lighting, heating, and all sorts of industrial uses. This system will inevitably require a significant amount of record-keeping between the different authorities, the World-State government, and the customers, and naturally, this bookkeeping will be most efficiently done in units of physical energy.

It is not incredible that the assessment of the various local administrations for the central world government would be already calculated upon the estimated total of energy, periodically available in each locality, and booked and spoken of in these physical units. Accounts between central and local governments could be kept in these terms. Moreover, one may imagine Utopian local authorities making contracts in which payment would be no longer in coinage upon the gold basis, but in notes good for so many thousands or millions of units of energy at one or other of the generating stations.

It's not surprising that the evaluation of different local governments by the central world government would already be based on the estimated total amount of energy available in each area, measured and discussed in these physical units. Financial transactions between the central and local governments could be recorded in these terms. Additionally, one can envision ideal local authorities creating agreements where payment wouldn't rely on coinage based on gold, but in notes valid for a certain number of thousands or millions of units of energy at various generating stations.

Now the problems of economic theory will have undergone an enormous clarification if, instead of measuring in fluctuating money values, the same scale of energy units can be extended to their discussion, if, in fact, the idea of trading could be entirely eliminated. In my Utopia, at any rate, this has been done, the production and distribution of common commodities have been expressed as a problem in the conversion of energy, and the scheme that Utopia was now discussing was the application of this idea of energy as the standard of value to the entire Utopian coinage. Every one of those giant local authorities was to be free to issue energy notes against the security of its surplus of saleable available energy, and to make all its contracts for payment in those notes up to a certain maximum defined by the amount of energy produced and disposed of in that locality in the previous year. This power of issue was to be renewed just as rapidly as the notes came in for redemption. In a world without boundaries, with a population largely migratory and emancipated from locality, the price of the energy notes of these various local bodies would constantly tend to be uniform, because employment would constantly shift into the areas where energy was cheap. Accordingly, the price of so many millions of units of energy at any particular moment in coins of the gold currency would be approximately the same throughout the world. It was proposed to select some particular day when the economic atmosphere was distinctly equable, and to declare a fixed ratio between the gold coinage and the energy notes; each gold Lion and each Lion of credit representing exactly the number of energy units it could buy on that day. The old gold coinage was at once to cease to be legal tender beyond certain defined limits, except to the central government, which would not reissue it as it came in. It was, in fact, to become a temporary token coinage, a token coinage of full value for the day of conversion at any rate, if not afterwards, under the new standard of energy, and to be replaceable by an ordinary token coinage as time went on. The old computation by Lions and the values of the small change of daily life were therefore to suffer no disturbance whatever.

Now the issues in economic theory would be greatly clarified if we could discuss them using a consistent measurement of energy units instead of changing money values, essentially eliminating the concept of trading. In my Utopia, this has been achieved; the production and distribution of everyday goods are framed as a problem of energy conversion, and the plan that Utopia is currently exploring involves using energy as the standard of value for all currency. Each of those major local authorities would be able to issue energy notes backed by their surplus of saleable energy, making payment contracts in those notes up to a maximum based on the energy produced and sold in that area in the previous year. This ability to issue notes would be renewed as the notes were redeemed. In a world without borders, where the population is largely mobile and free from local ties, the value of these energy notes from different local authorities would generally remain the same, since jobs would shift to regions with cheaper energy. Therefore, the value of millions of energy units at any given time in gold currency would be approximately equal worldwide. It was suggested to pick a specific day when the economic climate was notably stable and establish a fixed exchange rate between the gold currency and the energy notes; each gold Lion and each Lion of credit would equal exactly the number of energy units it could purchase that day. The old gold currency would immediately stop being legal tender beyond certain limits, except for the central government, which wouldn’t reissue it as it came back in. Essentially, it would become a temporary currency, fully valuable for the day of conversion, and eventually replaced by a standard token currency as time passed. The old system of Lions and the values of everyday change would therefore remain completely unaffected.

The economists of Utopia, as I apprehended them, had a different method and a very different system of theories from those I have read on earth, and this makes my exposition considerably more difficult. This article upon which I base my account floated before me in an unfamiliar, perplexing, and dream-like phraseology. Yet I brought away an impression that here was a rightness that earthly economists have failed to grasp. Few earthly economists have been able to disentangle themselves from patriotisms and politics, and their obsession has always been international trade. Here in Utopia the World State cuts that away from beneath their feet; there are no imports but meteorites, and no exports at all. Trading is the earthly economists' initial notion, and they start from perplexing and insoluble riddles about exchange value, insoluble because all trading finally involves individual preferences which are incalculable and unique. Nowhere do they seem to be handling really defined standards, every economic dissertation and discussion reminds one more strongly than the last of the game of croquet Alice played in Wonderland, when the mallets were flamingoes and the balls were hedgehogs and crawled away, and the hoops were soldiers and kept getting up and walking about. But economics in Utopia must be, it seems to me, not a theory of trading based on bad psychology, but physics applied to problems in the theory of sociology. The general problem of Utopian economics is to state the conditions of the most efficient application of the steadily increasing quantities of material energy the progress of science makes available for human service, to the general needs of mankind. Human labour and existing material are dealt with in relation to that. Trading and relative wealth are merely episodical in such a scheme. The trend of the article I read, as I understood it, was that a monetary system based upon a relatively small amount of gold, upon which the business of the whole world had hitherto been done, fluctuated unreasonably and supplied no real criterion of well-being, that the nominal values of things and enterprises had no clear and simple relation to the real physical prosperity of the community, that the nominal wealth of a community in millions of pounds or dollars or Lions, measured nothing but the quantity of hope in the air, and an increase of confidence meant an inflation of credit and a pessimistic phase a collapse of this hallucination of possessions. The new standards, this advocate reasoned, were to alter all that, and it seemed to me they would.

The economists of Utopia, as I understood them, had a different approach and a completely different set of theories from those I’ve seen on Earth, which makes my explanation much more challenging. This article I’m using for my account was filled with unfamiliar, confusing, and dream-like language. Yet I came away with the impression that there was something right here that earthly economists have overlooked. Few economists on Earth can detach themselves from national loyalties and politics, and they are always focused on international trade. In Utopia, the World State removes that foundation; there are no imports except meteorites, and no exports at all. Trading is the foundational concept for earthly economists, who grapple with complicated and unsolvable problems about exchange value, which are unsolvable because all trading ultimately hinges on individual preferences that are unpredictable and unique. They don't seem to work with clearly defined standards; every economic essay and discussion increasingly resembles the surreal game of croquet that Alice played in Wonderland, where the mallets were flamingos, the balls were hedgehogs that wandered off, and the hoops were soldiers who kept getting up and moving around. However, economics in Utopia should not be a flawed trading theory rooted in poor psychology, but rather a form of physics applied to sociological issues. The core challenge of Utopian economics is to outline the conditions for the most efficient use of the continually increasing amounts of material energy that scientific progress makes available for the benefit of humanity, addressing general human needs. Human labor and available materials are considered within that context. Trading and relative wealth are just minor aspects of this framework. As I understood it, the article I read suggested that a monetary system based on a relatively small amount of gold, which had previously underpinned global business, was erratic and provided no real measure of well-being. It argued that the nominal values of goods and businesses had no clear or straightforward connection to the true physical prosperity of the community, that a community’s nominal wealth in millions of pounds, dollars, or other currencies measured only the level of hope in the atmosphere, and that an increase in confidence led to inflated credit, while a pessimistic phase meant a collapse of this illusion of ownership. The proposed new standards, this advocate argued, were set to change all that, and I believed they would.

I have tried to indicate the drift of these remarkable proposals, but about them clustered an elaborate mass of keen and temperate discussion. Into the details of that discussion I will not enter now, nor am I sure I am qualified to render the multitudinous aspect of this complicated question at all precisely. I read the whole thing in the course of an hour or two of rest after lunch—it was either the second or third day of my stay in Utopia—and we were sitting in a little inn at the end of the Lake of Uri. We had loitered there, and I had fallen reading because of a shower of rain.... But certainly as I read it the proposition struck me as a singularly simple and attractive one, and its exposition opened out to me for the first time clearly, in a comprehensive outline, the general conception of the economic nature of the Utopian State.

I’ve tried to show the main ideas behind these remarkable proposals, but they were surrounded by a complex mix of thoughtful and respectful discussion. I won’t get into the details of that discussion right now, nor am I sure I can accurately capture the many angles of this complicated issue. I read the whole thing in an hour or two of relaxing after lunch—it was either the second or third day of my stay in Utopia—and we were at a small inn by the Lake of Uri. We had been lingering there, and I started reading because of a rain shower.... But as I read, the proposal struck me as uniquely simple and appealing, and its explanation for the first time clearly laid out for me the overall idea of the economic structure of the Utopian State.

§ 3

The difference between the social and economic sciences as they exist in our world [Footnote: But see Gidding's Principles of Sociology, a modern and richly suggestive American work, imperfectly appreciated by the British student. See also Walter Bagehot's Economic Studies.] and in this Utopia deserves perhaps a word or so more. I write with the utmost diffidence, because upon earth economic science has been raised to a very high level of tortuous abstraction by the industry of its professors, and I can claim neither a patient student's intimacy with their productions nor—what is more serious—anything but the most generalised knowledge of what their Utopian equivalents have achieved. The vital nature of economic issues to a Utopia necessitates, however, some attempt at interpretation between the two.

The difference between the social and economic sciences as they exist in our world [Footnote: But see Gidding's Principles of Sociology, a modern and thought-provoking American work, which is not fully appreciated by British students. See also Walter Bagehot's Economic Studies.] and in this Utopia deserves a bit more discussion. I'm writing this with a lot of hesitation, because in our world, economic science has become very complex and abstract due to the efforts of its scholars. I don't have the in-depth knowledge that a dedicated student would have of their work, nor—more importantly—anything more than a very basic understanding of what their Utopian counterparts have accomplished. However, the critical nature of economic issues in a Utopia requires some effort to compare the two.

In Utopia there is no distinct and separate science of economics. Many problems that we should regard as economic come within the scope of Utopian psychology. My Utopians make two divisions of the science of psychology, first, the general psychology of individuals, a sort of mental physiology separated by no definite line from physiology proper, and secondly, the psychology of relationship between individuals. This second is an exhaustive study of the reaction of people upon each other and of all possible relationships. It is a science of human aggregations, of all possible family groupings, of neighbours and neighbourhood, of companies, associations, unions, secret and public societies, religious groupings, of common ends and intercourse, and of the methods of intercourse and collective decision that hold human groups together, and finally of government and the State. The elucidation of economic relationships, depending as it does on the nature of the hypothesis of human aggregation actually in operation at any time, is considered to be subordinate and subsequent to this general science of Sociology. Political economy and economics, in our world now, consist of a hopeless muddle of social assumptions and preposterous psychology, and a few geographical and physical generalisations. Its ingredients will be classified out and widely separated in Utopian thought. On the one hand there will be the study of physical economies, ending in the descriptive treatment of society as an organisation for the conversion of all the available energy in nature to the material ends of mankind—a physical sociology which will be already at such a stage of practical development as to be giving the world this token coinage representing energy—and on the other there will be the study of economic problems as problems in the division of labour, having regard to a social organisation whose main ends are reproduction and education in an atmosphere of personal freedom. Each of these inquiries, working unencumbered by the other, will be continually contributing fresh valid conclusions for the use of the practical administrator.

In Utopia, there isn't a separate and distinct field of economics. Many issues we would consider economic fall under Utopian psychology. My Utopians divide psychology into two areas: first, the general psychology of individuals, a kind of mental physiology that has no clear boundary with physical physiology; and second, the psychology of relationships between individuals. This second area thoroughly examines how people react to each other and all possible types of relationships. It's a science of human groups, encompassing all kinds of family structures, neighbors and neighborhoods, companies, associations, unions, secret and public societies, religious groups, shared goals and interactions, as well as the methods of communication and collective decision-making that hold human groups together, ultimately including government and the State. The exploration of economic relationships, which depends on the nature of the human aggregation currently in operation, is seen as secondary to this broader field of Sociology. Political economy and economics today consist of a confusing mix of social assumptions, dubious psychology, and some geographical and physical generalizations. In Utopian thought, these components will be clearly identified and distinctly separated. On one side, there will be the study of physical economies, culminating in the descriptive analysis of society as an organization that converts all available natural energy into material benefits for humanity—creating a physical sociology that will already be advanced enough to provide the world with a form of currency representing energy. On the other side, there will be the examination of economic issues as related to the division of labor, focusing on a social organization whose primary goals are reproduction and education in a context of personal freedom. Each of these studies, operating independently, will continuously yield new and valid insights for practical administrators to use.

In no region of intellectual activity will our hypothesis of freedom from tradition be of more value in devising a Utopia than here. From its beginning the earthly study of economics has been infertile and unhelpful, because of the mass of unanalysed and scarcely suspected assumptions upon which it rested. The facts were ignored that trade is a bye-product and not an essential factor in social life, that property is a plastic and fluctuating convention, that value is capable of impersonal treatment only in the case of the most generalised requirements. Wealth was measured by the standards of exchange. Society was regarded as a practically unlimited number of avaricious adult units incapable of any other subordinate groupings than business partnerships, and the sources of competition were assumed to be inexhaustible. Upon such quicksands rose an edifice that aped the securities of material science, developed a technical jargon and professed the discovery of “laws.” Our liberation from these false presumptions through the rhetoric of Carlyle and Ruskin and the activities of the Socialists, is more apparent than real. The old edifice oppresses us still, repaired and altered by indifferent builders, underpinned in places, and with a slight change of name. “Political Economy” has been painted out, and instead we read “Economics—under entirely new management.” Modern Economics differs mainly from old Political Economy in having produced no Adam Smith. The old “Political Economy” made certain generalisations, and they were mostly wrong; new Economics evades generalisations, and seems to lack the intellectual power to make them. The science hangs like a gathering fog in a valley, a fog which begins nowhere and goes nowhere, an incidental, unmeaning inconvenience to passers-by. Its most typical exponents display a disposition to disavow generalisations altogether, to claim consideration as “experts,” and to make immediate political application of that conceded claim. Now Newton, Darwin, Dalton, Davy, Joule, and Adam Smith did not affect this “expert” hankey-pankey, becoming enough in a hairdresser or a fashionable physician, but indecent in a philosopher or a man of science. In this state of impotent expertness, however, or in some equally unsound state, economics must struggle on—a science that is no science, a floundering lore wallowing in a mud of statistics—until either the study of the material organisation of production on the one hand as a development of physics and geography, or the study of social aggregation on the other, renders enduring foundations possible.

In no area of intellectual activity will our idea of freedom from tradition be more valuable in creating a Utopia than here. Since the beginning, the study of economics has been unproductive and unhelpful due to the countless unexamined and barely recognized assumptions it relies on. It ignored that trade is a byproduct and not a key element of social life, that property is a flexible and changing convention, and that value can only be treated impersonally in the case of very generalized needs. Wealth was measured by exchange standards. Society was seen as a practically unlimited number of greedy individual units unable to form any other subordinate groupings than business partnerships, and competition was assumed to be endless. On such unstable ground, a structure emerged that mimicked the certainties of material science, developed a technical jargon, and claimed to have discovered “laws.” Our liberation from these false assumptions through the writings of Carlyle and Ruskin and the actions of Socialists is more superficial than real. The old structure still oppresses us, repaired and altered by careless builders, supported in some places, but with just a slight name change. “Political Economy” has been erased, and now we see “Economics—under entirely new management.” Modern Economics differs mainly from old Political Economy in that it hasn't produced an Adam Smith. The old “Political Economy” made some generalizations, and most of them were wrong; new Economics avoids generalizations and seems to lack the intellectual power to make them. The science hangs like a thick fog in a valley, a fog that begins nowhere and ends nowhere, a trivial inconvenience to passersby. Its most typical representatives tend to completely reject generalizations, claiming status as “experts,” and making immediate political applications of that accepted status. Newton, Darwin, Dalton, Davy, Joule, and Adam Smith did not engage in this “expert” nonsense; it's acceptable in a hairdresser or a trendy doctor, but inappropriate in a philosopher or scientist. In this state of ineffective expertise, or some similarly flawed situation, economics must continue to struggle—being a science that isn't a science, a struggling body of knowledge mired in statistics—until either the examination of the material organization of production as an extension of physics and geography, or the study of social aggregation, makes lasting foundations possible.

§ 4

The older Utopias were all relatively small states; Plato's Republic, for example, was to be smaller than the average English borough, and no distinction was made between the Family, the Local Government, and the State. Plato and Campanella—for all that the latter was a Christian priest—carried communism to its final point and prescribed even a community of husbands and wives, an idea that was brought at last to the test of effectual experiment in the Oneida Community of New York State (1848-1879). This latter body did not long survive its founder, at least as a veritable communism, by reason of the insurgent individualism of its vigorous sons. More, too, denied privacy and ruled an absolute community of goods, at any rate, and so, coming to the Victorian Utopias, did Cabet. But Cabet's communism was one of the “free store” type, and the goods were yours only after you had requisitioned them. That seems the case in the “Nowhere” of Morris also. Compared with the older writers Bellamy and Morris have a vivid sense of individual separation, and their departure from the old homogeneity is sufficiently marked to justify a doubt whether there will be any more thoroughly communistic Utopias for ever.

The older Utopias were all relatively small states; Plato's Republic, for example, was intended to be smaller than the average English borough, and there was no distinction made between the Family, Local Government, and the State. Plato and Campanella—despite Campanella being a Christian priest—took communism to its extreme and even suggested a community of husbands and wives, an idea that was ultimately tested in the Oneida Community of New York State (1848-1879). However, this community didn't last long after its founder, largely due to the rising individualism of its strong members. More also rejected privacy and enforced a complete community of goods, and similarly, Cabet did as well when it came to the Victorian Utopias. But Cabet's version of communism was the “free store” model, meaning you only had access to the goods after you requested them. This seems to be the case in Morris's “Nowhere” as well. Compared to earlier writers, Bellamy and Morris demonstrate a strong sense of individual identity, and their departure from the previous uniformity is so significant that it raises questions about whether there will ever be any truly communistic Utopias again.

A Utopia such as this present one, written in the opening of the Twentieth Century, and after the most exhaustive discussion—nearly a century long—between Communistic and Socialistic ideas on the one hand, and Individualism on the other, emerges upon a sort of effectual conclusion to those controversies. The two parties have so chipped and amended each other's initial propositions that, indeed, except for the labels still flutteringly adhesive to the implicated men, it is hard to choose between them. Each side established a good many propositions, and we profit by them all. We of the succeeding generation can see quite clearly that for the most part the heat and zeal of these discussions arose in the confusion of a quantitative for a qualitative question. To the onlooker, both Individualism and Socialism are, in the absolute, absurdities; the one would make men the slaves of the violent or rich, the other the slaves of the State official, and the way of sanity runs, perhaps even sinuously, down the intervening valley. Happily the dead past buries its dead, and it is not our function now to adjudicate the preponderance of victory. In the very days when our political and economic order is becoming steadily more Socialistic, our ideals of intercourse turn more and more to a fuller recognition of the claims of individuality. The State is to be progressive, it is no longer to be static, and this alters the general condition of the Utopian problem profoundly; we have to provide not only for food and clothing, for order and health, but for initiative. The factor that leads the World State on from one phase of development to the next is the interplay of individualities; to speak teleologically, the world exists for the sake of and through initiative, and individuality is the method of initiative. Each man and woman, to the extent that his or her individuality is marked, breaks the law of precedent, transgresses the general formula, and makes a new experiment for the direction of the life force. It is impossible, therefore, for the State, which represents all and is preoccupied by the average, to make effectual experiments and intelligent innovations, and so supply the essential substance of life. As against the individual the state represents the species, in the case of the Utopian World State it absolutely represents the species. The individual emerges from the species, makes his experiment, and either fails, dies, and comes to an end, or succeeds and impresses himself in offspring, in consequences and results, intellectual, material and moral, upon the world.

A Utopia like this one, written at the start of the Twentieth Century after nearly a century of intense debate between Communist and Socialist ideas on one side and Individualism on the other, reaches a sort of effective conclusion to those arguments. The two sides have revised each other's original ideas so much that, apart from the labels still attached to those involved, it’s hard to choose between them. Each side has proposed many ideas, and we benefit from all of them. We, in the next generation, can see clearly that the majority of the passion and energy in these discussions came from confusing a quantitative issue with a qualitative one. To an outsider, both Individualism and Socialism seem ridiculous; one risks making people the slaves of the powerful or wealthy, while the other risks making them the slaves of government officials. The path to sanity likely lies, perhaps in a winding way, in the middle ground. Fortunately, the past is gone, and it’s not our job now to determine who won. Even as our political and economic system increasingly leans toward Socialism, our ideals of interaction are shifting toward a greater acknowledgment of individual rights. The State should be forward-thinking, no longer static, which profoundly changes the nature of the Utopian challenge; we must ensure not just food and clothing, order and health, but also motivation. The element that drives the World State from one stage of development to another is the interaction of individuals; to put it in ultimate terms, the world exists for the sake of and through initiative, and individuality is the way that initiative manifests. Each individual, to the degree that their individuality stands out, breaks from tradition, defies the general norm, and creates a new experiment in the direction of life. Therefore, it’s impossible for the State, which represents everyone and is focused on the average, to conduct effective experiments and meaningful innovations, and thus provide the essential substance of life. When compared to the individual, the state embodies the species, especially in a Utopian World State context, it completely represents the species. The individual comes from the species, conducts their experiment, and either fails, ceases to exist, or succeeds and leaves a mark on the world through their offspring, their impact, and their contributions—intellectual, material, and moral.

Biologically the species is the accumulation of the experiments of all its successful individuals since the beginning, and the World State of the Modern Utopist will, in its economic aspect, be a compendium of established economic experience, about which individual enterprise will be continually experimenting, either to fail and pass, or to succeed and at last become incorporated with the undying organism of the World State. This organism is the universal rule, the common restriction, the rising level platform on which individualities stand.

Biologically, a species is the sum of the experiments of all its successful individuals since the beginning. The World State of the Modern Utopist will, in its economic aspect, be a collection of established economic experiences, where individual enterprises will continuously experiment, either to fail and be replaced, or to succeed and eventually become part of the enduring organism of the World State. This organism represents the universal rule, the shared limitations, the rising platform on which individualities stand.

The World State in this ideal presents itself as the sole landowner of the earth, with the great local governments I have adumbrated, the local municipalities, holding, as it were, feudally under it as landlords. The State or these subordinates holds all the sources of energy, and either directly or through its tenants, farmers and agents, develops these sources, and renders the energy available for the work of life. It or its tenants will produce food, and so human energy, and the exploitation of coal and electric power, and the powers of wind and wave and water will be within its right. It will pour out this energy by assignment and lease and acquiescence and what not upon its individual citizens. It will maintain order, maintain roads, maintain a cheap and efficient administration of justice, maintain cheap and rapid locomotion and be the common carrier of the planet, convey and distribute labour, control, let, or administer all natural productions, pay for and secure healthy births and a healthy and vigorous new generation, maintain the public health, coin money and sustain standards of measurement, subsidise research, and reward such commercially unprofitable undertakings as benefit the community as a whole; subsidise when needful chairs of criticism and authors and publications, and collect and distribute information. The energy developed and the employment afforded by the State will descend like water that the sun has sucked out of the sea to fall upon a mountain range, and back to the sea again it will come at last, debouching in ground rent and royalty and license fees, in the fees of travellers and profits upon carrying and coinage and the like, in death duty, transfer tax, legacy and forfeiture, returning to the sea. Between the clouds and the sea it will run, as a river system runs, down through a great region of individual enterprise and interplay, whose freedom it will sustain. In that intermediate region between the kindred heights and deeps those beginnings and promises will arise that are the essential significance, the essential substance, of life. From our human point of view the mountains and sea are for the habitable lands that lie between. So likewise the State is for Individualities. The State is for Individuals, the law is for freedoms, the world is for experiment, experience, and change: these are the fundamental beliefs upon which a modern Utopia must go.

The World State in this vision presents itself as the only landowner on Earth, with the local governments I’ve described, the local municipalities, operating under it like feudal tenants. The State or its subordinates control all sources of energy, developing these resources directly or through its tenants, farmers, and agents, and making the energy available for everyday life. It or its tenants will produce food and human energy, and the extraction of coal and electricity, as well as harnessing the powers of wind, waves, and water, will be within its rights. It will distribute this energy to its individual citizens through assignments, leases, and various agreements. It will keep order, maintain roads, ensure an affordable and effective justice system, provide cheap and speedy transportation, and serve as the common carrier for the planet, managing and distributing labor, controlling natural resources, funding and ensuring healthy births for a strong new generation, upholding public health, minting money, and maintaining measurement standards. It will support research and reward ventures that may not be profitable but benefit society as a whole, fund critical chairs, authors, and publications, and gather and disseminate information. The energy generated and jobs created by the State will flow like water evaporated by the sun from the sea, falling back to the ocean, reemerging as land rents, royalties, license fees, traveler fees, profits from transport and currency, and death duties, transfer taxes, legacies, and forfeitures, returning to the source. It will move between the clouds and the sea like a river system through a vast landscape of personal enterprise and interaction, which it will support. In that space between the related heights and depths, the fundamental beginnings and promises of life will arise. From our human perspective, the mountains and sea exist for the habitable lands in between. Similarly, the State exists for Individuals. The State is for Individuals, the law protects freedoms, and the world is for experimentation, experience, and change: these are the core beliefs on which a modern Utopia must be built.

§ 5

Within this scheme, which makes the State the source of all energy, and the final legatee, what will be the nature of the property a man may own? Under modern conditions—indeed, under any conditions—a man without some negotiable property is a man without freedom, and the extent of his property is very largely the measure of his freedom. Without any property, without even shelter or food, a man has no choice but to set about getting these things; he is in servitude to his needs until he has secured property to satisfy them. But with a certain small property a man is free to do many things, to take a fortnight's holiday when he chooses, for example, and to try this new departure from his work or that; with so much more, he may take a year of freedom and go to the ends of the earth; with so much more, he may obtain elaborate apparatus and try curious novelties, build himself houses and make gardens, establish businesses and make experiments at large. Very speedily, under terrestrial conditions, the property of a man may reach such proportions that his freedom oppresses the freedom of others. Here, again, is a quantitative question, an adjustment of conflicting freedoms, a quantitative question that too many people insist on making a qualitative one.

Within this framework, where the State is the source of all power and the ultimate owner, what kind of property can a person possess? In today's world—really, in any context—a person without some kind of valuable property is a person without freedom, and the amount of property they hold largely determines their freedom. Without any property, not even basic shelter or food, a person has no option but to focus on acquiring these essentials; they are enslaved to their needs until they have secured property to fulfill them. However, with a small amount of property, a person is free to do various things, like taking a two-week vacation whenever they want, or trying out new projects. With a bit more, they could take a year off and travel the world; with even more, they could invest in equipment to explore interesting ideas, build houses, create gardens, start businesses, and experiment in broader ways. Quickly, under earthly conditions, a person's property might grow to such an extent that their freedom starts to infringe on the freedom of others. This is, again, a quantitative issue, a balancing act of conflicting freedoms, an issue that too many people wrongly turn into a qualitative one.

The object sought in the code of property laws that one would find in operation in Utopia would be the same object that pervades the whole Utopian organisation, namely, a universal maximum of individual freedom. Whatever far-reaching movements the State or great rich men or private corporations may make, the starvation by any complication of employment, the unwilling deportation, the destruction of alternatives to servile submissions, must not ensue. Beyond such qualifications, the object of Modern Utopian statesmanship will be to secure to a man the freedom given by all his legitimate property, that is to say, by all the values his toil or skill or foresight and courage have brought into being. Whatever he has justly made he has a right to keep, that is obvious enough; but he will also have a right to sell and exchange, and so this question of what may be property takes really the form of what may a man buy in Utopia?

The goal of property laws in Utopia would be the same aim that runs throughout the entire Utopian structure: a universal maximum of individual freedom. Regardless of any significant actions taken by the State, wealthy individuals, or private companies, there should be no scenarios leading to starvation due to job complications, forced relocations, or the elimination of alternatives to servitude. Beyond these conditions, the aim of Modern Utopian governance will be to ensure that a person enjoys the freedom granted by all their legitimate property, meaning all the value created through their labor, skills, foresight, and bravery. It's clear that whatever someone has rightfully created, they should be able to keep; but they should also have the right to sell and trade, making the real question about property one of what goods a person can purchase in Utopia.

A modern Utopian most assuredly must have a practically unqualified property in all those things that become, as it were, by possession, extensions and expressions of his personality; his clothing, his jewels, the tools of his employment, his books, the objects of art he may have bought or made, his personal weapons (if Utopia have need of such things), insignia, and so forth. All such things that he has bought with his money or acquired—provided he is not a professional or habitual dealer in such property—will be inalienably his, his to give or lend or keep, free even from taxation. So intimate is this sort of property that I have no doubt Utopia will give a man posthumous rights over it—will permit him to assign it to a successor with at the utmost the payment of a small redemption. A horse, perhaps, in certain districts, or a bicycle, or any such mechanical conveyance personally used, the Utopians might find it well to rank with these possessions. No doubt, too, a house and privacy owned and occupied by a man, and even a man's own household furniture, might be held to stand as high or almost as high in the property scale, might be taxed as lightly and transferred under only a slightly heavier redemption, provided he had not let these things on hire, or otherwise alienated them from his intimate self. A thorough-going, Democratic Socialist will no doubt be inclined at first to object that if the Utopians make these things a specially free sort of property in this way, men would spend much more upon them than they would otherwise do, but indeed that will be an excellent thing. We are too much affected by the needy atmosphere of our own mismanaged world. In Utopia no one will have to hunger because some love to make and have made and own and cherish beautiful things. To give this much of property to individuals will tend to make clothing, ornamentation, implements, books, and all the arts finer and more beautiful, because by buying such things a man will secure something inalienable—save in the case of bankruptcy—for himself and for those who belong to him. Moreover, a man may in his lifetime set aside sums to ensure special advantages of education and care for the immature children of himself and others, and in this manner also exercise a posthumous right. [Footnote: But a Statute of Mortmain will set a distinct time limit to the continuance of such benefactions. A periodic revision of endowments is a necessary feature in any modern Utopia.]

A modern Utopian definitely must have a nearly unrestricted ownership of all those items that, in a way, represent extensions and expressions of his personality; his clothes, his jewelry, the tools he uses for work, his books, the art pieces he has purchased or created, his personal weapons (if Utopia needs such things), insignia, and so on. All these items that he has bought with his money or acquired—unless he is a professional or habitual dealer in such items—will be indisputably his, his to give, lend, or keep, free even from taxation. This kind of property is so personal that I have no doubt Utopia will allow a person posthumous rights over it—permitting him to pass it on to a successor with only a nominal redemption fee. A horse, perhaps, in certain areas, or a bicycle, or any similar mechanical transport used personally, the Utopians might consider on par with these possessions. Certainly, a house that someone owns and occupies, and even his own household furniture, could also rank equally high or almost as high in property value, taxed lightly and transferred with only a slightly heavier redemption fee, assuming he hasn't rented these items out or otherwise separated them from his intimate self. A committed Democratic Socialist might initially argue that if the Utopians categorize these items as a uniquely free kind of property, men would likely spend much more on them than they would otherwise, but that would actually be a positive outcome. We are too influenced by the needy atmosphere of our poorly managed world. In Utopia, no one will go hungry because some people enjoy creating, possessing, and cherishing beautiful things. Allowing individuals this level of property will encourage clothing, decorations, tools, books, and all the arts to become finer and more beautiful, since by purchasing such items a person will secure something that cannot be taken away—except in the case of bankruptcy—for himself and for those he cares about. Additionally, a person may set aside funds in his lifetime to ensure special educational opportunities and care for the young children of himself and others, also exercising a posthumous right. [Footnote: However, a Statute of Mortmain will set a clear time limit on the continuation of such benefactions. Regular reviews of endowments are essential in any modern Utopia.]

For all other property, the Utopians will have a scantier respect; even money unspent by a man, and debts to him that bear no interest, will at his death stand upon a lower level than these things. What he did not choose to gather and assimilate to himself, or assign for the special education of his children, the State will share in the lion's proportion with heir and legatee.

For all other property, the Utopians have less regard; even unused money and low-interest debts owed to a person will be valued less at his death than these items. What he didn’t choose to collect and use for himself, or designate for the specific education of his children, the State will take a significant share of along with the heir and legatee.

This applies, for example, to the property that a man creates and acquires in business enterprises, which are presumably undertaken for gain, and as a means of living rather than for themselves. All new machinery, all new methods, all uncertain and variable and non-universal undertakings, are no business for the State; they commence always as experiments of unascertained value, and next after the invention of money, there is no invention has so facilitated freedom and progress as the invention of the limited liability company to do this work of trial and adventure. The abuses, the necessary reforms of company law on earth, are no concern of ours here and now, suffice it that in a Modern Utopia such laws must be supposed to be as perfect as mortal laws can possibly be made. Caveat vendor will be a sound qualification of Caveat emptor in the beautifully codified Utopian law. Whether the Utopian company will be allowed to prefer this class of share to that or to issue debentures, whether indeed usury, that is to say lending money at fixed rates of interest, will be permitted at all in Utopia, one may venture to doubt. But whatever the nature of the shares a man may hold, they will all be sold at his death, and whatever he has not clearly assigned for special educational purposes will—with possibly some fractional concession to near survivors—lapse to the State. The “safe investment,” that permanent, undying claim upon the community, is just one of those things Utopia will discourage; which indeed the developing security of civilisation quite automatically discourages through the fall in the rate of interest. As we shall see at a later stage, the State will insure the children of every citizen, and those legitimately dependent upon him, against the inconvenience of his death; it will carry out all reasonable additional dispositions he may have made for them in the same event; and it will insure him against old age and infirmity; and the object of Utopian economics will be to give a man every inducement to spend his surplus money in intensifying the quality of his surroundings, either by economic adventures and experiments, which may yield either losses or large profits, or in increasing the beauty, the pleasure, the abundance and promise of life.

This applies, for example, to the property that a person creates and acquires in business ventures, which are typically undertaken for profit and as a means of living rather than for personal gain. All new machinery, all new methods, and all uncertain and variable undertakings are not the State's responsibility; they always start as experiments with unknown value. After the invention of money, nothing has facilitated freedom and progress as much as the creation of the limited liability company to undertake these trials and adventures. The issues and necessary reforms of company law on Earth aren't our concern right now; it's enough to say that in a Modern Utopia, such laws should be as perfect as human laws can be. Caveat vendor will be a strong addition to Caveat emptor in the well-structured Utopian law. Whether the Utopian company will be allowed to prioritize this class of shares over that or to issue debentures, or indeed whether lending money at fixed interest rates, known as usury, will be allowed at all in Utopia, is uncertain. But whatever kind of shares a person holds, they will all be sold upon their death, and anything they haven't clearly designated for specific educational purposes will—with perhaps some minor concession to close relatives—revert to the State. The "safe investment," that permanent, unyielding claim on the community, is just one of those things Utopia will discourage; indeed, the growing security of civilization automatically discourages it through the declining interest rates. As we'll see later, the State will ensure support for the children of every citizen and those who legitimately depend on them, protecting them from the disruption caused by his death; it will honor any reasonable additional arrangements he may have made for them in that event; and it will provide insurance against old age and illness. The goal of Utopian economics will be to encourage individuals to spend their surplus money on enhancing the quality of their environment, whether through economic ventures and experiments that may result in losses or significant profits, or by increasing the beauty, enjoyment, abundance, and promise of life.

Besides strictly personal possessions and shares in business adventures, Utopia will no doubt permit associations of its citizens to have a property in various sorts of contracts and concessions, in leases of agricultural and other land, for example; in houses they may have built, factories and machinery they may have made, and the like. And if a citizen prefer to adventure into business single-handed, he will have all the freedoms of enterprise enjoyed by a company; in business affairs he will be a company of one, and his single share will be dealt with at his death like any other shares.... So much for the second kind of property. And these two kinds of property will probably exhaust the sorts of property a Utopian may possess.

Aside from personal belongings and stakes in business ventures, Utopia will certainly allow its citizens to own various types of contracts and agreements, like leases for agricultural and other kinds of land. They can own houses they’ve built, factories, and machinery they’ve created, and so on. If a citizen chooses to venture into business on their own, they will have all the freedoms of enterprise that a company enjoys; in business matters, they will be a one-person company, and their individual share will be handled at their death just like any other shares… So that's it for the second type of property. These two types of property will likely cover all the assets a Utopian can own.

The trend of modern thought is entirely against private property in land or natural objects or products, and in Utopia these things will be the inalienable property of the World State. Subject to the rights of free locomotion, land will be leased out to companies or individuals, but—in view of the unknown necessities of the future—never for a longer period than, let us say, fifty years.

The current trend of thinking completely opposes private ownership of land or natural resources and products, and in Utopia, these will be the permanent property of the World State. While respecting the rights to freely move, land will be leased to companies or individuals, but—considering the unpredictable needs of the future—never for more than, say, fifty years.

The property of a parent in his children, and of a husband in his wife, seems to be undergoing a steadily increasing qualification in the world of to-day, but the discussion of the Utopian state of affairs in regard to such property may be better reserved until marriage becomes our topic. Suffice it here to remark, that the increasing control of a child's welfare and upbringing by the community, and the growing disposition to limit and tax inheritance are complementary aspects of the general tendency to regard the welfare and free intraplay of future generations no longer as the concern of parents and altruistic individuals, but as the predominant issue of statesmanship, and the duty and moral meaning of the world community as a whole.

The ownership a parent has over their children and a husband has over his wife seems to be increasingly challenged in today's world. However, we can save the discussion about an ideal society regarding these ownership issues for when we talk about marriage. For now, it's worth noting that the rising influence of the community on a child's welfare and upbringing, along with the growing trend to restrict and tax inheritance, reflects a shift in thinking. No longer is the well-being and development of future generations seen solely as the responsibility of parents and caring individuals; instead, it is becoming a key issue in governance and a duty that falls on the global community as a whole.

§ 6

From the conception of mechanical force as coming in from Nature to the service of man, a conception the Utopian proposal of a coinage based on energy units would emphasise, arise profound contrasts between the modern and the classical Utopias. Except for a meagre use of water power for milling, and the wind for sailing—so meagre in the latter case that the classical world never contrived to do without the galley slave—and a certain restricted help from oxen in ploughing, and from horses in locomotion, all the energy that sustained the old-fashioned State was derived from the muscular exertion of toiling men. They ran their world by hand. Continual bodily labour was a condition of social existence. It is only with the coming of coal burning, of abundant iron and steel, and of scientific knowledge that this condition has been changed. To-day, I suppose, if it were possible to indicate, in units of energy, the grand total of work upon which the social fabric of the United States or England rests, it would be found that a vastly preponderating moiety is derived from non-human sources, from coal and liquid fuel, and explosives and wind and water. There is every indication of a steady increase in this proportion of mechanical energy, in this emancipation of men from the necessity of physical labour. There appears no limit to the invasion of life by the machine.

From the idea that mechanical force comes from nature to serve humanity—a concept that the Utopian proposal for a currency based on energy units would highlight—there are significant contrasts between modern and classical Utopias. Aside from a minimal use of water power for milling and wind for sailing—so limited in the latter case that the classical world never managed to eliminate the need for galley slaves—along with some limited assistance from oxen for plowing and horses for transportation, all the energy that supported the traditional state was drawn from the physical effort of working humans. They operated their world manually. Continuous physical labor was essential for social existence. It’s only with the advent of coal burning, abundant iron and steel, and scientific knowledge that this situation has changed. Today, if it were possible to quantify, in energy units, the total amount of work that supports the social structure of the United States or England, it would become clear that a significant majority comes from non-human sources—such as coal, liquid fuel, explosives, wind, and water. There is strong evidence of a steady increase in this share of mechanical energy, indicating a growing liberation of people from the need for physical labor. It seems there are no limits to how machines can invade our lives.

Now it is only in the last three hundred years that any human being seems to have anticipated this. It stimulates the imagination to remark how entirely it was overlooked as a modifying cause in human development. [Footnote: It is interesting to note how little even Bacon seems to see of this, in his New Atlantis.] Plato clearly had no ideas about machines at all as a force affecting social organisation. There was nothing in his world to suggest them to him. I suppose there arose no invention, no new mechanical appliance or method of the slightest social importance through all his length of years. He never thought of a State that did not rely for its force upon human muscle, just as he never thought of a State that was not primarily organised for warfare hand to hand. Political and moral inventions he saw enough of and to spare, and in that direction he still stimulates the imagination. But in regard to all material possibilities he deadens rather than stimulates. [Footnote: The lost Utopia of Hippodamus provided rewards for inventors, but unless Aristotle misunderstood him, and it is certainly the fate of all Utopias to be more or less misread, the inventions contemplated were political devices.] An infinitude of nonsense about the Greek mind would never have been written if the distinctive intellectual and artistic quality of Plato's time, its extraordinarily clear definition of certain material conditions as absolutely permanent, coupled with its politico-social instability, had been borne in mind. The food of the Greek imagination was the very antithesis of our own nourishment. We are educated by our circumstances to think no revolution in appliances and economic organisation incredible, our minds play freely about possibilities that would have struck the men of the Academy as outrageous extravagance, and it is in regard to politico-social expedients that our imaginations fail. Sparta, for all the evidence of history, is scarcely more credible to us than a motor-car throbbing in the agora would have been to Socrates.

Now, it’s only in the last three hundred years that any human being seems to have anticipated this. It’s interesting to notice how completely it was overlooked as a factor in human development. [Footnote: It’s notable how little even Bacon seems to recognize this in his New Atlantis.] Plato clearly didn’t have any ideas about machines as a force affecting social organization. There was nothing in his world to suggest them to him. I guess there were no inventions, no new mechanical tools or methods of any social importance throughout all his years. He never imagined a State that relied on anything other than human strength, just as he never thought of a State that wasn’t primarily organized for hand-to-hand warfare. He observed enough political and moral innovations, and in that regard, he still sparks the imagination. But when it comes to all material possibilities, he stifles rather than inspires. [Footnote: The lost Utopia of Hippodamus provided rewards for inventors, but unless Aristotle misunderstood him, and it's certainly the fate of all Utopias to be somewhat misinterpreted, the inventions he envisioned were political devices.] A ton of nonsense about the Greek mind wouldn't have been written if the unique intellectual and artistic qualities of Plato's time, its unusually clear definition of certain material conditions as completely permanent, combined with its political and social instability, had been considered. The food for the Greek imagination was the exact opposite of what nourishes us today. Our circumstances educate us to believe that no revolution in tools and economic organization is unbelievable, and our minds roam freely around possibilities that would have seemed outrageous to the men of the Academy. In contrast, our imaginations struggle when it comes to political and social solutions. Sparta, despite all historical evidence, seems no more credible to us than a car buzzing in the agora would have been to Socrates.

By sheer inadvertence, therefore, Plato commenced the tradition of Utopias without machinery, a tradition we find Morris still loyally following, except for certain mechanical barges and such-like toys, in his News from Nowhere. There are some foreshadowings of mechanical possibilities in the New Atlantis, but it is only in the nineteenth century that Utopias appeared in which the fact is clearly recognised that the social fabric rests no longer upon human labour. It was, I believe, Cabet [Footnote: Cabet, Voyage en Icarie, 1848.] who first in a Utopian work insisted upon the escape of man from irksome labours through the use of machinery. He is the great primitive of modern Utopias, and Bellamy is his American equivalent. Hitherto, either slave labour (Phaleas), [Footnote: Aristotle's Politics, Bk. II., Ch. VIII.] or at least class distinctions involving unavoidable labour in the lower class, have been assumed—as Plato does, and as Bacon in the New Atlantis probably intended to do (More gave his Utopians bondsmen sans phrase for their most disagreeable toil); or there is—as in Morris and the outright Return-to-Nature Utopians—a bold make-believe that all toil may be made a joy, and with that a levelling down of all society to an equal participation in labour. But indeed this is against all the observed behaviour of mankind. It needed the Olympian unworldliness of an irresponsible rich man of the shareholding type, a Ruskin or a Morris playing at life, to imagine as much. Road-making under Mr. Ruskin's auspices was a joy at Oxford no doubt, and a distinction, and it still remains a distinction; it proved the least contagious of practices. And Hawthorne did not find bodily toil anything more than the curse the Bible says it is, at Brook Farm. [Footnote: The Blythedale Experiment, and see also his Notebook.]

By pure coincidence, Plato started the tradition of Utopias without machinery, a tradition that Morris still follows, apart from some mechanical barges and similar gadgets, in his News from Nowhere. There are hints of mechanical possibilities in the New Atlantis, but it wasn't until the nineteenth century that Utopias clearly acknowledged that society no longer relies on human labor. I believe it was Cabet [Footnote: Cabet, Voyage en Icarie, 1848.] who was the first, in a Utopian work, to emphasize that people could escape tedious labor through the use of machinery. He is the great precursor of modern Utopias, and Bellamy is his American counterpart. Until now, either slave labor (Phaleas) [Footnote: Aristotle's Politics, Bk. II., Ch. VIII.] or class distinctions with unavoidable labor for the lower class have been taken for granted—as Plato assumed, and as Bacon in the New Atlantis probably intended (More assigned his Utopians bondsmen sans phrase for their least pleasant tasks); or there's the approach seen in Morris and the outright Return-to-Nature Utopians—a bold fantasy that all work can be enjoyable, which implies leveling society to share labor equally. But this contradicts all observable human behavior. It took the detached, unrealistic perspective of a wealthy investor, someone like Ruskin or Morris playing at life, to envision such a situation. Road-building under Mr. Ruskin's guidance was surely a joy at Oxford and a privilege, and it still remains a privilege; it turned out to be one of the least widely embraced activities. And Hawthorne found physical labor to be nothing more than the curse that the Bible describes, at Brook Farm. [Footnote: The Blythedale Experiment, and see also his Notebook.]

If toil is a blessing, never was blessing so effectually disguised, and the very people who tell us that, hesitate to suggest more than a beautiful ease in the endless day of Heaven. A certain amount of bodily or mental exercise, a considerable amount of doing things under the direction of one's free imagination is quite another matter. Artistic production, for example, when it is at its best, when a man is freely obeying himself, and not troubling to please others, is really not toil at all. It is quite a different thing digging potatoes, as boys say, “for a lark,” and digging them because otherwise you will starve, digging them day after day as a dull, unavoidable imperative. The essence of toil is that imperative, and the fact that the attention must cramp itself to the work in hand—that it excludes freedom, and not that it involves fatigue. So long as anything but a quasi-savage life depended upon toil, so long was it hopeless to expect mankind to do anything but struggle to confer just as much of this blessing as possible upon one another. But now that the new conditions physical science is bringing about, not only dispense with man as a source of energy but supply the hope that all routine work may be made automatic, it is becoming conceivable that presently there may be no need for anyone to toil habitually at all; that a labouring class—that is to say, a class of workers without personal initiative—will become unnecessary to the world of men.

If hard work is a blessing, it’s never been so well hidden, and the same people who tell us this hesitate to suggest anything more than a beautiful ease in the endless day of Heaven. A certain amount of physical or mental activity, a significant amount of doing things guided by one's own imagination is a completely different story. Artistic creation, for instance, when it’s at its best—when a person is freely following their own instincts and not worrying about pleasing others—is actually not hard work at all. It’s one thing to dig potatoes, as kids say, “for fun,” and quite another to dig them because otherwise, you’ll starve, doing it day after day as a dull, unavoidable necessity. The core of hard work is that necessity, and that the attention must confine itself to the task at hand—that it leaves no room for freedom, and not just that it leads to fatigue. As long as anything more than a somewhat primitive life relied on hard work, it was pointless to expect humanity to do anything but fight to share as much of this blessing as possible with one another. But now that the new conditions created by physical science are not only eliminating the need for people as a source of energy but also offering the hope that all routine work may become automatic, it’s becoming possible to imagine a time when nobody will need to work hard regularly at all; that a working class—that is, a group of workers without personal initiative—will become unnecessary in the world.

The plain message physical science has for the world at large is this, that were our political and social and moral devices only as well contrived to their ends as a linotype machine, an antiseptic operating plant, or an electric tram-car, there need now at the present moment be no appreciable toil in the world, and only the smallest fraction of the pain, the fear, and the anxiety that now makes human life so doubtful in its value. There is more than enough for everyone alive. Science stands, a too competent servant, behind her wrangling underbred masters, holding out resources, devices, and remedies they are too stupid to use. [Footnote: See that most suggestive little book, Twentieth Century Inventions, by Mr. George Sutherland.] And on its material side a modern Utopia must needs present these gifts as taken, and show a world that is really abolishing the need of labour, abolishing the last base reason for anyone's servitude or inferiority.

The straightforward message that physical science has for the world is this: if our political, social, and moral systems were as well designed as a linotype machine, a sterile surgical facility, or an electric tram, there shouldn’t be any significant toil in the world right now, and only a tiny bit of the pain, fear, and anxiety that currently makes human life so uncertain in its value. There is more than enough for everyone. Science stands ready, an overly capable servant, behind its squabbling, ill-mannered masters, offering resources, tools, and solutions that they are too foolish to use. [Footnote: See that very insightful little book, Twentieth Century Inventions, by Mr. George Sutherland.] A modern Utopia must showcase these gifts as accepted and demonstrate a world that is genuinely eliminating the need for labor, removing the final reasons for anyone’s servitude or inferiority.

§ 7

The effectual abolition of a labouring and servile class will make itself felt in every detail of the inn that will shelter us, of the bedrooms we shall occupy. You conceive my awakening to all these things on the morning after our arrival. I shall lie for a minute or so with my nose peeping over the coverlet, agreeably and gently coming awake, and with some vague nightmare of sitting at a common table with an unavoidable dustman in green and gold called Boffin, [Footnote: Vide William Morris's News from Nowhere.] fading out of my mind. Then I should start up. You figure my apprehensive, startled inspection of my chamber. “Where am I?” that classic phrase, recurs. Then I perceive quite clearly that I am in bed in Utopia.

The complete elimination of a working and servile class will be felt in every aspect of the inn that will host us, including the bedrooms we'll stay in. You can imagine me waking up to all this on the morning after we arrive. I’ll lie there for a minute or so with my nose peeking over the blanket, gradually waking up, while some vague nightmare about sharing a common table with an unavoidable dustman in green and gold named Boffin, [Footnote: Vide William Morris's News from Nowhere.] fades from my mind. Then I should bolt up. You can picture my anxious, startled look around the room. “Where am I?” that classic question pops up again. Then I realize quite clearly that I’m in bed in Utopia.

Utopia! The word is enough to bring anyone out of bed, to the nearest window, but thence I see no more than the great mountain mass behind the inn, a very terrestrial looking mountain mass. I return to the contrivances about me, and make my examination as I dress, pausing garment in hand to hover over first this thing of interest and then that.

Utopia! Just hearing the word is enough to get anyone out of bed and to the nearest window, but all I see is the big mountain range behind the inn, a very ordinary-looking mountain range. I go back to my surroundings and check things out as I get dressed, stopping with a piece of clothing in hand to take a closer look at this interesting thing and then that one.

The room is, of course, very clear and clean and simple; not by any means cheaply equipped, but designed to economise the labour of redding and repair just as much as is possible. It is beautifully proportioned, and rather lower than most rooms I know on earth. There is no fireplace, and I am perplexed by that until I find a thermometer beside six switches on the wall. Above this switch-board is a brief instruction: one switch warms the floor, which is not carpeted, but covered by a substance like soft oilcloth; one warms the mattress (which is of metal with resistance coils threaded to and fro in it); and the others warm the wall in various degrees, each directing current through a separate system of resistances. The casement does not open, but above, flush with the ceiling, a noiseless rapid fan pumps air out of the room. The air enters by a Tobin shaft. There is a recess dressing-room, equipped with a bath and all that is necessary to one's toilette, and the water, one remarks, is warmed, if one desires it warm, by passing it through an electrically heated spiral of tubing. A cake of soap drops out of a store machine on the turn of a handle, and when you have done with it, you drop that and your soiled towels and so forth, which also are given you by machines, into a little box, through the bottom of which they drop at once, and sail down a smooth shaft. A little notice tells you the price of your room, and you gather the price is doubled if you do not leave the toilette as you found it. Beside the bed, and to be lit at night by a handy switch over the pillow, is a little clock, its face flush with the wall. The room has no corners to gather dirt, wall meets floor with a gentle curve, and the apartment could be swept out effectually by a few strokes of a mechanical sweeper. The door frames and window frames are of metal, rounded and impervious to draught. You are politely requested to turn a handle at the foot of your bed before leaving the room, and forthwith the frame turns up into a vertical position, and the bedclothes hang airing. You stand at the doorway and realise that there remains not a minute's work for anyone to do. Memories of the fœtid disorder of many an earthly bedroom after a night's use float across your mind.

The room is, of course, very clear, clean, and simple; not in any way cheaply furnished, but designed to minimize the effort of tidying and repairs as much as possible. It is beautifully proportioned and a bit lower than most rooms I know on Earth. There’s no fireplace, which confuses me until I notice a thermometer next to six switches on the wall. Above this switch panel is a short instruction: one switch warms the floor, which isn't carpeted but covered with a soft, oilcloth-like material; one warms the mattress (which is metal with resistance coils woven throughout it); and the others heat the walls to different levels, each controlling current through a separate resistance system. The window doesn’t open, but a silent, fast fan flush with the ceiling exhausts air from the room. The air comes in through a Tobin shaft. There’s a small dressing area with a bath and everything needed for one's grooming, and the water, you notice, can be warmed, if you want it that way, by passing through an electrically heated spiral tube. A bar of soap automatically dispenses from a machine when you turn a handle, and when you're done with it, you drop it and your used towels, which are also provided by machines, into a small box that immediately sends them down a smooth shaft. A little notice shows the price of your room, and you gather that the rate doubles if you don’t leave the bathroom as you found it. Next to the bed, which can be lit at night by a handy switch over the pillow, is a small clock with its face set into the wall. The room has no corners to collect dirt; the wall meets the floor with a gentle curve, making it easy to sweep out with just a few motions of a mechanical sweeper. The door and window frames are made of metal, rounded and draft-proof. You are politely asked to turn a handle at the foot of your bed before leaving the room, which then raises the frame into a vertical position, airing the bedding. You stand at the doorway and notice there’s not a minute’s work left for anyone to do. Memories of the foul mess of many earthly bedrooms after a night’s use drift through your mind.

And you must not imagine this dustless, spotless, sweet apartment as anything but beautiful. Its appearance is a little unfamiliar of course, but all the muddle of dust-collecting hangings and witless ornament that cover the earthly bedroom, the valances, the curtains to check the draught from the ill-fitting wood windows, the worthless irrelevant pictures, usually a little askew, the dusty carpets, and all the paraphernalia about the dirty, black-leaded fireplace are gone. But the faintly tinted walls are framed with just one clear coloured line, as finely placed as the member of a Greek capital; the door handles and the lines of the panels of the door, the two chairs, the framework of the bed, the writing table, have all that final simplicity, that exquisite finish of contour that is begotten of sustained artistic effort. The graciously shaped windows each frame a picture—since they are draughtless the window seats are no mere mockeries as are the window seats of earth—and on the sill, the sole thing to need attention in the room, is one little bowl of blue Alpine flowers.

And you shouldn't think of this dust-free, spotless, cozy apartment as anything but beautiful. Its look is a bit unfamiliar, but all the clutter of dust-collecting decor and pointless ornaments that usually fill a messy bedroom—the valances, the curtains to block drafts from the poorly fitting wooden windows, the meaningless pictures that are often slightly crooked, the dusty carpets, and all the stuff around the dirty, blackened fireplace—has been removed. Instead, the softly colored walls are lined with a single clear colored strip, as perfectly placed as a detail on a Greek column. The doorknobs and the panel lines on the door, the two chairs, the bed frame, and the writing desk all have that ultimate simplicity and exquisite finish that comes from dedicated artistic effort. The elegantly shaped windows each frame a scene—since they don’t let in drafts, the window seats here are not just a joke like they often are elsewhere—and on the sill, the only thing needing attention in the room is a small bowl of blue Alpine flowers.

The same exquisite simplicity meets one downstairs.

The same beautiful simplicity greets you downstairs.

Our landlord sits down at table with us for a moment, and seeing we do not understand the electrically heated coffee-pot before us, shows us what to do. Coffee and milk we have, in the Continental fashion, and some excellent rolls and butter.

Our landlord sits down at the table with us for a moment, and seeing that we don’t understand the electric coffee pot in front of us, shows us how to use it. We have coffee and milk, in the European style, along with some excellent rolls and butter.

He is a swarthy little man, our landlord, and overnight we saw him preoccupied with other guests. But we have risen either late or early by Utopian standards, we know not which, and this morning he has us to himself. His bearing is kindly and inoffensive, but he cannot conceal the curiosity that possesses him. His eye meets ours with a mute inquiry, and then as we fall to, we catch him scrutinising our cuffs, our garments, our boots, our faces, our table manners. He asks nothing at first, but says a word or so about our night's comfort and the day's weather, phrases that have an air of being customary. Then comes a silence that is interrogative.

He is a dark-skinned little man, our landlord, and overnight we noticed him focused on other guests. But we’ve either woken up late or early by Utopian standards—we’re not sure which, and this morning he has our full attention. He is friendly and unassuming, but he can’t hide his curiosity. His gaze meets ours with a silent question, and as we begin to eat, we catch him examining our cuffs, our clothes, our shoes, our faces, and our table manners. He doesn’t ask anything at first, but says a few words about how we slept and the weather today, phrases that feel routine. Then there’s a silence that seems to ask a question.

“Excellent coffee,” I say to fill the gap.

"Great coffee," I say to fill the silence.

“And excellent rolls,” says my botanist.

“And great rolls,” says my botanist.

Our landlord indicates his sense of our approval.

Our landlord shows that he thinks we approve.

A momentary diversion is caused by the entry of an elfin-tressed little girl, who stares at us half impudently, half shyly, with bright black eyes, hesitates at the botanist's clumsy smile and nod, and then goes and stands by her father and surveys us steadfastly.

A brief distraction occurs when a little girl with delicate hair enters. She looks at us with a mix of boldness and shyness, her bright black eyes taking in the scene. She hesitates at the botanist's awkward smile and nod before going to stand by her father, watching us intently.

“You have come far?” ventures our landlord, patting his daughter's shoulder.

"You've come a long way?" our landlord asks, giving his daughter's shoulder a reassuring pat.

I glance at the botanist. “Yes,” I say, “we have.”

I look at the botanist. “Yeah,” I say, “we have.”

I expand. “We have come so far that this country of yours seems very strange indeed to us.”

I elaborate. “We've come so far that your country feels really strange to us.”

“The mountains?”

"The mountains?"

“Not only the mountains.”

"Not just the mountains."

“You came up out of the Ticino valley?”

“You came up from the Ticino valley?”

“No—not that way.”

“No—not like that.”

“By the Oberalp?”

"At the Oberalp?"

“No.”

“Nope.”

“The Furka?”

"The Furka Pass?"

“No.”

“No.”

“Not up from the lake?”

“Not back from the lake?”

“No.”

“Nope.”

He looks puzzled.

He's looking confused.

“We came,” I say, “from another world.”

“We came,” I say, “from another world.”

He seems trying to understand. Then a thought strikes him, and he sends away his little girl with a needless message to her mother.

He looks like he's trying to understand. Then an idea hits him, and he sends his little girl away with a pointless message to her mother.

“Ah!” he says. “Another world—eh? Meaning―?”

“Ah!” he says. “Another world—right? What does that mean―?”

“Another world—far in the deeps of space.”

“Another world—far in the depths of space.”

Then at the expression of his face one realises that a Modern Utopia will probably keep its more intelligent citizens for better work than inn-tending. He is evidently inaccessible to the idea we think of putting before him. He stares at us a moment, and then remarks, “There's the book to sign.”

Then, from the look on his face, you realize that a Modern Utopia will likely reserve its more intelligent citizens for more valuable work than managing an inn. He clearly can't grasp the idea we're trying to present to him. He stares at us for a moment and then says, “There's the book to sign.”

We find ourselves confronted with a book, a little after the fashion of the familiar hotel visitors' book of earth. He places this before us, and beside it puts pen and ink and a slab, upon which ink has been freshly smeared.

We are presented with a book, somewhat like the well-known guest book found in hotels. He sets this in front of us, along with a pen, ink, and a slab that has been freshly inked.

“Thumbmarks,” says my scientific friend hastily in English.

“Thumbmarks,” my scientific friend says quickly in English.

“You show me how to do it,” I say as quickly.

“You show me how to do it,” I say quickly.

He signs first, and I look over his shoulder.

He signs first, and I glance over his shoulder.

He is displaying more readiness than I should have expected. The book is ruled in broad transverse lines, and has a space for a name, for a number, and a thumbmark. He puts his thumb upon the slab and makes the thumbmark first with the utmost deliberation. Meanwhile he studies the other two entries. The “numbers” of the previous guests above are complex muddles of letters and figures. He writes his name, then with a calm assurance writes down his number, A.M.a.1607.2.αβ⊕. I am wrung with momentary admiration. I follow his example, and fabricate an equally imposing signature. We think ourselves very clever. The landlord proffers finger bowls for our thumbs, and his eye goes, just a little curiously, to our entries.

He’s showing more willingness than I would have expected. The book has wide horizontal lines and includes spaces for a name, a number, and a thumbprint. He places his thumb on the page and carefully makes his thumbprint first. Meanwhile, he looks at the other two entries. The "numbers" of the previous guests above are complicated mixes of letters and numbers. He writes his name, then confidently writes down his number, A.M.a.1607.2.αβ⊕. I feel a moment of admiration. I follow his lead and come up with an equally impressive signature. We think we’re quite clever. The landlord offers finger bowls for our thumbs, and his eyes glance, just a bit curiously, at our entries.

I decide it is advisable to pay and go before any conversation about our formulæ arises.

I think it’s best to pay and leave before any discussion about our formulas starts.

As we emerge into the corridor, and the morning sunlight of the Utopian world, I see the landlord bending over the book.

As we step into the hallway and the morning sunlight of the Utopian world, I see the landlord leaning over the book.

“Come on,” I say. “The most tiresome thing in the world is explanations, and I perceive that if we do not get along, they will fall upon us now.”

“Come on,” I say. “The most exhausting thing in the world is explanations, and I can tell that if we don’t get along, they’re going to end up on us now.”

I glance back to discover the landlord and a gracefully robed woman standing outside the pretty simplicity of the Utopian inn, watching us doubtfully as we recede.

I look back to see the landlord and a elegantly dressed woman standing outside the charming simplicity of the Utopian inn, watching us with uncertainty as we move away.

“Come on,” I insist.

“Let’s go,” I insist.

§ 8

We should go towards the Schoellenen gorge, and as we went, our fresh morning senses would gather together a thousand factors for our impression of this more civilised world. A Modern Utopia will have done with yapping about nationality, and so the ugly fortifications, the barracks and military defilements of the earthly vale of Urseren will be wanting. Instead there will be a great multitude of gracious little houses clustering in college-like groups, no doubt about their common kitchens and halls, down and about the valley slopes. And there will be many more trees, and a great variety of trees—all the world will have been ransacked for winter conifers. Despite the height of the valley there will be a double avenue along the road. This high road with its tramway would turn with us to descend the gorge, and we should hesitate upon the adventure of boarding the train. But now we should have the memory of our landlord's curious eye upon us, and we should decide at last to defer the risk of explanations such an enterprise might precipitate.

We should head towards the Schoellenen gorge, and as we go, our fresh morning senses will pick up a thousand details about this more civilized world. A Modern Utopia will move past the chatter about nationality, so the ugly fortifications, barracks, and military ugliness of the earthly vale of Urseren will be absent. Instead, there will be a large number of charming little houses clustered in college-like groups, undoubtedly with shared kitchens and common areas, down the valley slopes. There will be many more trees, and a great variety of them—all the world will have been searched for winter conifers. Despite the valley’s height, there will be a double avenue along the road. This main road with its tramway will curve with us as we descend the gorge, and we might hesitate about the adventure of getting on the train. But now we would remember our landlord’s curious eye on us, and we would ultimately decide to put off the risk of the explanations this venture might lead to.

We should go by the great road for a time, and note something of the difference between Utopian and terrestrial engineering.

We should take the main road for a while and notice some of the differences between Utopian and real-world engineering.

The tramway, the train road, the culverts, and bridges, the Urnerloch tunnel, into which the road plunges, will all be beautiful things.

The tramway, the railway, the culverts and bridges, and the Urnerloch tunnel, where the road descends, will all be beautiful sights.

There is nothing in machinery, there is nothing in embankments and railways and iron bridges and engineering devices to oblige them to be ugly. Ugliness is the measure of imperfection; a thing of human making is for the most part ugly in proportion to the poverty of its constructive thought, to the failure of its producer fully to grasp the purpose of its being. Everything to which men continue to give thought and attention, which they make and remake in the same direction, and with a continuing desire to do as well as they can, grows beautiful inevitably. Things made by mankind under modern conditions are ugly, primarily because our social organisation is ugly, because we live in an atmosphere of snatch and uncertainty, and do everything in an underbred strenuous manner. This is the misfortune of machinery, and not its fault. Art, like some beautiful plant, lives on its atmosphere, and when the atmosphere is good, it will grow everywhere, and when it is bad nowhere. If we smashed and buried every machine, every furnace, every factory in the world, and without any further change set ourselves to home industries, hand labour, spade husbandry, sheep-folding and pig minding, we should still do things in the same haste, and achieve nothing but dirtiness, inconvenience, bad air, and another gaunt and gawky reflection of our intellectual and moral disorder. We should mend nothing.

There’s nothing about machinery, embankments, railways, iron bridges, and engineering devices that forces them to be ugly. Ugliness reflects imperfection; something made by humans is mostly ugly in proportion to the lack of thoughtful design and the creator’s failure to fully understand its purpose. Everything that deserves human thought and attention, that we continuously create and improve with a genuine desire to excel, inevitably becomes beautiful. The things we create under modern conditions are ugly mainly because our social structure is ugly, because we live in a chaotic and unpredictable atmosphere, and we approach everything in a rushed and unrefined manner. This is the unfortunate reality of machinery, not its fault. Art, like a beautiful plant, thrives on its environment; when the atmosphere is good, it flourishes everywhere, but when it’s bad, it doesn’t grow at all. If we were to destroy and bury every machine, furnace, and factory in the world, and without any further changes focused on home industries, manual labor, farming, and raising livestock, we would still act with the same urgency and achieve nothing but messiness, inconvenience, poor air quality, and a distorted reflection of our intellectual and moral chaos. We wouldn’t fix anything.

But in Utopia a man who designs a tram road will be a cultivated man, an artist craftsman; he will strive, as a good writer, or a painter strives, to achieve the simplicity of perfection. He will make his girders and rails and parts as gracious as that first engineer, Nature, has made the stems of her plants and the joints and gestures of her animals. To esteem him a sort of anti-artist, to count every man who makes things with his unaided thumbs an artist, and every man who uses machinery as a brute, is merely a passing phase of human stupidity. This tram road beside us will be a triumph of design. The idea will be so unfamiliar to us that for a time it will not occur to us that it is a system of beautiful objects at all. We shall admire its ingenious adaptation to the need of a district that is buried half the year in snow, the hard bed below, curved and guttered to do its own clearing, the great arched sleeper masses, raising the rails a good two yards above the ground, the easy, simple standards and insulators. Then it will creep in upon our minds, “But, by Jove! This is designed!

But in Utopia, a person who designs a tramway will be a refined individual, an artistic craftsman; they will strive, like a good writer or a painter, to achieve a straightforward form of perfection. They will create their girders, rails, and components as elegantly as Nature’s first engineer made the stems of her plants and the movements of her animals. To regard them as a sort of anti-artist, to think that every person who makes things with their bare hands is an artist while viewing anyone who uses machinery as a brute, is just a temporary phase of human ignorance. This tramway beside us will be a triumph of design. The concept will be so new to us that for a while, we won’t even realize that it’s a collection of beautiful objects. We will appreciate its clever adaptation to an area that is covered in snow for half the year, the solid base underneath, shaped and sloped to do its own clearing, the large curved sleeper masses lifting the rails a solid two yards off the ground, and the straightforward, uncomplicated standards and insulators. Then it will dawn on us, “But, wow! This is designed!

Indeed the whole thing will be designed.

Indeed, the whole thing will be designed.

Later on, perhaps, we may find students in an art school working in competition to design an electric tram, students who know something of modern metallurgy, and something of electrical engineering, and we shall find people as keenly critical of a signal box or an iron bridge as they are on earth of―! Heavens! what are they critical about on earth?

Later on, we might see students at an art school competing to design an electric tram, students who understand modern metallurgy and some electrical engineering, and we’ll find people just as critically engaged with a signal box or an iron bridge as they are about—Oh my! What are they actually critical about down here?

The quality and condition of a dress tie!

The quality and condition of a dress tie!

We should make some unpatriotic comparisons with our own planet, no doubt.

We should definitely make some unpatriotic comparisons with our own planet.

CHAPTER THE FOURTH
The Voice of Nature

§ 1

Presently we recognise the fellow of the earthly Devil's Bridge, still intact as a footway, spanning the gorge, and old memories turn us off the road down the steep ruin of an ancient mule track towards it. It is our first reminder that Utopia too must have a history. We cross it and find the Reuss, for all that it has already lit and warmed and ventilated and cleaned several thousands of houses in the dale above, and for all that it drives those easy trams in the gallery overhead, is yet capable of as fine a cascade as ever it flung on earth. So we come to a rocky path, wild as one could wish, and descend, discoursing how good and fair an ordered world may be, but with a certain unformulated qualification in our minds about those thumb marks we have left behind.

Right now, we see the bridge known as the Devil’s Bridge, still standing as a pathway across the gorge, and old memories lead us off the road down the steep, crumbling mule track towards it. It’s our first reminder that even Utopia must have a history. We cross the bridge and find the Reuss, which, despite already lighting, warming, ventilating, and cleaning thousands of homes in the valley above, and powering the convenient trams in the overhead gallery, is still capable of creating a stunning cascade as it always has. So we come to a rugged path, as wild as one could hope for, and make our way down, discussing how good and beautiful a well-ordered world can be, but with an unspoken hesitation in our minds about those thumbprints we’ve left behind.

“Do you recall the Zermatt valley?” says my friend, “and how on earth it reeks and stinks with smoke?”

“Do you remember the Zermatt valley?” my friend says, “and how it smells so bad from the smoke?”

“People make that an argument for obstructing change, instead of helping it forward!”

“People use that as a reason to block change, instead of supporting it!”

And here perforce an episode intrudes. We are invaded by a talkative person.

And here, an episode forces its way in. We are interrupted by a chatty person.

He overtakes us and begins talking forthwith in a fluty, but not unamiable, tenor. He is a great talker, this man, and a fairly respectable gesticulator, and to him it is we make our first ineffectual tentatives at explaining who indeed we are; but his flow of talk washes that all away again. He has a face of that rubicund, knobby type I have heard an indignant mineralogist speak of as botryoidal, and about it waves a quantity of disorderly blond hair. He is dressed in leather doublet and knee breeches, and he wears over these a streaming woollen cloak of faded crimson that give him a fine dramatic outline as he comes down towards us over the rocks. His feet, which are large and handsome, but bright pink with the keen morning air, are bare, except for sandals of leather. (It was the only time that we saw anyone in Utopia with bare feet.) He salutes us with a scroll-like waving of his stick, and falls in with our slower paces.

He passes us and starts talking right away in a smooth, but not unfriendly, voice. This guy is a real chatterbox and a decent gesticulator, and we attempt to explain who we are, but his constant talking washes that all away. He has a round, ruddy face that I've heard an angry mineralogist refer to as botryoidal, and his messy blond hair is all over the place. He's dressed in a leather jacket and knee-length pants, and over that, he wears a long, flowing wool cloak of faded crimson that gives him a dramatic look as he walks towards us over the rocks. His feet are large and attractive, but they’re bright pink from the chilly morning air, and he’s barefoot except for leather sandals. (This was the only time we saw anyone in Utopia with bare feet.) He greets us with a grand wave of his stick and matches our slower pace.

“Climbers, I presume?” he says, “and you scorn these trams of theirs? I like you. So do I! Why a man should consent to be dealt with as a bale of goods holding an indistinctive ticket—when God gave him legs and a face—passes my understanding.”

“Climbers, I assume?” he says. “And you look down on these trams of theirs? I like you. So do I! Why would a man agree to be treated like a piece of cargo with a generic ticket—when God gave him legs and a face—just doesn’t make sense to me.”

As he speaks, his staff indicates the great mechanical road that runs across the gorge and high overhead through a gallery in the rock, follows it along until it turns the corner, picks it up as a viaduct far below, traces it until it plunges into an arcade through a jutting crag, and there dismisses it with a spiral whirl. “No!” he says.

As he talks, his team points out the huge mechanical road that stretches across the gorge and high above through a tunnel in the rock. They follow it until it turns the corner, then pick it up as a viaduct far below, tracing it until it dives into an arcade through a jutting cliff, and there, it disappears with a spiral twist. “No!” he says.

He seems sent by Providence, for just now we had been discussing how we should broach our remarkable situation to these Utopians before our money is spent.

He seems sent by Providence, because just now we were talking about how we should bring up our unusual situation to these Utopians before we run out of money.

Our eyes meet, and I gather from the botanist that I am to open our case.

Our eyes connect, and I understand from the botanist that I'm supposed to open our case.

I do my best.

I do my best.

“You came from the other side of space!” says the man in the crimson cloak, interrupting me. “Precisely! I like that—it's exactly my note! So do I! And you find this world strange! Exactly my case! We are brothers! We shall be in sympathy. I am amazed, I have been amazed as long as I can remember, and I shall die, most certainly, in a state of incredulous amazement, at this remarkable world. Eh?... You found yourselves suddenly upon a mountain top! Fortunate men!” He chuckled. “For my part I found myself in the still stranger position of infant to two parents of the most intractable dispositions!”

“You came from the other side of space!” says the man in the crimson cloak, cutting me off. “Exactly! I love that—it’s totally my vibe! So do I! And you think this world is weird! Just like me! We’re like brothers! We’re going to vibe together. I’m blown away; I’ve been blown away for as long as I can remember, and I know I’ll definitely die in a state of total amazement at this incredible world. Right?... You found yourselves suddenly on a mountaintop! Lucky guys!” He laughed. “As for me, I ended up in the even weirder situation of being a baby born to two really stubborn parents!”

“The fact remains,” I protest.

"The fact is," I protest.

“A position, I can assure you, demanding Tact of an altogether superhuman quality!”

“A position, I can assure you, that requires a level of tact that's truly remarkable!”

We desist for a space from the attempt to explain our remarkable selves, and for the rest of the time this picturesque and exceptional Utopian takes the talk entirely under his control....

We take a break from trying to explain our remarkable selves, and for the rest of the time, this striking and unique Utopian completely takes charge of the conversation....

§ 2

An agreeable person, though a little distracting, he was, and he talked, we recall, of many things. He impressed us, we found afterwards, as a poseur beyond question, a conscious Ishmaelite in the world of wit, and in some subtly inexplicable way as a most consummate ass. He talked first of the excellent and commodious trams that came from over the passes, and ran down the long valley towards middle Switzerland, and of all the growth of pleasant homes and châlets amidst the heights that made the opening gorge so different from its earthly parallel, with a fine disrespect. “But they are beautiful,” I protested. “They are graciously proportioned, they are placed in well-chosen positions; they give no offence to the eye.”

He was a pleasant guy, a bit distracting, and he talked about a lot of things. Later on, we realized he was definitely a show-off, a self-aware outsider in the world of humor, and somehow, in a way that's hard to explain, he came off as a total fool. He first talked about the great trams that came over the mountains, running down the long valley toward central Switzerland, and how all the nice homes and chalets in the hills made the opening gorge feel so different from its earthly counterpart, with a touch of arrogance. "But they're beautiful," I argued. "They're nicely designed, put in great spots; they don't hurt the eye."

“What do we know of the beauty they replace? They are a mere rash. Why should we men play the part of bacteria upon the face of our Mother?”

“What do we know about the beauty they're taking away? They are just a nuisance. Why should we men act like bacteria on the face of our Mother?”

“All life is that!”

“All life is this!”

“No! not natural life, not the plants and the gentle creatures that live their wild shy lives in forest and jungle. That is a part of her. That is the natural bloom of her complexion. But these houses and tramways and things, all made from ore and stuff torn from her veins―! You can't better my image of the rash. It's a morbid breaking out! I'd give it all for one—what is it?—free and natural chamois.”

“No! Not natural life, not the plants and the gentle creatures that live their wild, shy lives in the forest and jungle. That’s part of her. That’s the natural glow of her complexion. But these houses, tramways, and things, all made from ore and stuff ripped from her veins—! You can't change my view of the rash. It's a sickly breakout! I'd trade it all for one—what is it?—free and natural chamois.”

“You live at times in a house?” I asked.

"You sometimes live in a house?" I asked.

He ignored my question. For him, untroubled Nature was the best, he said, and, with a glance at his feet, the most beautiful. He professed himself a Nazarite, and shook back his Teutonic poet's shock of hair. So he came to himself, and for the rest of our walk he kept to himself as the thread of his discourse, and went over himself from top to toe, and strung thereon all topics under the sun by way of illustrating his splendours. But especially his foil was the relative folly, the unnaturalness and want of logic in his fellow men. He held strong views about the extreme simplicity of everything, only that men, in their muddle-headedness, had confounded it all. “Hence, for example, these trams! They are always running up and down as though they were looking for the lost simplicity of nature. ‘We dropped it here!’” He earned a living, we gathered, “some considerable way above the minimum wage,” which threw a chance light on the labour problem—by perforating records for automatic musical machines—no doubt of the Pianotist and Pianola kind—and he spent all the leisure he could gain in going to and fro in the earth lecturing on “The Need of a Return to Nature,” and on “Simple Foods and Simple Ways.” He did it for the love of it. It was very clear to us he had an inordinate impulse to lecture, and esteemed us fair game. He had been lecturing on these topics in Italy, and he was now going back through the mountains to lecture in Saxony, lecturing on the way, to perforate a lot more records, lecturing the while, and so start out lecturing again. He was undisguisedly glad to have us to lecture to by the way.

He ignored my question. For him, untroubled nature was the best, he said, and, glancing at his feet, the most beautiful. He claimed to be a Nazarite and tossed back his Northern European poet's wild hair. So he found himself, and for the rest of our walk, he kept to himself as his thoughts flowed, going over himself from head to toe and stringing together all sorts of topics under the sun to illustrate his ideas. But his biggest contrast was the relative foolishness, the unnaturalness, and lack of logic in his fellow humans. He had strong opinions about the extreme simplicity of everything, saying that people, in their confusion, had mixed it all up. “Hence, for example, these trams! They constantly run back and forth as if they're searching for the lost simplicity of nature. ‘We left it here!’” We gathered that he earned a living “well above minimum wage,” which shed some light on the labor issue—by punching holes in records for automatic musical machines—likely of the Pianotist and Pianola kind—and he spent all his free time traveling around lecturing on “The Need for a Return to Nature” and “Simple Foods and Simple Ways.” He did it for the love of it. It was clear to us that he had an overwhelming urge to lecture and saw us as his audience. He had been giving talks on these topics in Italy, and now he was making his way back through the mountains to lecture in Saxony, lecturing along the way, to punch more records, and starting the cycle of lecturing all over again. He was openly delighted to have us to lecture to along the way.

He called our attention to his costume at an early stage. It was the embodiment of his ideal of Nature-clothing, and it had been made especially for him at very great cost. “Simply because naturalness has fled the earth, and has to be sought now, and washed out from your crushed complexities like gold.”

He drew our attention to his outfit early on. It was the perfect representation of his vision of nature-inspired clothing, and it had been made specifically for him at a significant expense. “Just because naturalness has disappeared from the earth, it now has to be sought after and extracted from your tangled complexities like gold.”

“I should have thought,” said I, “that any clothing whatever was something of a slight upon the natural man.”

“I should have thought,” I said, “that any clothes at all were a bit of an insult to our natural state.”

“Not at all,” said he, “not at all! You forget his natural vanity!”

“Not at all,” he said, “not at all! You’re forgetting his natural vanity!”

He was particularly severe on our artificial hoofs, as he called our boots, and our hats or hair destructors. “Man is the real King of Beasts and should wear a mane. The lion only wears it by consent and in captivity.” He tossed his head.

He was especially harsh about our fake hooves, as he called our boots, and our hats, or hair destroyers. “Man is the true King of Beasts and should have a mane. The lion only has one by permission and when in captivity.” He flipped his head.

Subsequently while we lunched and he waited for the specific natural dishes he ordered—they taxed the culinary resources of the inn to the utmost—he broached a comprehensive generalisation. “The animal kingdom and the vegetable kingdom are easily distinguished, and for the life of me I see no reason for confusing them. It is, I hold, a sin against Nature. I keep them distinct in my mind and I keep them distinct in my person. No animal substance inside, no vegetable without;—what could be simpler or more logical? Nothing upon me but leather and allwool garments, within, cereals, fruit, nuts, herbs, and the like. Classification—order—man's function. He is here to observe and accentuate Nature's simplicity. These people”—he swept an arm that tried not too personally to include us—“are filled and covered with confusion.”

While we had lunch and he waited for the specific natural dishes he ordered— which really pushed the inn's culinary skills to the limit—he brought up a broad idea. “The animal kingdom and the plant kingdom are easy to tell apart, and I honestly don’t see why anyone would mix them up. In my opinion, it’s a crime against Nature. I keep them separate in my mind and in my body. No animal products inside, no plants outside; what could be easier or more logical? I wear only leather and wool, and inside, I have grains, fruits, nuts, herbs, and so on. Classification—order—it's man's role. We're here to observe and highlight Nature's simplicity. These people”—he gestured broadly to include us—“are completely mixed up.”

He ate great quantities of grapes and finished with a cigarette. He demanded and drank a great horn of unfermented grape juice, and it seemed to suit him well.

He ate a lot of grapes and finished with a cigarette. He asked for and drank a large cup of unfermented grape juice, and it seemed to agree with him.

We three sat about the board—it was in an agreeable little arbour on a hill hard by the place where Wassen stands on earth, and it looked down the valley to the Uri Rothstock, and ever and again we sought to turn his undeniable gift of exposition to the elucidation of our own difficulties.

We three gathered around the table—it was in a cozy little nook on a hill near where Wassen is located, and it overlooked the valley toward the Uri Rothstock. Every now and then, we tried to use his undeniable talent for explaining things to help clarify our own challenges.

But we seemed to get little, his style was so elusive. Afterwards, indeed, we found much information and many persuasions had soaked into us, but at the time it seemed to us he told us nothing. He indicated things by dots and dashes, instead of by good hard assertive lines. He would not pause to see how little we knew. Sometimes his wit rose so high that he would lose sight of it himself, and then he would pause, purse his lips as if he whistled, and then till the bird came back to the lure, fill his void mouth with grapes. He talked of the relations of the sexes, and love—a passion he held in great contempt as being in its essence complex and disingenuous—and afterwards we found we had learnt much of what the marriage laws of Utopia allow and forbid.

But we felt like we got very little; his style was so hard to grasp. Later on, we realized that a lot of information and persuasive ideas had absorbed into us, but at that moment, it felt like he shared nothing. He signaled things with dots and dashes instead of clear, direct statements. He wouldn’t take a moment to see how little we understood. Sometimes his wit soared so high that he would lose track of it himself, and then he would stop, purse his lips like he was about to whistle, and while waiting for his thoughts to return, he’d fill his empty mouth with grapes. He talked about relationships between the sexes and love—a passion he looked down on as inherently complex and insincere—and later we discovered we had learned a lot about what the marriage laws of Utopia allow and prohibit.

“A simple natural freedom,” he said, waving a grape in an illustrative manner, and so we gathered the Modern Utopia did not at any rate go to that. He spoke, too, of the regulation of unions, of people who were not allowed to have children, of complicated rules and interventions. “Man,” he said, “had ceased to be a natural product!”

“A simple natural freedom,” he said, waving a grape as he spoke, and so we realized the Modern Utopia completely missed that point. He also talked about regulating unions, about people who weren’t allowed to have children, and about all the complicated rules and interventions. “Humans,” he said, “have stopped being a natural product!”

We tried to check him with questions at this most illuminating point, but he drove on like a torrent, and carried his topic out of sight. The world, he held, was overmanaged, and that was the root of all evil. He talked of the overmanagement of the world, and among other things of the laws that would not let a poor simple idiot, a “natural,” go at large. And so we had our first glimpse of what Utopia did with the feeble and insane. “We make all these distinctions between man and man, we exalt this and favour that, and degrade and seclude that; we make birth artificial, life artificial, death artificial.”

We tried to engage him with questions at this really revealing moment, but he kept going like a flood, and took his topic out of reach. He believed the world was overregulated, and that was the root of all problems. He spoke about how the world was overregulated, particularly about the laws that wouldn't allow a poor simple fool, a "natural," to be free. And so we got our first look at how Utopia treated the weak and insane. "We create all these distinctions between people, we elevate some and favor others, while degrading and isolating others; we make birth artificial, life artificial, death artificial."

“You say We,” said I, with the first glimmering of a new idea, “but you don't participate?”

“You say We,” I said, with the first hint of a new idea, “but you don't take part?”

“Not I! I'm not one of your samurai, your voluntary noblemen who have taken the world in hand. I might be, of course, but I'm not.”

“Not me! I'm not one of your samurai, your willing noblemen who have taken control of the world. I could be, but I'm not.”

Samurai!” I repeated, “voluntary noblemen!” and for the moment could not frame a question.

Samurai!” I said again, “voluntary noblemen!” and for the moment couldn’t come up with a question.

He whirled on to an attack on science, that stirred the botanist to controversy. He denounced with great bitterness all specialists whatever, and particularly doctors and engineers.

He turned to launch an attack on science, which fired up the botanist into a heated debate. He passionately criticized all specialists in general, especially doctors and engineers.

“Voluntary noblemen!” he said, “voluntary Gods I fancy they think themselves,” and I was left behind for a space in the perplexed examination of this parenthesis, while he and the botanist—who is sedulous to keep his digestion up to date with all the newest devices—argued about the good of medicine men.

“Voluntary nobles!” he said, “they probably think of themselves as voluntary gods.” I was momentarily left behind, puzzled by this aside, while he and the botanist—who is eager to keep his digestion current with all the latest techniques—debated the benefits of medicine men.

“The natural human constitution,” said the blond-haired man, “is perfectly simple, with one simple condition—you must leave it to Nature. But if you mix up things so distinctly and essentially separated as the animal and vegetable kingdoms for example, and ram that in for it to digest, what can you expect?

“The natural human constitution,” said the blond-haired man, “is really quite simple, with one straightforward rule—you have to let Nature take its course. But if you jumble together things that are clearly and fundamentally different, like the animal and plant kingdoms, and force that into it to process, what do you think will happen?”

“Ill health! There isn't such a thing—in the course of Nature. But you shelter from Nature in houses, you protect yourselves by clothes that are useful instead of being ornamental, you wash—with such abstersive chemicals as soap for example—and above all you consult doctors.” He approved himself with a chuckle. “Have you ever found anyone seriously ill without doctors and medicine about? Never! You say a lot of people would die without shelter and medical attendance! No doubt—but a natural death. A natural death is better than an artificial life, surely? That's—to be frank with you—the very citadel of my position.”

“Ill health! That doesn’t really exist in the natural world. But you protect yourselves from nature by living in houses, you wear clothes more for practicality than style, you wash with harsh chemicals like soap, and most importantly, you rely on doctors.” He chuckled to himself. “Have you ever seen anyone seriously ill without doctors and medicine around? Never! You claim a lot of people would die without shelter and medical care! Of course, but that would be a natural death. A natural death is better than an artificial life, right? That’s—honestly speaking—the foundation of my argument.”

That led him, and rather promptly, before the botanist could rally to reply, to a great tirade against the laws that forbade “sleeping out.” He denounced them with great vigour, and alleged that for his own part he broke that law whenever he could, found some corner of moss, shaded from an excess of dew, and there sat up to sleep. He slept, he said, always in a sitting position, with his head on his wrists, and his wrists on his knees—the simple natural position for sleep in man.... He said it would be far better if all the world slept out, and all the houses were pulled down.

That led him, and pretty quickly, before the botanist could gather his thoughts to respond, to launch into a passionate rant against the laws that banned “sleeping out.” He criticized them vigorously and claimed that he personally broke that law whenever he could, finding a patch of moss, sheltered from getting too dewy, where he would sit up to sleep. He said he always slept in a sitting position, with his head resting on his wrists and his wrists on his knees—the natural position for humans to sleep.... He argued that it would be much better if everyone slept outside and all the houses were torn down.

You will understand, perhaps, the subdued irritation I felt, as I sat and listened to the botanist entangling himself in the logical net of this wild nonsense. It impressed me as being irrelevant. When one comes to a Utopia one expects a Cicerone, one expects a person as precise and insistent and instructive as an American advertisement—the advertisement of one of those land agents, for example, who print their own engaging photographs to instil confidence and begin, “You want to buy real estate.” One expects to find all Utopians absolutely convinced of the perfection of their Utopia, and incapable of receiving a hint against its order. And here was this purveyor of absurdities!

You might understand the subtle irritation I felt as I sat and listened to the botanist getting tangled up in the logical mess of his wild nonsense. It struck me as irrelevant. When you arrive in a Utopia, you expect a guide; you expect someone as clear, persistent, and informative as an American ad—like one of those land agents who print their own appealing photos to build trust and start with, “You want to buy real estate.” You expect to find all Utopians completely convinced of their Utopia’s perfection and unable to take any criticism of its system. And here was this seller of absurdities!

And yet now that I come to think it over, is not this too one of the necessary differences between a Modern Utopia and those finite compact settlements of the older school of dreamers? It is not to be a unanimous world any more, it is to have all and more of the mental contrariety we find in the world of the real; it is no longer to be perfectly explicable, it is just our own vast mysterious welter, with some of the blackest shadows gone, with a clearer illumination, and a more conscious and intelligent will. Irrelevance is not irrelevant to such a scheme, and our blond-haired friend is exactly just where he ought to be here.

And now that I think about it, isn't this one of the key differences between a Modern Utopia and the smaller, more defined communities imagined by earlier dreamers? It won't be a world where everyone agrees; instead, it will embrace all the mental conflicts we see in the real world. It's not meant to be perfectly understandable anymore; it's our own vast and mysterious mixture, with some of the darkest shadows eliminated, better clarity, and a more aware and thoughtful intention. Irrelevance actually fits into this vision, and our blond-haired friend is exactly in the right place here.

Still―

Still—

§ 3

I ceased to listen to the argumentation of my botanist with this apostle of Nature. The botanist, in his scientific way, was, I believe, defending the learned professions. (He thinks and argues like drawing on squared paper.) It struck me as transiently remarkable that a man who could not be induced to forget himself and his personal troubles on coming into a whole new world, who could waste our first evening in Utopia upon a paltry egotistical love story, should presently become quite heated and impersonal in the discussion of scientific professionalism. He was—absorbed. I can't attempt to explain these vivid spots and blind spots in the imaginations of sane men; there they are!

I stopped paying attention to my botanist friend arguing with this advocate of Nature. The botanist, in his scientific way, was, I think, trying to defend the academic professions. (He thinks and argues like he's drawing on graph paper.) It struck me as oddly memorable that a man who couldn’t set aside his personal issues when entering a completely new world, who could waste our first evening in Utopia on a trivial, self-centered love story, could suddenly become really passionate and objective when discussing scientific professionalism. He was—totally absorbed. I can't begin to explain these vivid moments and blind spots in the minds of otherwise rational people; they just exist!

“You say,” said the botanist, with a prevalent index finger, and the resolute deliberation of a big siege gun being lugged into action over rough ground by a number of inexperienced men, “you prefer a natural death to an artificial life. But what is your definition (stress) of artificial?...”

“You say,” said the botanist, pointing his finger emphatically, like a heavy artillery piece being moved into position over bumpy terrain by a group of unskilled workers, “you’d rather have a natural death than a made-up life. But what’s your definition (emphasis) of artificial?...”

And after lunch too! I ceased to listen, flicked the end of my cigarette ash over the green trellis of the arbour, stretched my legs with a fine restfulness, leant back, and gave my mind to the fields and houses that lay adown the valley.

And after lunch too! I stopped paying attention, flicked the end of my cigarette ash over the green trellis of the arbor, stretched my legs with a nice sense of relaxation, leaned back, and focused my thoughts on the fields and houses that were down the valley.

What I saw interwove with fragmentary things our garrulous friend had said, and with the trend of my own speculations....

What I saw connected with the bits and pieces our chatty friend had mentioned, and with the direction of my own thoughts....

The high road, with its tramways and its avenues on either side, ran in a bold curve, and with one great loop of descent, down the opposite side of the valley, and below crossed again on a beautiful viaduct, and dipped into an arcade in the side of the Bristenstock. Our inn stood out boldly, high above the level this took. The houses clustered in their collegiate groups over by the high road, and near the subordinate way that ran almost vertically below us and past us and up towards the valley of the Meien Reuss. There were one or two Utopians cutting and packing the flowery mountain grass in the carefully levelled and irrigated meadows by means of swift, light machines that ran on things like feet and seemed to devour the herbage, and there were many children and a woman or so, going to and fro among the houses near at hand. I guessed a central building towards the high road must be the school from which these children were coming. I noted the health and cleanliness of these young heirs of Utopia as they passed below.

The main road, with its tram lines and tree-lined avenues on both sides, curved boldly and made a big loop as it descended on the opposite side of the valley. Below, it crossed again on a beautiful viaduct and dipped into an arcade built into the side of the Bristenstock. Our inn stood out prominently, high above where the road continued. The houses clustered together in their collegiate groups along the main road and near the secondary path that ran almost straight down below us and headed up towards the Meien Reuss valley. There were a couple of Utopians cutting and packing the grassy mountain meadows using swift, light machines that moved like feet and seemed to devour the vegetation. Many children and a few women wandered among the nearby houses. I figured the central building by the main road must be the school from which these children were returning. I noted the health and cleanliness of these young heirs of Utopia as they passed below.

The pervading quality of the whole scene was a sane order, the deliberate solution of problems, a progressive intention steadily achieving itself, and the aspect that particularly occupied me was the incongruity of this with our blond-haired friend.

The overall vibe of the scene was one of clear order, a careful approach to solving problems, and a forward-looking attitude consistently moving toward its goals. What really caught my attention, though, was how out of place it all felt with our blond-haired friend.

On the one hand here was a state of affairs that implied a power of will, an organising and controlling force, the co-operation of a great number of vigorous people to establish and sustain its progress, and on the other this creature of pose and vanity, with his restless wit, his perpetual giggle at his own cleverness, his manifest incapacity for comprehensive co-operation.

On one hand, there was a situation that suggested a strong will, an organizing and controlling force, and the collaboration of many energetic people to create and maintain its progress. On the other hand, there was this person of pretense and vanity, with his restless humor, his constant laughter at his own cleverness, and his clear inability to work together effectively.

Now, had I come upon a hopeless incompatibility? Was this the reductio ad absurdum of my vision, and must it even as I sat there fade, dissolve, and vanish before my eyes?

Now, had I encountered an impossible incompatibility? Was this the reductio ad absurdum of my vision, and must it, as I sat there, fade, dissolve, and disappear before my eyes?

There was no denying our blond friend. If this Utopia is indeed to parallel our earth, man for man—and I see no other reasonable choice to that—there must be this sort of person and kindred sorts of persons in great abundance. The desire and gift to see life whole is not the lot of the great majority of men, the service of truth is the privilege of the elect, and these clever fools who choke the avenues of the world of thought, who stick at no inconsistency, who oppose, obstruct, confuse, will find only the freer scope amidst Utopian freedoms.

There was no denying our blonde friend. If this Utopia is really going to mirror our world, man for man—and I see no other reasonable option—there has to be this type of person and similar individuals in large numbers. The ability and desire to see life as a whole isn’t something most people have; the pursuit of truth is a privilege for the select few. Those clever fools who clutter the pathways of thought, who have no problem with inconsistencies, who oppose, obstruct, and confuse, will only find more freedom in a Utopian society.

(They argued on, these two, as I worried my brains with riddles. It was like a fight between a cock sparrow and a tortoise; they both went on in their own way, regardless of each other's proceedings. The encounter had an air of being extremely lively, and the moments of contact were few. “But you mistake my point,” the blond man was saying, disordering his hair—which had become unruffled in the preoccupation of dispute—with a hasty movement of his hand, “you don't appreciate the position I take up.”)

(They kept arguing, these two, while I puzzled over riddles. It was like a fight between a sparrow and a tortoise; they both continued in their own way, ignoring each other’s moves. The encounter felt very lively, with only a few moments of real interaction. “But you’re missing my point,” the blonde guy was saying, running his hand through his hair—which had become tousled in the heat of the argument—“you don’t understand my position.”)

“Ugh!” said I privately, and lighted another cigarette and went away into my own thoughts with that.

“Ugh!” I said to myself, lit another cigarette, and slipped away into my own thoughts with that.

The position he takes up! That's the way of your intellectual fool, the Universe over. He takes up a position, and he's going to be the most brilliant, delightful, engaging and invincible of gay delicious creatures defending that position you can possibly imagine. And even when the case is not so bad as that, there still remains the quality. We “take up our positions,” silly little contentious creatures that we are, we will not see the right in one another, we will not patiently state and restate, and honestly accommodate and plan, and so we remain at sixes and sevens. We've all a touch of Gladstone in us, and try to the last moment to deny we have made a turn. And so our poor broken-springed world jolts athwart its trackless destiny. Try to win into line with some fellow weakling, and see the little host of suspicions, aggressions, misrepresentations, your approach will stir—like summer flies on a high road—the way he will try to score a point and claim you as a convert to what he has always said, his fear lest the point should be scored to you.

The stance he takes! That's the way of your intellectual fool everywhere. He picks a side and becomes the most brilliant, charming, engaging, and unbeatable of delightful creatures defending that stance you can imagine. Even when things aren’t as extreme, there’s still that quality. We "pick our sides," silly little argumentative beings that we are, refusing to see the good in one another, not willing to patiently explain and re-explain, and honestly come to terms and plan, which leaves us all confused. We all have a bit of Gladstone in us, and we try, until the very end, to deny that we’ve shifted. And so our poor, broken world bumps off its intended path. Try to get aligned with another weak person, and notice the flood of suspicions, hostilities, and misunderstandings your approach will provoke—like summer flies on a busy road—the way they will attempt to score points and claim you as a convert to their beliefs, fearing you might take that point for yourself.

It is not only such gross and palpable cases as our blond and tenoring friend. I could find the thing negligible were it only that. But when one sees the same thread woven into men who are leaders, men who sway vast multitudes, who are indeed great and powerful men; when one sees how unfair they can be, how unteachable, the great blind areas in their eyes also, their want of generosity, then one's doubts gather like mists across this Utopian valley, its vistas pale, its people become unsubstantial phantoms, all its order and its happiness dim and recede....

It's not just obvious and extreme cases like our blond and singing friend. I could overlook it if it were only that. But when you notice the same pattern in men who are leaders, those who influence large crowds, who are truly great and powerful; when you see how unfair they can be, how unwilling to learn, the significant blind spots in their perspectives, their lack of generosity, then your doubts start to roll in like fog across this ideal valley, its views become dull, its people turn into insubstantial shadows, and all its order and happiness fade away....

If we are to have any Utopia at all, we must have a clear common purpose, and a great and steadfast movement of will to override all these incurably egotistical dissentients. Something is needed wide and deep enough to float the worst of egotisms away. The world is not to be made right by acclamation and in a day, and then for ever more trusted to run alone. It is manifest this Utopia could not come about by chance and anarchy, but by co-ordinated effort and a community of design, and to tell of just land laws and wise government, a wisely balanced economic system, and wise social arrangements without telling how it was brought about, and how it is sustained against the vanity and self-indulgence, the moody fluctuations and uncertain imaginations, the heat and aptitude for partisanship that lurk, even when they do not flourish, in the texture of every man alive, is to build a palace without either door or staircase.

If we're going to have any kind of Utopia, we need a clear common goal and a strong, determined effort to overcome all these inherently selfish dissenters. We need something broad and deep enough to lift away the worst of egotism. The world can’t be fixed with a simple vote or in one day, only to be left to run itself forever after. It’s clear that this Utopia won’t happen by chance or chaos, but through coordinated effort and a unified vision. To talk about fair land laws and wise governance, a well-balanced economic system, and thoughtful social arrangements without explaining how it all came to be and how it’s maintained against the vanity and self-indulgence, the unpredictable mood swings and uncertain ideas, the passion and tendencies for partisanship that exist, even if they’re not always visible, in every person, is like building a palace without doors or stairs.

I had not this in mind when I began.

I didn't have this in mind when I started.

Somewhere in the Modern Utopia there must be adequate men, men the very antithesis of our friend, capable of self-devotion, of intentional courage, of honest thought, and steady endeavour. There must be a literature to embody their common idea, of which this Modern Utopia is merely the material form; there must be some organisation, however slight, to keep them in touch one with the other.

Somewhere in the Modern Utopia, there must be capable individuals, the complete opposite of our friend, who can demonstrate selflessness, intentional bravery, honest thinking, and consistent effort. There must be a body of literature that represents their shared ideas, of which this Modern Utopia is just the tangible version; there must be some form of organization, however minimal, to keep them connected with each other.

Who will these men be? Will they be a caste? a race? an organisation in the nature of a Church? ... And there came into my mind the words of our acquaintance, that he was not one of these “voluntary noblemen.”

Who will these men be? Will they be a caste? a race? an organization like a Church? ... And I remembered the words of our friend, that he was not one of these “voluntary noblemen.”

At first that phrase struck me as being merely queer, and then I began to realise certain possibilities that were wrapped up in it.

At first, that phrase seemed just strange to me, but then I started to see certain possibilities that were hidden within it.

The animus of our chance friend, at any rate, went to suggest that here was his antithesis. Evidently what he is not, will be the class to contain what is needed here. Evidently.

The attitude of our random acquaintance clearly hinted that he saw this as his opposite. Obviously, what he isn’t will be the type that includes what’s needed here. Clearly.

§ 4

I was recalled from my meditations by the hand of the blond-haired man upon my arm.

I was pulled out of my thoughts by the blond-haired man touching my arm.

I looked up to discover the botanist had gone into the inn.

I looked up to see that the botanist had gone into the inn.

The blond-haired man was for a moment almost stripped of pose.

The blond-haired man was momentarily almost without pretense.

“I say,” he said. “Weren't you listening to me?”

“I say,” he said. “Weren't you paying attention to me?”

“No,” I said bluntly.

“No,” I said flatly.

His surprise was manifest. But by an effort he recalled what he had meant to say.

His surprise was obvious. But with some effort, he remembered what he had intended to say.

“Your friend,” he said, “has been telling me, in spite of my sustained interruptions, a most incredible story.”

“Your friend,” he said, “has been telling me, despite my constant interruptions, a really unbelievable story.”

I wondered how the botanist managed to get it in. “About that woman?” I said.

I was curious how the botanist got it inside. “About that woman?” I asked.

“About a man and a woman who hate each other and can't get away from each other.”

“About a guy and a girl who can't stand each other but can't escape from one another.”

“I know,” I said.

"I know," I replied.

“It sounds absurd.”

"That sounds ridiculous."

“It is.”

"It is."

“Why can't they get away? What is there to keep them together? It's ridiculous. I―”

“Why can’t they escape? What’s holding them together? It’s ridiculous. I―”

“Quite.”

"Definitely."

“He would tell it to me.”

“He would tell me.”

“It's his way.”

“That's just how he is.”

“He interrupted me. And there's no point in it. Is he―” he hesitated, “mad?”

“He interrupted me. And there's no point in it. Is he—” he hesitated, “crazy?”

“There's a whole world of people mad with him,” I answered after a pause.

"There's a whole world of people angry with him," I replied after a pause.

The perplexed expression of the blond-haired man intensified. It is vain to deny that he enlarged the scope of his inquiry, visibly if not verbally. “Dear me!” he said, and took up something he had nearly forgotten. “And you found yourselves suddenly on a mountain side?... I thought you were joking.”

The confused look on the blond-haired guy deepened. It’s pointless to deny that he broadened his questions, obviously if not aloud. “Wow!” he said, picking up something he had almost forgotten. “And you guys suddenly found yourselves on a mountainside?... I thought you were kidding.”

I turned round upon him with a sudden access of earnestness. At least I meant my manner to be earnest, but to him it may have seemed wild.

I turned to him suddenly with intense seriousness. I intended my approach to be sincere, but to him, it might have seemed a bit crazy.

“You,” I said, “are an original sort of man. Do not be alarmed. Perhaps you will understand.... We were not joking.”

“You,” I said, “are a unique kind of guy. Don’t freak out. Maybe you’ll get it... We weren’t joking.”

“But, my dear fellow!”

"But, my friend!"

“I mean it! We come from an inferior world! Like this, but out of order.”

“I mean it! We come from a lesser world! Like this, but messed up.”

“No world could be more out of order―”

“No world could be more chaotic―”

“You play at that and have your fun. But there's no limit to the extent to which a world of men may get out of gear. In our world―”

“You play around and enjoy yourself. But there's no end to how much a world of men can fall apart. In our world―”

He nodded, but his eye had ceased to be friendly.

He nodded, but his expression had turned unfriendly.

“Men die of starvation; people die by the hundred thousand needlessly and painfully; men and women are lashed together to make hell for each other; children are born—abominably, and reared in cruelty and folly; there is a thing called war, a horror of blood and vileness. The whole thing seems to me at times a cruel and wasteful wilderness of muddle. You in this decent world have no means of understanding―”

“People die from starvation; thousands suffer and die for no reason; men and women are forced together, creating a living nightmare for each other; children are born—horribly, and raised in pain and ignorance; war exists, a terrifying reality filled with bloodshed and brutality. Sometimes, it all seems like a cruel and wasteful mess. You in this decent world have no way of understanding—”

“No?” he said, and would have begun, but I went on too quickly.

“No?” he said, and was about to start, but I interrupted him.

“No! When I see you dandering through this excellent and hopeful world, objecting, obstructing, and breaking the law, displaying your wit on science and order, on the men who toil so ingloriously to swell and use the knowledge that is salvation, this salvation for which our poor world cries to heaven―”

“No! When I see you wandering through this amazing and hopeful world, complaining, obstructing, and breaking the law, showcasing your cleverness about science and order, and the people who work so hard to grow and use the knowledge that brings salvation, this salvation our poor world desperately needs—”

“You don't mean to say,” he said, “that you really come from some other world where things are different and worse?”

“You're not saying,” he said, “that you actually come from another world where everything is different and worse?”

“I do.”

"I do."

“And you want to talk to me about it instead of listening to me?”

“And you want to talk to me about it instead of actually listening to me?”

“Yes.”

“Yep.”

“Oh, nonsense!” he said abruptly. “You can't do it—really. I can assure you this present world touches the nadir of imbecility. You and your friend, with his love for the lady who's so mysteriously tied—you're romancing! People could not possibly do such things. It's—if you'll excuse me—ridiculous. He began—he would begin. A most tiresome story—simply bore me down. We'd been talking very agreeably before that, or rather I had, about the absurdity of marriage laws, the interference with a free and natural life, and so on, and suddenly he burst like a dam. No!” He paused. “It's really impossible. You behave perfectly well for a time, and then you begin to interrupt.... And such a childish story, too!”

“Oh, come on!” he said suddenly. “You can't actually believe that—seriously. I can promise you this world is at its lowest point of stupidity. You and your friend, with his crush on that woman who's so mysteriously tied up—you're just fantasizing! People just can't do things like that. It's—if you don't mind me saying—absurd. He started—he would start. A really boring story—just wearied me out. We had been having a nice conversation before that, or rather I was, about the ridiculousness of marriage laws, how they interfere with a free and natural life, and so on, and suddenly he just lost it. No!” He paused. “It's just unbelievable. You can act perfectly fine for a while, and then you start interrupting.... And such a childish story, too!”

He spun round upon his chair, got up, glanced at me over his shoulder, and walked out of the arbour. He stepped aside hastily to avoid too close an approach to the returning botanist. “Impossible,” I heard him say. He was evidently deeply aggrieved by us. I saw him presently a little way off in the garden, talking to the landlord of our inn, and looking towards us as he talked—they both looked towards us—and after that, without the ceremony of a farewell, he disappeared, and we saw him no more. We waited for him a little while, and then I expounded the situation to the botanist....

He spun around in his chair, got up, glanced at me over his shoulder, and walked out of the arbor. He quickly moved aside to avoid getting too close to the returning botanist. "Impossible," I heard him say. He was clearly very upset with us. I saw him a short distance away in the garden, talking to the landlord of our inn and looking in our direction as he spoke—they both looked at us—and then, without saying goodbye, he disappeared, and we didn't see him again. We waited for him for a little while, and then I explained the situation to the botanist....

“We are going to have a very considerable amount of trouble explaining ourselves,” I said in conclusion. “We are here by an act of the imagination, and that is just one of those metaphysical operations that are so difficult to make credible. We are, by the standard of bearing and clothing I remark about us, unattractive in dress and deportment. We have nothing to produce to explain our presence here, no bit of a flying machine or a space travelling sphere or any of the apparatus customary on these occasions. We have no means beyond a dwindling amount of small change out of a gold coin, upon which I suppose in ethics and the law some native Utopian had a better claim. We may already have got ourselves into trouble with the authorities with that confounded number of yours!”

“We're going to have a lot of trouble explaining ourselves,” I said in conclusion. “We're here because of an act of imagination, and that’s one of those metaphysical things that are really hard to make believable. By the way we look and dress, we aren't exactly appealing in our appearance or behavior. We have nothing to show for our presence here, no flying machine or space travel sphere or any of the usual gear for situations like this. All we have is a small amount of change from a gold coin, which I assume some local Utopian has more right to ethically and legally. We might have already gotten ourselves in trouble with the authorities because of that ridiculous number of yours!”

“You did one too!”

"You did one too!"

“All the more bother, perhaps, when the thing is brought home to us. There's no need for recriminations. The thing of moment is that we find ourselves in the position—not to put too fine a point upon it—of tramps in this admirable world. The question of all others of importance to us at present is what do they do with their tramps? Because sooner or later, and the balance of probability seems to incline to sooner, whatever they do with their tramps that they will do with us.”

“All the more hassle, perhaps, when it really hits home. There’s no need for blame. What matters is that we find ourselves in the position—no sugarcoating here—of being outcasts in this great world. The most important question for us right now is, what do they do with their outcasts? Because sooner or later, and it seems more likely to be sooner, whatever they do with their outcasts, they will do with us.”

“Unless we can get some work.”

“Unless we can find some work.”

“Exactly—unless we can get some work.”

"Exactly—unless we can find some work."

“Get work!”

“Get a job!”

The botanist leant forward on his arms and looked out of the arbour with an expression of despondent discovery. “I say,” he remarked; “this is a strange world—quite strange and new. I'm only beginning to realise just what it means for us. The mountains there are the same, the old Bristenstock and all the rest of it; but these houses, you know, and that roadway, and the costumes, and that machine that is licking up the grass there—only....”

The botanist leaned forward on his arms and looked out of the arbor with a look of hopeless discovery. “I mean,” he said, “this is a weird world—really weird and new. I'm just starting to understand what it means for us. The mountains over there are the same, the old Bristenstock and everything else; but these houses, you know, and that road, and the clothes people are wearing, and that machine that’s mowing the grass over there—only....”

He sought expression. “Who knows what will come in sight round the bend of the valley there? Who knows what may happen to us anywhere? We don't know who rules over us even ... we don't know that!”

He wanted to express himself. “Who knows what we'll see around the bend of the valley? Who knows what could happen to us anywhere? We don’t even know who’s in charge of us... we don’t know that!”

“No,” I echoed, “we don't know that.”

“No,” I echoed, “we don’t know that.”

CHAPTER THE FIFTH
Failure in a Modern Utopia

§ 1

The old Utopias—save for the breeding schemes of Plato and Campanella—ignored that reproductive competition among individualities which is the substance of life, and dealt essentially with its incidentals. The endless variety of men, their endless gradation of quality, over which the hand of selection plays, and to which we owe the unmanageable complication of real life, is tacitly set aside. The real world is a vast disorder of accidents and incalculable forces in which men survive or fail. A Modern Utopia, unlike its predecessors, dare not pretend to change the last condition; it may order and humanise the conflict, but men must still survive or fail.

The old Utopias—except for the breeding ideas of Plato and Campanella—overlooked the competition in reproduction among individuals, which is the essence of life, and focused primarily on secondary aspects. They ignored the endless variety of people and the continuous range of qualities that selection influences, which contribute to the complex reality of life. The real world is a vast chaos of random events and unpredictable forces where people thrive or struggle. A Modern Utopia, unlike its predecessors, cannot pretend to change this fundamental reality; it can organize and make the conflict more humane, but people will still either thrive or struggle.

Most Utopias present themselves as going concerns, as happiness in being; they make it an essential condition that a happy land can have no history, and all the citizens one is permitted to see are well looking and upright and mentally and morally in tune. But we are under the dominion of a logic that obliges us to take over the actual population of the world with only such moral and mental and physical improvements as lie within their inherent possibilities, and it is our business to ask what Utopia will do with its congenital invalids, its idiots and madmen, its drunkards and men of vicious mind, its cruel and furtive souls, its stupid people, too stupid to be of use to the community, its lumpish, unteachable and unimaginative people? And what will it do with the man who is “poor” all round, the rather spiritless, rather incompetent low-grade man who on earth sits in the den of the sweater, tramps the streets under the banner of the unemployed, or trembles—in another man's cast-off clothing, and with an infinity of hat-touching—on the verge of rural employment?

Most Utopias present themselves as thriving places of happiness; they claim that a happy land must have no history, and all the citizens we’re allowed to see are attractive, upright, and mentally and morally aligned. But we're bound by a logic that requires us to accept the actual population of the world with only the moral, mental, and physical improvements that they can inherently achieve. We should ask what Utopia will do with its natural invalids, its people with mental disabilities, its alcoholics, its cruel and sneaky individuals, its foolish people—those too dim-witted to contribute to the community, its sluggish, unteachable, and unimaginative members. And what will it do with the man who is “poor” all around, the somewhat spiritless, somewhat inept low-grade individual who, in reality, is stuck in the grip of exploitation, wandering the streets as part of the unemployed, or barely scraping by in someone else's discarded clothes, nervously hoping for rural work?

These people will have to be in the descendant phase, the species must be engaged in eliminating them; there is no escape from that, and conversely the people of exceptional quality must be ascendant. The better sort of people, so far as they can be distinguished, must have the fullest freedom of public service, and the fullest opportunity of parentage. And it must be open to every man to approve himself worthy of ascendency.

These individuals will need to be in a lower phase, as the species must be focused on eliminating them; there's no way around that. In contrast, exceptional individuals must be on the rise. The best people, as much as they can be recognized, should have the greatest freedom to serve publicly and the best opportunities for parenthood. And every man should have the chance to prove himself worthy of advancement.

The way of Nature in this process is to kill the weaker and the sillier, to crush them, to starve them, to overwhelm them, using the stronger and more cunning as her weapon. But man is the unnatural animal, the rebel child of Nature, and more and more does he turn himself against the harsh and fitful hand that reared him. He sees with a growing resentment the multitude of suffering ineffectual lives over which his species tramples in its ascent. In the Modern Utopia he will have set himself to change the ancient law. No longer will it be that failures must suffer and perish lest their breed increase, but the breed of failure must not increase, lest they suffer and perish, and the race with them.

The natural way of things is to eliminate the weak and foolish, to crush them, starve them, and overpower them, using the stronger and smarter as tools. But humans are the unnatural beings, the defiant offspring of nature, and increasingly, they turn against the harsh and unpredictable forces that brought them into existence. They observe with growing resentment the countless suffering lives that their species steps over in its rise. In the Modern Utopia, they will have set out to change the old rule. No longer will failures need to suffer and die to prevent their numbers from growing, but rather, the presence of failure must be limited to prevent suffering and death, along with the entire species.

Now we need not argue here to prove that the resources of the world and the energy of mankind, were they organised sanely, are amply sufficient to supply every material need of every living human being. And if it can be so contrived that every human being shall live in a state of reasonable physical and mental comfort, without the reproduction of inferior types, there is no reason whatever why that should not be secured. But there must be a competition in life of some sort to determine who are to be pushed to the edge, and who are to prevail and multiply. Whatever we do, man will remain a competitive creature, and though moral and intellectual training may vary and enlarge his conception of success and fortify him with refinements and consolations, no Utopia will ever save him completely from the emotional drama of struggle, from exultations and humiliations, from pride and prostration and shame. He lives in success and failure just as inevitably as he lives in space and time.

Now, we don’t need to argue here to show that the world’s resources and human energy, if organized properly, are more than enough to meet every material need of every living person. If we can ensure that everyone lives in a state of reasonable physical and mental comfort, without producing inferior types, there’s no reason why that can’t be achieved. However, there has to be some form of competition in life to decide who gets to thrive and who ends up on the margins. No matter what we do, humans will always be competitive beings, and while moral and intellectual training might broaden their understanding of success and equip them with more refined views and comforts, no perfect society will ever completely shield them from the emotional struggles that come with life—exultation and humiliation, pride and shame. They will experience both success and failure just as inevitably as they exist in space and time.

But we may do much to make the margin of failure endurable. On earth, for all the extravagance of charity, the struggle for the mass of men at the bottom resolves itself into a struggle, and often a very foul and ugly struggle, for food, shelter, and clothing. Deaths outright from exposure and starvation are now perhaps uncommon, but for the multitude there are only miserable houses, uncomfortable clothes, and bad and insufficient food; fractional starvation and exposure, that is to say. A Utopia planned upon modern lines will certainly have put an end to that. It will insist upon every citizen being being properly housed, well nourished, and in good health, reasonably clean and clothed healthily, and upon that insistence its labour laws will be founded. In a phrasing that will be familiar to everyone interested in social reform, it will maintain a standard of life. Any house, unless it be a public monument, that does not come up to its rising standard of healthiness and convenience, the Utopian State will incontinently pull down, and pile the material and charge the owner for the labour; any house unduly crowded or dirty, it must in some effectual manner, directly or indirectly, confiscate and clear and clean. And any citizen indecently dressed, or ragged and dirty, or publicly unhealthy, or sleeping abroad homeless, or in any way neglected or derelict, must come under its care. It will find him work if he can and will work, it will take him to it, it will register him and lend him the money wherewith to lead a comely life until work can be found or made for him, and it will give him credit and shelter him and strengthen him if he is ill. In default of private enterprises it will provide inns for him and food, and it will—by itself acting as the reserve employer—maintain a minimum wage which will cover the cost of a decent life. The State will stand at the back of the economic struggle as the reserve employer of labour. This most excellent idea does, as a matter of fact, underlie the British institution of the workhouse, but it is jumbled up with the relief of old age and infirmity, it is administered parochially and on the supposition that all population is static and localised whereas every year it becomes more migratory; it is administered without any regard to the rising standards of comfort and self-respect in a progressive civilisation, and it is administered grudgingly. The thing that is done is done as unwilling charity by administrators who are often, in the rural districts at least, competing for low-priced labour, and who regard want of employment as a crime. But if it were possible for any citizen in need of money to resort to a place of public employment as a right, and there work for a week or month without degradation upon certain minimum terms, it seems fairly certain that no one would work, except as the victim of some quite exceptional and temporary accident, for less.

But we can do a lot to make failure more bearable. On earth, despite all the generosity of charity, the vast majority of people at the bottom are fighting, often in a very dirty and unpleasant way, for food, shelter, and clothing. While outright deaths from exposure and starvation may be rare now, many still live in miserable homes, wearing uncomfortable clothes, and eating poor and insufficient food; they experience what could be called fractional starvation and exposure. A Utopia envisioned with modern principles would definitely put an end to that. It would require that every citizen is properly housed, well-fed, in good health, reasonably clean, and dressed in a healthy way, and this requirement would form the basis of its labor laws. In terms familiar to anyone interested in social reform, it would uphold a standard of living. Any house, unless it is a public landmark, that doesn't meet its rising standard of health and comfort, would be immediately torn down by the Utopian State, which would clear the debris and charge the owner for the labor; any house that is overcrowded or filthy must be confiscated, cleared, and cleaned in some effective way, whether directly or indirectly. Any citizen who is poorly dressed, ragged, dirty, unhealthy, homeless, or in any way neglected must be cared for. The state would find them work if they are able and willing to work, assist them in finding it, register them, and lend them the money needed to live a decent life until they can find or create work, and it would provide credit and shelter them if they are ill. If private enterprises fail, it would offer inns and food, and it would act as the backup employer, ensuring a minimum wage that covers the cost of a decent life. The State would support individuals in the economic struggle as the backup employer of labor. This excellent idea actually underpins the British workhouse system, but it’s mixed up with support for the elderly and disabled, administered locally and based on the outdated idea that population is static and localized, when in fact it becomes increasingly mobile each year; it also ignores the rising standards of comfort and dignity in a progressive society, and it is delivered begrudgingly. The actions taken are seen as unwilling charity by officials who often, especially in rural areas, compete for low-priced labor and view unemployment as a failure. However, if any citizen in need of money could go to a public employment center as a right and work there for a week or a month under certain minimum conditions without feeling degraded, it’s likely that no one would settle for less, unless they were facing some unusual and temporary situation.

The work publicly provided would have to be toilsome, but not cruel or incapacitating. A choice of occupations would need to be afforded, occupations adapted to different types of training and capacity, with some residual employment of a purely laborious and mechanical sort for those who were incapable of doing the things that required intelligence. Necessarily this employment by the State would be a relief of economic pressure, but it would not be considered a charity done to the individual, but a public service. It need not pay, any more than the police need pay, but it could probably be done at a small margin of loss. There is a number of durable things bound finally to be useful that could be made and stored whenever the tide of more highly paid employment ebbed and labour sank to its minimum, bricks, iron from inferior ores, shaped and preserved timber, pins, nails, plain fabrics of cotton and linen, paper, sheet glass, artificial fuel, and so on; new roads could be made and public buildings reconstructed, inconveniences of all sorts removed, until under the stimulus of accumulating material, accumulating investments or other circumstances, the tide of private enterprise flowed again.

The work provided to the public would need to be hard but not harsh or debilitating. There should be a range of job options available, suited to different skills and training, including some purely labor-intensive jobs for those unable to perform tasks that require intelligence. This government employment would relieve economic stress, but it wouldn't be seen as charity for individuals; rather, it would be viewed as a public service. It wouldn’t necessarily need to pay, just like the police don’t, but it could likely operate at a small loss. There are many durable goods that could be made and stored for future use when higher-paying jobs are scarce; things like bricks, iron from lower-quality ores, shaped and preserved wood, pins, nails, basic cotton and linen fabrics, paper, sheet glass, artificial fuel, and so on. New roads could be built and public buildings repaired, removing various inconveniences, until the spark of accumulating resources, investments, or other factors reignites private enterprise.

The State would provide these things for its citizen as though it was his right to require them; he would receive as a shareholder in the common enterprise and not with any insult of charity. But on the other hand it will require that the citizen who renders the minimum of service for these concessions shall not become a parent until he is established in work at a rate above the minimum, and free of any debt he may have incurred. The State will never press for its debt, nor put a limit to its accumulation so long as a man or woman remains childless; it will not even grudge them temporary spells of good fortune when they may lift their earnings above the minimum wage. It will pension the age of everyone who cares to take a pension, and it will maintain special guest homes for the very old to which they may come as paying guests, spending their pensions there. By such obvious devices it will achieve the maximum elimination of its feeble and spiritless folk in every generation with the minimum of suffering and public disorder.

The State would provide these things for its citizens as if it were their right to demand them; they would receive them as a stakeholder in a shared endeavor, not as an act of charity. However, it will require that citizens who only contribute the bare minimum for these benefits should not become parents until they have secured a job that pays above the minimum wage and are free of any debts. The State will never demand repayment of its debts, nor place limits on their accumulation as long as a man or woman remains childless; it won't even resent them for temporary bursts of good luck that raise their earnings above the minimum wage. It will provide pensions for anyone who wants one, and it will maintain special retirement homes for the elderly, where they can stay as paying guests, using their pensions. Through these straightforward measures, it aims to maximize the reduction of its weaker and less spirited individuals in every generation with as little suffering and social unrest as possible.

§ 2

But the mildly incompetent, the spiritless and dull, the poorer sort who are ill, do not exhaust our Utopian problem. There remain idiots and lunatics, there remain perverse and incompetent persons, there are people of weak character who become drunkards, drug takers, and the like. Then there are persons tainted with certain foul and transmissible diseases. All these people spoil the world for others. They may become parents, and with most of them there is manifestly nothing to be done but to seclude them from the great body of the population. You must resort to a kind of social surgery. You cannot have social freedom in your public ways, your children cannot speak to whom they will, your girls and gentle women cannot go abroad while some sorts of people go free. And there are violent people, and those who will not respect the property of others, thieves and cheats, they, too, so soon as their nature is confirmed, must pass out of the free life of our ordered world. So soon as there can be no doubt of the disease or baseness of the individual, so soon as the insanity or other disease is assured, or the crime repeated a third time, or the drunkenness or misdemeanour past its seventh occasion (let us say), so soon must he or she pass out of the common ways of men.

But the somewhat inept, the uninspired and uninteresting, the poorer individuals who are unwell, do not solve our Utopian dilemma. There are still idiots and the mentally ill, there are twisted and incapable people, and those with weak character who turn into alcoholics, drug users, and the like. Then there are individuals affected by certain vile and contagious diseases. All these people make the world less pleasant for others. They might become parents, and with most of them, there is clearly nothing we can do except to isolate them from the larger population. You have to perform a kind of social surgery. You can't have social freedom in your public spaces, your children can't talk to whoever they want, and your girls and ladies can't go out freely while some types of people live unrestricted. And there are violent people, and those who won't respect other people's property—thieves and con artists—who, as soon as their nature is set, must be removed from the free life of our organized society. As soon as there’s no doubt about the individual’s illness or moral failing, as soon as the insanity or other disorder is confirmed, or the crime is repeated for the third time, or the drunkenness or misbehavior has happened more than seven times (for example), then they must be excluded from the common paths of society.

The dreadfulness of all such proposals as this lies in the possibility of their execution falling into the hands of hard, dull, and cruel administrators. But in the case of a Utopia one assumes the best possible government, a government as merciful and deliberate as it is powerful and decisive. You must not too hastily imagine these things being done—as they would be done on earth at present—by a number of zealous half-educated people in a state of panic at a quite imaginary “Rapid Multiplication of the Unfit.”

The awful thing about all these proposals is that they could end up being executed by harsh, unimaginative, and cruel officials. But when we think about a Utopia, we imagine the best possible government—one that is as compassionate and thoughtful as it is strong and decisive. Don't be too quick to picture these actions being taken—like they would be on Earth today—by a group of eager but poorly educated people in a frenzy over a totally made-up "Rapid Multiplication of the Unfit."

No doubt for first offenders, and for all offenders under five-and-twenty, the Modern Utopia will attempt cautionary and remedial treatment. There will be disciplinary schools and colleges for the young, fair and happy places, but with less confidence and more restraint than the schools and colleges of the ordinary world. In remote and solitary regions these enclosures will lie, they will be fenced in and forbidden to the common run of men, and there, remote from all temptation, the defective citizen will be schooled. There will be no masking of the lesson; “which do you value most, the wide world of humanity, or this evil trend in you?” From that discipline at last the prisoners will return.

No doubt for first-time offenders, and for all offenders under twenty-five, the Modern Utopia will try cautionary and rehabilitative measures. There will be disciplinary schools and colleges for young people, nice and pleasant places, but with less leniency and more discipline than the schools and colleges in the ordinary world. These facilities will be located in remote and isolated areas, fenced off and off-limits to the general public, where, away from all temptation, the troubled citizens will receive their education. The lesson won’t be sugar-coated: “What do you value more, the vast world of humanity, or this negative tendency within you?” Eventually, from that discipline, the prisoners will reintegrate into society.

But the others; what would a saner world do with them?

But what would a more rational world do with the others?

Our world is still vindictive, but the all-reaching State of Utopia will have the strength that begets mercy. Quietly the outcast will go from among his fellow men. There will be no drumming of him out of the ranks, no tearing off of epaulettes, no smiting in the face. The thing must be just public enough to obviate secret tyrannies, and that is all.

Our world is still harsh, but the all-encompassing State of Utopia will possess the strength that inspires compassion. Quietly, the outcast will part ways with their fellow humans. There won't be any public shaming, no stripping of titles, no violence. It just needs to be open enough to prevent hidden abuses of power, and that's it.

There would be no killing, no lethal chambers. No doubt Utopia will kill all deformed and monstrous and evilly diseased births, but for the rest, the State will hold itself accountable for their being. There is no justice in Nature perhaps, but the idea of justice must be sacred in any good society. Lives that statesmanship has permitted, errors it has not foreseen and educated against, must not be punished by death. If the State does not keep faith, no one will keep faith. Crime and bad lives are the measure of a State's failure, all crime in the end is the crime of the community. Even for murder Utopia will not, I think, kill.

There won't be any killing or execution chambers. Sure, Utopia will eliminate all deformed, monstrous, and severely diseased births, but for everyone else, the State will take responsibility for their existence. Nature may not have justice, but the concept of justice should be upheld in any decent society. Lives that government has allowed, mistakes it hasn’t anticipated and taken measures against, shouldn’t be met with the death penalty. If the State breaks its trust, no one else will trust it. Crime and poor lives reflect a State's failure; ultimately, all crime is a communal issue. Even for murder, I believe Utopia will not resort to execution.

I doubt even if there will be jails. No men are quite wise enough, good enough and cheap enough to staff jails as a jail ought to be staffed. Perhaps islands will be chosen, islands lying apart from the highways of the sea, and to these the State will send its exiles, most of them thanking Heaven, no doubt, to be quit of a world of prigs. The State will, of course, secure itself against any children from these people, that is the primary object in their seclusion, and perhaps it may even be necessary to make these island prisons a system of island monasteries and island nunneries. Upon that I am not competent to speak, but if I may believe the literature of the subject—unhappily a not very well criticised literature—it is not necessary to enforce this separation. [Footnote: See for example Dr. W. A. Chapple's The Fertility of the Unfit.]

I doubt there will even be jails. No one is really wise enough, good enough, or cheap enough to staff jails the way they should be. Maybe islands will be chosen, islands located away from the main shipping routes, and the State will send its exiles there, most of whom will probably thank their luck for getting away from a world of self-righteous people. The State will, of course, take steps to prevent any children from coming from these people, which is the main reason for their isolation, and it might even be necessary to turn these island prisons into a sort of system of island monasteries and nunneries. I'm not an expert on that topic, but if I can trust the literature on the subject—unfortunately, it's not very thoroughly critiqued—it seems that this separation doesn't need to be enforced. [Footnote: See for example Dr. W. A. Chapple's The Fertility of the Unfit.]

About such islands patrol boats will go, there will be no freedoms of boat building, and it may be necessary to have armed guards at the creeks and quays. Beyond that the State will give these segregated failures just as full a liberty as they can have. If it interferes any further it will be simply to police the islands against the organisation of serious cruelty, to maintain the freedom of any of the detained who wish it to transfer themselves to other islands, and so to keep a check upon tyranny. The insane, of course, will demand care and control, but there is no reason why the islands of the hopeless drunkard, for example, should not each have a virtual autonomy, have at the most a Resident and a guard. I believe that a community of drunkards might be capable of organising even its own bad habit to the pitch of tolerable existence. I do not see why such an island should not build and order for itself and manufacture and trade. “Your ways are not our ways,” the World State will say; “but here is freedom and a company of kindred souls. Elect your jolly rulers, brew if you will, and distil; here are vine cuttings and barley fields; do as it pleases you to do. We will take care of the knives, but for the rest—deal yourselves with God!”

About these islands, patrol boats will be deployed; there won’t be any freedoms for boat building, and it may be necessary to have armed guards at the creeks and docks. Aside from that, the State will grant these segregated individuals as much freedom as they can handle. If it interferes any further, it will simply be to police the islands against serious cruelty, to uphold the freedom of any detainees who wish to transfer to other islands, and to keep tyranny in check. The mentally ill, of course, will require care and supervision, but there’s no reason why the islands for hopeless alcoholics, for example, shouldn't have a level of autonomy, with just a Resident and a guard at most. I believe a community of alcoholics might even organize their bad habit into a somewhat tolerable way of living. I don’t see why such an island shouldn’t be able to build, manage itself, manufacture, and trade. “Your ways are not our ways,” the World State will say; “but here is freedom and a group of like-minded individuals. Choose your cheerful leaders, brew if you want, and distill; here are vine cuttings and barley fields; do as you please. We'll handle the knives, but for everything else—figure it out with God!”

And you see the big convict steamship standing in to the Island of Incurable Cheats. The crew are respectfully at their quarters, ready to lend a hand overboard, but wide awake, and the captain is hospitably on the bridge to bid his guests good-bye and keep an eye on the movables. The new citizens for this particular Alsatia, each no doubt with his personal belongings securely packed and at hand, crowd the deck and study the nearing coast. Bright, keen faces would be there, and we, were we by any chance to find ourselves beside the captain, might recognise the double of this great earthly magnate or that, Petticoat Lane and Park Lane cheek by jowl. The landing part of the jetty is clear of people, only a government man or so stands there to receive the boat and prevent a rush, but beyond the gates a number of engagingly smart-looking individuals loiter speculatively. One figures a remarkable building labelled Custom House, an interesting fiscal revival this population has made, and beyond, crowding up the hill, the painted walls of a number of comfortable inns clamour loudly. One or two inhabitants in reduced circumstances would act as hotel touts, there are several hotel omnibuses and a Bureau de Change, certainly a Bureau de Change. And a small house with a large board, aimed point-blank seaward, declares itself a Gratis Information Office, and next to it rises the graceful dome of a small Casino. Beyond, great hoardings proclaim the advantages of many island specialities, a hustling commerce, and the opening of a Public Lottery. There is a large cheap-looking barrack, the school of Commercial Science for gentlemen of inadequate training....

And you can see the large convict steamship approaching the Island of Incurable Cheats. The crew is respectfully at their posts, ready to help with anything overboard, but fully alert, while the captain is on the bridge, warmly saying goodbye to his guests and keeping an eye on the luggage. The new residents for this particular area, each with their belongings securely packed and ready, crowd the deck, looking out at the approaching coast. There are bright, eager faces, and if we happened to stand next to the captain, we might recognize the counterpart of this prominent person or that one, with Petticoat Lane and Park Lane side by side. The landing area of the jetty is empty of people, just a government official or two standing by to meet the boat and manage any crowding, but beyond the gates, a number of sharply dressed individuals linger, eyeing the scene. You can spot a notable building labeled Custom House, reflecting the interesting economic revival this population has achieved, and further up the hill, colorful signs from various cozy inns grab attention. A couple of residents in tough situations act as hotel touts; there are several hotel buses and definitely a Bureau de Change. A small building with a large sign facing straight toward the sea advertises itself as a Free Information Office, and next to it, a charming dome of a small Casino can be seen. Beyond that, large billboards promote the perks of various island specialties, an active trading scene, and the launch of a Public Lottery. There’s also a large, rather unattractive barrack serving as the school of Commercial Science for men with inadequate training....

Altogether a very go-ahead looking little port it would be, and though this disembarkation would have none of the flow of hilarious good fellowship that would throw a halo of genial noise about the Islands of Drink, it is doubtful if the new arrivals would feel anything very tragic in the moment. Here at last was scope for adventure after their hearts.

Overall, it would be a very lively little port, and although this arrival wouldn’t have the cheerful camaraderie that usually fills the Islands of Drink with a warm buzz, it's unlikely the newcomers would feel anything too dramatic at that moment. Finally, there was a chance for adventure that they had been looking for.

This sounds more fantastic than it is. But what else is there to do, unless you kill? You must seclude, but why should you torment? All modern prisons are places of torture by restraint, and the habitual criminal plays the part of a damaged mouse at the mercy of the cat of our law. He has his little painful run, and back he comes again to a state more horrible even than destitution. There are no Alsatias left in the world. For my own part I can think of no crime, unless it is reckless begetting or the wilful transmission of contagious disease, for which the bleak terrors, the solitudes and ignominies of the modern prison do not seem outrageously cruel. If you want to go so far as that, then kill. Why, once you are rid of them, should you pester criminals to respect an uncongenial standard of conduct? Into such islands of exile as this a modern Utopia will have to purge itself. There is no alternative that I can contrive.

This sounds more amazing than it really is. But what else is there to do, unless you kill? You have to isolate yourself, but why should you be cruel? All modern prisons are places of suffering through confinement, and the habitual criminal is like a hurt mouse at the mercy of the law's cat. He gets his little painful escape, and then he returns to a situation that’s even worse than being broke. There are no more Alsatias in the world. Personally, I can't think of any crime, except for reckless reproduction or knowingly spreading contagious diseases, for which the harsh fears, the isolation, and the humiliations of modern prison don't seem excessively cruel. If you want to go that far, then just kill. Once you're rid of them, why should you bother criminals to follow a standard of behavior that doesn't suit them? A modern Utopia will need to cleanse itself into such islands of exile. There’s no other option I can come up with.

§ 3

Will a Utopian be free to be idle?

Will someone in a Utopia be allowed to be lazy?

Work has to be done, every day humanity is sustained by its collective effort, and without a constant recurrence of effort in the single man as in the race as a whole, there is neither health nor happiness. The permanent idleness of a human being is not only burthensome to the world, but his own secure misery. But unprofitable occupation is also intended by idleness, and it may be considered whether that freedom also will be open to the Utopian. Conceivably it will, like privacy, locomotion, and almost all the freedoms of life, and on the same terms—if he possess the money to pay for it.

Work must be done; every day, humanity relies on its collective effort. Without consistent effort from every individual, as well as from society as a whole, there’s neither health nor happiness. A person’s permanent idleness is not just a burden to the world but also a path to personal misery. However, unproductive activity is also a result of idleness, and it raises the question of whether that kind of freedom will be available in a Utopian society. It’s possible that it will, just like the freedoms of privacy, moving around, and almost all other aspects of life—assuming one has the money to afford it.

That last condition may produce a shock in minds accustomed to the proposition that money is the root of all evil, and to the idea that Utopia necessarily implies something rather oaken and hand-made and primitive in all these relations. Of course, money is not the root of any evil in the world; the root of all evil in the world, and the root of all good too, is the Will to Live, and money becomes harmful only when by bad laws and bad economic organisation it is more easily attained by bad men than good. It is as reasonable to say food is the root of all disease, because so many people suffer from excessive and unwise eating. The sane economic ideal is to make the possession of money the clear indication of public serviceableness, and the more nearly that ideal is attained, the smaller is the justification of poverty and the less the hardship of being poor. In barbaric and disorderly countries it is almost honourable to be indigent and unquestionably virtuous to give to a beggar, and even in the more or less civilised societies of earth, so many children come into life hopelessly handicapped, that austerity to the poor is regarded as the meanest of mean virtues. But in Utopia everyone will have had an education and a certain minimum of nutrition and training; everyone will be insured against ill-health and accidents; there will be the most efficient organisation for balancing the pressure of employment and the presence of disengaged labour, and so to be moneyless will be clear evidence of unworthiness. In Utopia, no one will dream of giving to a casual beggar, and no one will dream of begging.

That last condition might shock those who believe that money is the root of all evil and that Utopia has to be something old-fashioned and primitive in every way. Actually, money isn’t the root of evil at all; the true source of both good and evil is the Will to Live. Money only becomes a negative force when bad laws and poor economic systems make it easier for bad people to get it than good people. It’s just as silly to say that food is the root of all disease, just because so many people suffer from overeating and poor eating habits. The sensible economic ideal is to make having money a clear sign of valuable public service, and the closer we get to that ideal, the less justification there is for poverty and the less difficult it is to be poor. In chaotic and uncivilized countries, being poor can almost seem honorable, and it’s certainly seen as virtuous to give to a beggar. Even in more or less civilized societies, many children are born at a disadvantage, making it seem mean-spirited to be harsh toward the poor. But in Utopia, everyone will have an education and a basic level of nutrition and training; everyone will be protected against illness and accidents; there will be a highly efficient system for matching job availability with the unemployed, making it clear that being without money is a sign of unworthiness. In Utopia, nobody will think about giving to a random beggar, and nobody will think about begging.

There will need to be, in the place of the British casual wards, simple but comfortable inns with a low tariff—controlled to a certain extent no doubt, and even in some cases maintained, by the State. This tariff will have such a definite relation to the minimum permissible wage, that a man who has incurred no liabilities through marriage or the like relationship, will be able to live in comfort and decency upon that minimum wage, pay his small insurance premium against disease, death, disablement, or ripening years, and have a margin for clothing and other personal expenses. But he will get neither shelter nor food, except at the price of his freedom, unless he can produce money.

Instead of British casual wards, there will need to be simple yet comfortable inns with affordable rates—likely regulated to some extent, and perhaps even supported, by the government. These rates will be directly tied to the minimum wage, so a single man without financial responsibilities from marriage or similar relationships will be able to live comfortably and decently on that minimum wage, pay his small insurance premium for illness, death, disability, or old age, and still have some money left over for clothing and personal expenses. However, he won't have access to shelter or food unless he can pay for it, which means he would lose his freedom without having money.

But suppose a man without money in a district where employment is not to be found for him; suppose the amount of employment to have diminished in the district with such suddenness as to have stranded him there. Or suppose he has quarrelled with the only possible employer, or that he does not like his particular work. Then no doubt the Utopian State, which wants everyone to be just as happy as the future welfare of the race permits, will come to his assistance. One imagines him resorting to a neat and business-like post-office, and stating his case to a civil and intelligent official. In any sane State the economic conditions of every quarter of the earth will be watched as constantly as its meteorological phases, and a daily map of the country within a radius of three or four hundred miles showing all the places where labour is needed will hang upon the post-office wall. To this his attention will be directed. The man out of work will decide to try his luck in this place or that, and the public servant, the official, will make a note of his name, verify his identity—the freedom of Utopia will not be incompatible with the universal registration of thumb-marks—and issue passes for travel and coupons for any necessary inn accommodation on his way to the chosen destination. There he will seek a new employer.

But imagine a guy without money in an area where he can't find a job; let's say the job availability suddenly dropped, leaving him stuck there. Or maybe he had a falling out with the only person who could hire him, or he just doesn't want to do that particular job. It's clear that the ideal society, which aims for everyone to be as happy as possible for the sake of future generations, would step in to help him. Picture him going to a neat, efficient post office and explaining his situation to a polite and knowledgeable employee. In a reasonable society, the economic conditions in every region would be monitored as closely as the weather, and there would be a daily map on the post office wall showing all the places where jobs are available within a few hundred miles. That's where he would be directed. The man without work would consider trying his luck in various locations, and the public servant would write down his name, confirm his identity—the freedom of this ideal society wouldn't conflict with universal fingerprint registration—and provide travel passes and accommodation coupons for his journey to the selected destination. There, he would look for a new job.

Such a free change of locality once or twice a year from a region of restricted employment to a region of labour shortage will be among the general privileges of the Utopian citizen.

Such a free move to a different area once or twice a year, from a place with limited job opportunities to a place where jobs are needed, will be one of the general benefits of being a Utopian citizen.

But suppose that in no district in the world is there work within the capacity of this particular man?

But what if there isn't any work available anywhere in the world that suits this particular person?

Before we suppose that, we must take into consideration the general assumption one is permitted to make in all Utopian speculations. All Utopians will be reasonably well educated upon Utopian lines; there will be no illiterates unless they are unteachable imbeciles, no rule-of-thumb toilers as inadaptable as trained beasts. The Utopian worker will be as versatile as any well-educated man is on earth to-day, and no Trade Union will impose a limit to his activities. The world will be his Union. If the work he does best and likes best is not to be found, there is still the work he likes second best. Lacking his proper employment, he will turn to some kindred trade.

Before we assume that, we need to consider the general expectation we can make in all Utopian ideas. Everyone in Utopia will be reasonably well-educated in Utopian principles; there won’t be any illiterates unless they are unable to learn, and no unskilled laborers who are as unadaptable as trained animals. The Utopian worker will be as adaptable as any educated person today, and no Trade Union will limit what he can do. The world will be his Union. If the job he enjoys and excels at isn’t available, there will still be work he enjoys even if it’s not his first choice. If he can’t find his ideal job, he’ll switch to something related.

But even with that adaptability, it may be that sometimes he will not find work. Such a disproportion between the work to be done and the people to do it may arise as to present a surplus of labour everywhere. This disproportion may be due to two causes: to an increase of population without a corresponding increase of enterprises, or to a diminution of employment throughout the world due to the completion of great enterprises, to economies achieved, or to the operation of new and more efficient labour-saving appliances. Through either cause, a World State may find itself doing well except for an excess of citizens of mediocre and lower quality.

But even with that adaptability, there may be times when he can't find work. A mismatch between the available jobs and the number of people who can do them might lead to a surplus of labor everywhere. This mismatch can happen for two reasons: either an increase in population without a corresponding rise in job opportunities, or a decrease in employment around the world because major projects have been completed, costs have been cut, or new and more efficient labor-saving tools have been introduced. In either case, a World State might be thriving except for having too many citizens who are average or below average in quality.

But the first cause may be anticipated by wise marriage laws.... The full discussion of these laws will come later, but here one may insist that Utopia will control the increase of its population. Without the determination and ability to limit that increase as well as to stimulate it whenever it is necessary, no Utopia is possible. That was clearly demonstrated by Malthus for all time.

But the primary reason can be addressed by smart marriage laws.... The complete examination of these laws will be discussed later, but for now, it's important to emphasize that Utopia will manage its population growth. Without the resolve and capability to not only limit that growth but also encourage it whenever needed, no Utopia can exist. This was clearly proven by Malthus for all time.

The second cause is not so easily anticipated, but then, though its immediate result in glutting the labour market is similar, its final consequences are entirely different from those of the first. The whole trend of a scientific mechanical civilisation is continually to replace labour by machinery and to increase it in its effectiveness by organisation, and so quite independently of any increase in population labour must either fall in value until it can compete against and check the cheapening process, or if that is prevented, as it will be in Utopia, by a minimum wage, come out of employment. There is no apparent limit to this process. But a surplus of efficient labour at the minimum wage is exactly the condition that should stimulate new enterprises, and that in a State saturated with science and prolific in invention will stimulate new enterprises. An increasing surplus of available labour without an absolute increase of population, an increasing surplus of labour due to increasing economy and not to proliferation, and which, therefore, does not press on and disarrange the food supply, is surely the ideal condition for a progressive civilisation. I am inclined to think that, since labour will be regarded as a delocalised and fluid force, it will be the World State and not the big municipalities ruling the force areas that will be the reserve employer of labour. Very probably it will be convenient for the State to hand over the surplus labour for municipal purposes, but that is another question. All over the world the labour exchanges will be reporting the fluctuating pressure of economic demand and transferring workers from this region of excess to that of scarcity; and whenever the excess is universal, the World State—failing an adequate development of private enterprise—will either reduce the working day and so absorb the excess, or set on foot some permanent special works of its own, paying the minimum wage and allowing them to progress just as slowly or just as rapidly as the ebb and flow of labour dictated. But with sane marriage and birth laws there is no reason to suppose such calls upon the resources and initiative of the world more than temporary and exceptional occasions.

The second cause isn’t as easy to predict, but while its immediate effect on flooding the job market is similar to the first, its long-term outcomes are completely different. A scientific, mechanical society steadily replaces human labor with machines and boosts productivity through better organization. This means that, regardless of population growth, labor must either decrease in value until it can compete with the cheaper alternatives or, if that’s avoided, like it would be in Utopia with a minimum wage, end up with people out of work. There’s no clear limit to this situation. However, having a surplus of skilled labor at minimum wage is precisely what should inspire new businesses, and in a society rich in science and innovation, that will drive new ventures. An increasing surplus of available labor without a rise in population, resulting from greater efficiency rather than overpopulation, and not disrupting the food supply, is surely the perfect condition for a forward-thinking society. I believe that, since labor will be seen as a flexible and movable resource, it will be the World State, rather than large cities, that serves as the primary employer of labor. It’s likely that the State will delegate the surplus labor for municipal needs, but that’s a different issue. Globally, labor exchanges will monitor the shifting demands of the economy and move workers from areas with excess labor to those with shortages; and whenever there’s a widespread surplus, the World State—if private enterprise doesn’t adequately develop—will either shorten the workday to absorb the excess or initiate some ongoing special projects of its own, paying the minimum wage and allowing them to progress as slowly or as quickly as the labor supply fluctuates. But with sensible marriage and birth regulations, there’s no reason to think such demands on the world’s resources and creativity would be anything more than rare and temporary situations.

§ 4

The existence of our blond bare-footed friend was evidence enough that in a modern Utopia a man will be free to be just as idle or uselessly busy as it pleases him, after he has earned the minimum wage. He must do that, of course, to pay for his keep, to pay his assurance tax against ill-health or old age, and any charge or debt paternity may have brought upon him. The World State of the modern Utopist is no state of moral compulsions. If, for example, under the restricted Utopian scheme of inheritance, a man inherited sufficient money to release him from the need to toil, he would be free to go where he pleased and do what he liked. A certain proportion of men at ease is good for the world; work as a moral obligation is the morality of slaves, and so long as no one is overworked there is no need to worry because some few are underworked. Utopia does not exist as a solace for envy. From leisure, in a good moral and intellectual atmosphere, come experiments, come philosophy and the new departures.

The presence of our blond, barefoot friend clearly shows that in a modern Utopia, a person can be as lazy or as busy as they want, as long as they've earned enough to cover their basic needs. They have to do that, of course, to afford their living expenses, to pay for health insurance, and to handle any debts or obligations that parenthood might bring. The World State envisioned by modern Utopians doesn’t impose moral obligations. For instance, if, under the limited Utopian inheritance rules, someone inherits enough money to stop working, they would be free to travel and pursue whatever interests them. Having a certain number of people living comfortably is beneficial for society; viewing work as a moral duty is a mindset of slaves, and as long as no one is overworked, we shouldn't be concerned that some people are working less. Utopia isn't a solution for envy. From leisure, in a positive moral and intellectual environment, come experiments, philosophy, and new ideas.

In any modern Utopia there must be many leisurely people. We are all too obsessed in the real world by the strenuous ideal, by the idea that the vehement incessant fool is the only righteous man. Nothing done in a hurry, nothing done under strain, is really well done. A State where all are working hard, where none go to and fro, easily and freely, loses touch with the purpose of freedom.

In any modern Utopia, there need to be many relaxed people. In the real world, we're all too fixated on the demanding ideal, believing that the intensely busy fool is the only good person. Nothing done in a rush, nothing done under pressure, is truly well done. A State where everyone is working hard, where no one moves around easily and freely, loses sight of the true purpose of freedom.

But inherited independence will be the rarest and least permanent of Utopian facts, for the most part that wider freedom will have to be earned, and the inducements to men and women to raise their personal value far above the minimum wage will be very great indeed. Thereby will come privacies, more space in which to live, liberty to go everywhere and do no end of things, the power and freedom to initiate interesting enterprises and assist and co-operate with interesting people, and indeed all the best things of life. The modern Utopia will give a universal security indeed, and exercise the minimum of compulsions to toil, but it will offer some acutely desirable prizes. The aim of all these devices, the minimum wage, the standard of life, provision for all the feeble and unemployed and so forth, is not to rob life of incentives but to change their nature, to make life not less energetic, but less panic-stricken and violent and base, to shift the incidence of the struggle for existence from our lower to our higher emotions, so to anticipate and neutralise the motives of the cowardly and bestial, that the ambitious and energetic imagination which is man's finest quality may become the incentive and determining factor in survival.

But inherited independence will be the rarest and least lasting of ideal circumstances. For the most part, that greater freedom will need to be earned, and the reasons for men and women to increase their personal value far above the minimum wage will be significant. This will lead to personal space, more room to live, the freedom to go anywhere and do countless activities, the ability and liberty to start interesting projects and connect with fascinating people, and really, all the best things in life. The modern Utopia will provide universal security and impose minimal demands for work, but it will present some highly desirable rewards. The goal of all these strategies—the minimum wage, the standard of living, support for the weak and unemployed, and so on—is not to strip life of motivation, but to reshape it, aiming to make life not less energetic but less frantic, violent, and degrading. It seeks to shift the struggle for existence from our lesser to our greater emotions, anticipating and neutralizing the motives of the cowardly and brutal, so that the ambition and creative imagination, which are humanity's finest qualities, can become the driving forces in survival.

§ 5

After we have paid for our lunch in the little inn that corresponds to Wassen, the botanist and I would no doubt spend the rest of the forenoon in the discussion of various aspects and possibilities of Utopian labour laws. We should examine our remaining change, copper coins of an appearance ornamental rather than reassuring, and we should decide that after what we had gathered from the man with the blond hair, it would, on the whole, be advisable to come to the point with the labour question forthwith. At last we should draw the deep breath of resolution and arise and ask for the Public Office. We should know by this time that the labour bureau sheltered with the post-office and other public services in one building.

After we paid for our lunch at the little inn in Wassen, the botanist and I would probably spend the rest of the morning discussing various aspects and possibilities of Utopian labor laws. We would check our remaining change, which looked more decorative than reassuring, and decide that after what we learned from the guy with the blond hair, it would be wise to tackle the labor issue right away. Finally, we would take a deep breath of determination, stand up, and ask for directions to the Public Office. By this point, we would know that the labor bureau was located with the post office and other public services in one building.

The public office of Utopia would of course contain a few surprises for two men from terrestrial England. You imagine us entering, the botanist lagging a little behind me, and my first attempts to be offhand and commonplace in a demand for work.

The public office in Utopia would definitely hold some surprises for two guys from England. Picture us walking in, the botanist trailing a bit behind me, while I try to act casual and ordinary when asking for work.

The office is in charge of a quick-eyed little woman of six and thirty perhaps, and she regards us with a certain keenness of scrutiny.

The office is run by a sharp-eyed woman who is about thirty-six, and she looks at us with a noticeable intensity.

“Where are your papers?” she asks.

“Where are your papers?” she asks.

I think for a moment of the documents in my pocket, my passport chequered with visas and addressed in my commendation and in the name of her late Majesty by We, Robert Arthur Talbot Gascoigne Cecil, Marquess of Salisbury, Earl of Salisbury, Viscount Cranborne, Baron Cecil, and so forth, to all whom it may concern, my Carte d'Identité (useful on minor occasions) of the Touring Club de France, my green ticket to the Reading Room of the British Museum, and my Lettre d'Indication from the London and County Bank. A foolish humour prompts me to unfold all these, hand them to her and take the consequences, but I resist.

I pause for a moment to think about the documents in my pocket: my passport filled with visas, addressed in my commendation and in the name of her late Majesty by We, Robert Arthur Talbot Gascoigne Cecil, Marquess of Salisbury, Earl of Salisbury, Viscount Cranborne, Baron Cecil, and so on, to everyone it may concern; my Carte d'Identité (useful for minor occasions) from the Touring Club de France; my green ticket to the Reading Room of the British Museum; and my Lettre d'Indication from the London and County Bank. A silly urge makes me want to show all these documents to her and face the consequences, but I hold back.

“Lost,” I say, briefly.

"Lost," I say, briefly.

“Both lost?” she asks, looking at my friend.

“Both lost?” she asks, glancing at my friend.

“Both,” I answer.

"Both," I reply.

“How?”

"How?"

I astonish myself by the readiness of my answer.

I surprise myself with how quickly I respond.

“I fell down a snow slope and they came out of my pocket.”

“I fell down a snowy slope and they fell out of my pocket.”

“And exactly the same thing happened to both of you?”

“And the exact same thing happened to both of you?”

“No. He'd given me his to put with my own.” She raised her eyebrows. “His pocket is defective,” I add, a little hastily.

“No. He gave me his to put with mine.” She raised her eyebrows. “His pocket is broken,” I added, a bit too quickly.

Her manners are too Utopian for her to follow that up. She seems to reflect on procedure.

Her manners are too idealistic for her to pursue that further. She seems to think about the process.

“What are your numbers?” she asks, abruptly.

“What are your numbers?” she asks suddenly.

A vision of that confounded visitors' book at the inn above comes into my mind. “Let me see,” I say, and pat my forehead and reflect, refraining from the official eye before me. “Let me see.”

A vision of that annoying visitors' book at the inn above comes to me. “Let me see,” I say, tapping my forehead and thinking, avoiding the official gaze in front of me. “Let me see.”

“What is yours?” she asks the botanist.

“What’s yours?” she asks the botanist.

“A. B.,” he says, slowly, “little a, nine four seven, I think―”

“A. B.,” he says, slowly, “little a, nine four seven, I think―”

“Don't you know?”

"Don't you know?"

“Not exactly,” says the botanist, very agreeably. “No.”

"Not exactly," says the botanist, very agreeably. "No."

“Do you mean to say neither of you know your own numbers?” says the little post-mistress, with a rising note.

“Are you saying neither of you knows your own numbers?” the little post-mistress says, her voice getting louder.

“Yes,” I say, with an engaging smile and trying to keep up a good social tone. “It's queer, isn't it? We've both forgotten.”

“Yes,” I say, with a friendly smile and trying to maintain a good social vibe. “It's strange, isn't it? We've both forgotten.”

“You're joking,” she suggests.

"You're joking," she says.

“Well,” I temporise.

“Well,” I stall.

“I suppose you've got your thumbs?”

“I guess you have your thumbs?”

“The fact is―” I say and hesitate. “We've got our thumbs, of course.”

“The fact is—” I say and pause. “We have our thumbs, of course.”

“Then I shall have to send a thumb-print down to the office and get your number from that. But are you sure you haven't your papers or numbers? It's very queer.”

“Then I’ll have to send a thumbprint to the office and get your number from that. But are you sure you don’t have your papers or numbers? It's really strange.”

We admit rather sheepishly that it's queer, and question one another silently.

We sheepishly admit that it’s strange, and silently question each other.

She turns thoughtfully for the thumb-marking slab, and as she does so, a man enters the office. At the sight of him she asks with a note of relief, “What am I to do, sir, here?”

She turns thoughtfully towards the thumb-marking slab, and as she does, a man walks into the office. Relief washes over her as she asks, “What should I do here, sir?”

He looks from her to us gravely, and his eye lights to curiosity at our dress. “What is the matter, madam?” he asks, in a courteous voice.

He looks from her to us seriously, and his eyes spark with curiosity at our outfits. “What’s the matter, ma’am?” he asks in a polite voice.

She explains.

She clarifies.

So far the impression we have had of our Utopia is one of a quite unearthly sanity, of good management and comprehensive design in every material thing, and it has seemed to us a little incongruous that all the Utopians we have talked to, our host of last night, the post-mistress and our garrulous tramp, have been of the most commonplace type. But suddenly there looks out from this man's pose and regard a different quality, a quality altogether nearer that of the beautiful tramway and of the gracious order of the mountain houses. He is a well-built man of perhaps five and thirty, with the easy movement that comes with perfect physical condition, his face is clean shaven and shows the firm mouth of a disciplined man, and his grey eyes are clear and steady. His legs are clad in some woven stuff deep-red in colour, and over this he wears a white shirt fitting pretty closely, and with a woven purple hem. His general effect reminds me somehow of the Knights Templars. On his head is a cap of thin leather and still thinner steel, and with the vestiges of ear-guards—rather like an attenuated version of the caps that were worn by Cromwell's Ironsides.

So far, our impression of this Utopia has been one of an almost otherworldly sanity, showcasing good management and thoughtful design in every material aspect. It’s felt a bit odd that everyone we've talked to—our host from last night, the post-mistress, and our chatty wanderer—has been pretty ordinary. But suddenly, this man gives off a different vibe, one that resonates more with the elegant tramway and the tasteful arrangement of the mountain houses. He’s a fit man, around thirty-five, moving with the ease that comes from being in excellent physical shape. He’s clean-shaven, with a firm mouth that indicates self-discipline, and his grey eyes are clear and steady. His legs are dressed in a deep red woven fabric, topped with a snug white shirt that has a woven purple hem. Overall, he has an air reminiscent of the Knights Templar. On his head, he wears a cap made of thin leather and even thinner steel, with remnants of ear-guards—kind of like a slimmer version of the caps worn by Cromwell's Ironsides.

He looks at us and we interpolate a word or so as she explains and feel a good deal of embarrassment at the foolish position we have made for ourselves. I determine to cut my way out of this entanglement before it complicates itself further.

He looks at us, and we add a word or two as she explains, feeling quite embarrassed about the silly position we've put ourselves in. I decide to find a way out of this mess before it gets any more complicated.

“The fact is―” I say.

“The fact is—” I say.

“Yes?” he says, with a faint smile.

“Yeah?” he says, with a slight smile.

“We've perhaps been disingenuous. Our position is so entirely exceptional, so difficult to explain―”

“We may have been a bit dishonest. Our situation is so completely unique, so hard to explain―”

“What have you been doing?”

"What have you been up to?"

“No,” I say, with decision; “it can't be explained like that.”

“No,” I say firmly; “it can’t be explained like that.”

He looks down at his feet. “Go on,” he says.

He glances at his feet. “Go ahead,” he says.

I try to give the thing a quiet, matter-of-fact air. “You see,” I say, in the tone one adopts for really lucid explanations, “we come from another world. Consequently, whatever thumb-mark registration or numbering you have in this planet doesn't apply to us, and we don't know our numbers because we haven't got any. We are really, you know, explorers, strangers―”

I try to make it sound calm and straightforward. “You see,” I say, using that clear tone people usually use for explanations, “we're from another world. So, any kind of thumbprint or number system you have here doesn’t apply to us, and we don’t know our numbers because we don’t have any. We are, honestly, explorers, outsiders—”

“But what world do you mean?”

"But which world are you talking about?"

“It's a different planet—a long way away. Practically at an infinite distance.”

“It's a different planet—far away. Almost at an endless distance.”

He looks up in my face with the patient expression of a man who listens to nonsense.

He looks up at me with the patient expression of someone who listens to nonsense.

“I know it sounds impossible,” I say, “but here is the simple fact—we appear in your world. We appeared suddenly upon the neck of Lucendro—the Passo Lucendro—yesterday afternoon, and I defy you to discover the faintest trace of us before that time. Down we marched into the San Gotthard road and here we are! That's our fact. And as for papers―! Where in your world have you seen papers like this?”

“I know it sounds impossible,” I say, “but here’s the simple truth—we show up in your world. We suddenly appeared on the neck of Lucendro—the Passo Lucendro—yesterday afternoon, and I challenge you to find the slightest trace of us before then. Down we marched onto the San Gotthard road and here we are! That’s the reality. And about the papers—where in your world have you seen anything like these?”

I produce my pocket-book, extract my passport, and present it to him.

I take out my wallet, pull out my passport, and show it to him.

His expression has changed. He takes the document and examines it, turns it over, looks at me, and smiles that faint smile of his again.

His expression has changed. He takes the document and looks it over, flips it over, glances at me, and gives me that subtle smile of his again.

“Have some more,” I say, and proffer the card of the T.C.F.

“Have some more,” I say, handing over the T.C.F. card.

I follow up that blow with my green British Museum ticket, as tattered as a flag in a knight's chapel.

I follow up that hit with my worn green British Museum ticket, as tattered as a flag in a knight's chapel.

“You'll get found out,” he says, with my documents in his hand. “You've got your thumbs. You'll be measured. They'll refer to the central registers, and there you'll be!”

“You'll be caught,” he says, holding my documents. “You've got your thumbs. They’ll take measurements. They’ll check the central registers, and there you’ll be!”

“That's just it,” I say, “we sha'n't be.”

“That's the point,” I say, “we won't be.”

He reflects. “It's a queer sort of joke for you two men to play,” he decides, handing me back my documents.

He thinks for a moment. “It's a weird kind of joke for you two to pull,” he says, giving me back my documents.

“It's no joke at all,” I say, replacing them in my pocket-book.

“It's not a joke at all,” I say, putting them back in my wallet.

The post-mistress intervenes. “What would you advise me to do?”

The post-mistress steps in. “What do you think I should do?”

“No money?” he asks.

“No cash?” he asks.

“No.”

“Nope.”

He makes some suggestions. “Frankly,” he says, “I think you have escaped from some island. How you got so far as here I can't imagine, or what you think you'll do.... But anyhow, there's the stuff for your thumbs.”

He offers a few suggestions. “Honestly,” he says, “I think you must have escaped from some island. I can't imagine how you made it this far, or what you plan to do... But anyway, here's the stuff for your thumbs.”

He points to the thumb-marking apparatus and turns to attend to his own business.

He gestures toward the thumb-marking device and then turns to focus on his own tasks.

Presently we emerge from the office in a state between discomfiture and amusement, each with a tramway ticket for Lucerne in his hand and with sufficient money to pay our expenses until the morrow. We are to go to Lucerne because there there is a demand for comparatively unskilled labour in carving wood, which seems to us a sort of work within our range and a sort that will not compel our separation.

Right now, we are leaving the office feeling a mix of discomfort and amusement, each holding a tram ticket to Lucerne and enough cash to cover our expenses until tomorrow. We're heading to Lucerne because there's a need for relatively unskilled labor in wood carving, which seems like the kind of work we can handle and won't force us to split up.

§ 6

The old Utopias are sessile organisations; the new must square itself to the needs of a migratory population, to an endless coming and going, to a people as fluid and tidal as the sea. It does not enter into the scheme of earthly statesmanship, but indeed all local establishments, all definitions of place, are even now melting under our eyes. Presently all the world will be awash with anonymous stranger men.

The old Utopias are stagnant organizations; the new ones must adapt to the needs of a moving population, to constant arrivals and departures, to people as changeable and fluctuating as the sea. It doesn't fit into the plans of earthly governance, but in fact, all local institutions, all definitions of location, are already dissolving before us. Soon, the entire world will be filled with anonymous strangers.

Now the simple laws of custom, the homely methods of identification that served in the little communities of the past when everyone knew everyone, fail in the face of this liquefaction. If the modern Utopia is indeed to be a world of responsible citizens, it must have devised some scheme by which every person in the world can be promptly and certainly recognised, and by which anyone missing can be traced and found.

Now the basic customs and familiar ways of recognizing each other that worked in small communities of the past, where everyone knew everyone, fall short in this shifting reality. If the modern Utopia is truly going to be a place of responsible citizens, it must have come up with a system that allows every person in the world to be quickly and reliably identified, and that enables the tracing and finding of anyone who is missing.

This is by no means an impossible demand. The total population of the world is, on the most generous estimate, not more than 1,500,000,000, and the effectual indexing of this number of people, the record of their movement hither and thither, the entry of various material facts, such as marriage, parentage, criminal convictions and the like, the entry of the new-born and the elimination of the dead, colossal task though it would be, is still not so great as to be immeasurably beyond comparison with the work of the post-offices in the world of to-day, or the cataloguing of such libraries as that of the British Museum, or such collections as that of the insects in Cromwell Road. Such an index could be housed quite comfortably on one side of Northumberland Avenue, for example. It is only a reasonable tribute to the distinctive lucidity of the French mind to suppose the central index housed in a vast series of buildings at or near Paris. The index would be classified primarily by some unchanging physical characteristic, such as we are told the thumb-mark and finger-mark afford, and to these would be added any other physical traits that were of material value. The classification of thumb-marks and of inalterable physical characteristics goes on steadily, and there is every reason for assuming it possible that each human being could be given a distinct formula, a number or “scientific name,” under which he or she could be docketed. [Footnote: It is quite possible that the actual thumb-mark may play only a small part in the work of identification, but it is an obvious convenience to our thread of story to assume that it is the one sufficient feature.] About the buildings in which this great main index would be gathered, would be a system of other indices with cross references to the main one, arranged under names, under professional qualifications, under diseases, crimes and the like.

This is not an impossible request. The total population of the world, at most, is about 1,500,000,000. Keeping track of this number of people, recording their movements back and forth, noting important facts like marriages, parentage, criminal records, and so on, as well as documenting new births and deaths, would be a massive task, but it's still not so huge that it couldn’t be compared to the work done by today’s post offices or the cataloging of libraries like the British Museum, or collections like the insects in Cromwell Road. This index could easily fit in a building on one side of Northumberland Avenue, for example. It's only fair to credit the clarity of the French mindset by envisioning the central index housed in a large series of buildings in or near Paris. The index would mainly be sorted by some unchanging physical trait, like thumbprints and fingerprints, and would also include other physical characteristics that are important. The classification of thumbprints and other unchanging traits is ongoing, and there’s every reason to believe that every person could be assigned a unique identifier, a number or "scientific name," under which they could be cataloged. [Footnote: It's possible that actual thumbprints play only a small role in identification, but for our story, it's convenient to assume they're the main feature.] Surrounding the buildings that would hold this main index, there would be systems of additional indices with cross-references to the main one, organized by names, professional qualifications, diseases, crimes, and similar categories.

These index cards might conceivably be transparent and so contrived as to give a photographic copy promptly whenever it was needed, and they could have an attachment into which would slip a ticket bearing the name of the locality in which the individual was last reported. A little army of attendants would be at work upon this index day and night. From sub-stations constantly engaged in checking back thumb-marks and numbers, an incessant stream of information would come, of births, of deaths, of arrivals at inns, of applications to post-offices for letters, of tickets taken for long journeys, of criminal convictions, marriages, applications for public doles and the like. A filter of offices would sort the stream, and all day and all night for ever a swarm of clerks would go to and fro correcting this central register, and photographing copies of its entries for transmission to the subordinate local stations, in response to their inquiries. So the inventory of the State would watch its every man and the wide world write its history as the fabric of its destiny flowed on. At last, when the citizen died, would come the last entry of all, his age and the cause of his death and the date and place of his cremation, and his card would be taken out and passed on to the universal pedigree, to a place of greater quiet, to the ever-growing galleries of the records of the dead.

These index cards could be transparent and designed to provide a photographic copy whenever needed, and they might have a slot for a ticket that shows the name of the location where the person was last reported. A dedicated team of attendants would be working on this index around the clock. From sub-stations that continually verify fingerprints and numbers, a constant flow of information would come in—reporting births, deaths, check-ins at hotels, requests for letters at post offices, tickets purchased for long trips, criminal convictions, marriages, and applications for public assistance, among other things. A network of offices would filter this data, and all day and night, a workforce of clerks would tirelessly manage the central register, creating copies of its entries to send back to the local stations in response to their requests. Thus, the State's records would keep track of every citizen, and the world would document its history as the unfolding of its fate continued. Finally, when a citizen passed away, the last entry would be recorded, including their age, the cause of death, and the date and location of their cremation, with their card being removed and forwarded to the universal record of ancestry, a more peaceful place within the ever-expanding archives of the deceased.

Such a record is inevitable if a Modern Utopia is to be achieved.

Such a record is unavoidable if we are to achieve a Modern Utopia.

Yet at this, too, our blond-haired friend would no doubt rebel. One of the many things to which some will make claim as a right, is that of going unrecognised and secret whither one will. But that, so far as one's fellow wayfarers were concerned, would still be possible. Only the State would share the secret of one's little concealment. To the eighteenth-century Liberal, to the old-fashioned nineteenth-century Liberal, that is to say to all professed Liberals, brought up to be against the Government on principle, this organised clairvoyance will be the most hateful of dreams. Perhaps, too, the Individualist would see it in that light. But these are only the mental habits acquired in an evil time. The old Liberalism assumed bad government, the more powerful the government the worse it was, just as it assumed the natural righteousness of the free individual. Darkness and secrecy were, indeed, the natural refuges of liberty when every government had in it the near possibility of tyranny, and the Englishman or American looked at the papers of a Russian or a German as one might look at the chains of a slave. You imagine that father of the old Liberalism, Rousseau, slinking off from his offspring at the door of the Foundling Hospital, and you can understand what a crime against natural virtue this quiet eye of the State would have seemed to him. But suppose we do not assume that government is necessarily bad, and the individual necessarily good—and the hypothesis upon which we are working practically abolishes either alternative—then we alter the case altogether. The government of a modern Utopia will be no perfection of intentions ignorantly ruling the world.... [Footnote: In the typical modern State of our own world, with its population of many millions, and its extreme facility of movement, undistinguished men who adopt an alias can make themselves untraceable with the utmost ease. The temptation of the opportunities thus offered has developed a new type of criminality, the Deeming or Crossman type, base men who subsist and feed their heavy imaginations in the wooing, betrayal, ill-treatment, and sometimes even the murder of undistinguished women. This is a large, a growing, and, what is gravest, a prolific class, fostered by the practical anonymity of the common man. It is only the murderers who attract much public attention, but the supply of low-class prostitutes is also largely due to these free adventures of the base. It is one of the bye products of State Liberalism, and at present it is very probably drawing ahead in the race against the development of police organisation.]

Yet even this would probably make our blond-haired friend rebel. One of the many things some people claim as a right is the ability to go unnoticed and secretly travel wherever they want. However, that would still be possible, at least as far as fellow travelers are concerned. Only the State would know about one's little concealment. To the eighteenth-century Liberal, and the traditional nineteenth-century Liberal—that is, to all self-identified Liberals raised to be against the Government as a principle—this organized surveillance would be the most detestable nightmare. Perhaps the Individualist would see it similarly. But these are just the mental habits formed during a troubled era. The old Liberalism presumed poor governance; the more powerful the government, the worse it was, just as it assumed the natural righteousness of the free individual. Darkness and secrecy were, indeed, the natural havens of liberty when every government had the potential for tyranny, and the Englishman or American viewed the documents of a Russian or a German like one might view the chains of a slave. Imagine that founder of old Liberalism, Rousseau, sneaking away from his child at the door of the Foundling Hospital, and you can grasp how much of a crime against natural virtue this quiet oversight by the State would have seemed to him. But suppose we don't assume that government is inherently bad and the individual inherently good—and the assumption we're using practically eliminates either option—then we completely change the situation. The government of a modern Utopia won't be a perfect set of intentions blindly ruling the world.... [Footnote: In the typical modern State of our world, with its population of millions and its extreme ease of movement, ordinary people who use an alias can easily become untraceable. The temptation from the opportunities this creates has led to a new type of crime, the Deeming or Crossman type, comprised of low individuals who survive by exploiting, betraying, mistreating, and sometimes even murdering ordinary women. This is a large, growing, and, most concerning, a prolific class, nurtured by the practical anonymity of the common man. It’s mainly the murderers who catch public attention, but the increase in low-class prostitution is also largely due to these reckless actions of the immoral. This is one of the byproducts of State Liberalism, and currently, it’s likely outpacing the development of police organization.]

Such is the eye of the State that is now slowly beginning to apprehend our existence as two queer and inexplicable parties disturbing the fine order of its field of vision, the eye that will presently be focussing itself upon us with a growing astonishment and interrogation. “Who in the name of Galton and Bertillon,” one fancies Utopia exclaiming, “are you?”

Such is the gaze of the State, which is now slowly starting to notice our presence as two strange and puzzling groups disrupting the neat order of its view, the gaze that will soon be fixating on us with increasing amazement and questioning. “Who on Earth are you?” one imagines Utopia exclaiming.

I perceive I shall cut a queer figure in that focus. I shall affect a certain spurious ease of carriage no doubt. “The fact is, I shall begin....”

I realize I'm going to look pretty awkward in that spotlight. I’ll probably put on a fake sense of confidence for sure. “The truth is, I’m going to start….”

§ 7

And now see how an initial hypothesis may pursue and overtake its maker. Our thumb-marks have been taken, they have travelled by pneumatic tube to the central office of the municipality hard by Lucerne, and have gone on thence to the headquarters of the index at Paris. There, after a rough preliminary classification, I imagine them photographed on glass, and flung by means of a lantern in colossal images upon a screen, all finely squared, and the careful experts marking and measuring their several convolutions. And then off goes a brisk clerk to the long galleries of the index building.

And now see how an initial hypothesis can follow and catch up with its creator. Our fingerprints have been collected, sent through a pneumatic tube to the municipal office near Lucerne, and then forwarded to the main index office in Paris. There, after a basic initial classification, I picture them being photographed on glass and projected in large images onto a screen, all perfectly squared, while the meticulous experts mark and measure their various patterns. And then a swift clerk heads off to the long hallways of the index building.

I have told them they will find no sign of us, but you see him going from gallery to gallery, from bay to bay, from drawer to drawer, and from card to card. “Here he is!” he mutters to himself, and he whips out a card and reads. “But that is impossible!” he says....

I’ve told them they won’t find any trace of us, but you can see him moving from one gallery to another, from bay to bay, from drawer to drawer, and from card to card. “Here he is!” he mumbles to himself, pulling out a card to read. “But that can’t be true!” he exclaims...

You figure us returning after a day or so of such Utopian experiences as I must presently describe, to the central office in Lucerne, even as we have been told to do.

You imagine us coming back after a day or so of these amazing experiences that I need to describe, to the central office in Lucerne, just like we've been told to do.

I make my way to the desk of the man who has dealt with us before. “Well?” I say, cheerfully, “have you heard?”

I walk up to the desk of the man who has helped us before. “So?” I say, cheerfully, “have you heard?”

His expression dashes me a little. “We've heard,” he says, and adds, “it's very peculiar.”

His expression surprises me a bit. “We've heard,” he says, and adds, “it's really strange.”

“I told you you wouldn't find out about us,” I say, triumphantly.

“I told you that you wouldn't find out about us,” I say, triumphantly.

“But we have,” he says; “but that makes your freak none the less remarkable.”

“But we have,” he says; “but that makes your strange behavior no less remarkable.”

“You've heard! You know who we are! Well—tell us! We had an idea, but we're beginning to doubt.”

“You've heard! You know who we are! Well—tell us! We had an idea, but we're starting to question it.”

“You,” says the official, addressing the botanist, “are―!”

“You,” says the official, addressing the botanist, “are―!”

And he breathes his name. Then he turns to me and gives me mine.

And he says my name. Then he turns to me and tells me his.

For a moment I am dumbfounded. Then I think of the entries we made at the inn in the Urserenthal, and then in a flash I have the truth. I rap the desk smartly with my finger-tips and shake my index-finger in my friend's face.

For a moment, I'm speechless. Then I remember the entries we made at the inn in the Urserenthal, and suddenly it hits me. I tap the desk sharply with my fingertips and point my index finger at my friend's face.

“By Jove!” I say in English. “They've got our doubles!”

“Wow!” I say in English. “They’ve got our lookalikes!”

The botanist snaps his fingers. “Of course! I didn't think of that.”

The botanist snaps his fingers. “Oh right! I didn’t think of that.”

“Do you mind,” I say to this official, “telling us some more about ourselves?”

“Could you,” I say to this official, “tell us a bit more about ourselves?”

“I can't think why you keep it up,” he remarks, and then almost wearily tells me the facts about my Utopian self. They are a little difficult to understand. He says I am one of the samurai, which sounds Japanese, “but you will be degraded,” he says, with a gesture almost of despair. He describes my position in this world in phrases that convey very little.

“I can't figure out why you keep this up,” he says, and then almost tiredly shares the details about my ideal self. They're a bit hard to grasp. He says I'm one of the samurai, which sounds Japanese, “but you will be looked down upon,” he adds, with a gesture that almost shows despair. He explains my role in this world in ways that don't say much.

“The queer thing,” he remarks, “is that you were in Norway only three days ago.”

“The strange thing,” he says, “is that you were in Norway just three days ago.”

“I am there still. At least―. I'm sorry to be so much trouble to you, but do you mind following up that last clue and inquiring if the person to whom the thumb-mark really belongs isn't in Norway still?”

“I’m still there. At least—. I apologize for being such a hassle to you, but would you mind checking on that last clue and asking if the person the thumbprint really belongs to is still in Norway?”

The idea needs explanation. He says something incomprehensible about a pilgrimage. “Sooner or later,” I say, “you will have to believe there are two of us with the same thumb-mark. I won't trouble you with any apparent nonsense about other planets and so forth again. Here I am. If I was in Norway a few days ago, you ought to be able to trace my journey hither. And my friend?”

The idea needs some clarification. He talks about a pilgrimage, but it makes no sense. “Sooner or later,” I say, “you’re going to have to accept that there are two of us with the same thumbprint. I won’t bother you with any nonsense about other planets and things like that again. Here I am. If I was in Norway a few days ago, you should be able to follow my journey here. And what about my friend?”

“He was in India.” The official is beginning to look perplexed.

“He was in India.” The official is starting to look confused.

“It seems to me,” I say, “that the difficulties in this case are only just beginning. How did I get from Norway hither? Does my friend look like hopping from India to the Saint Gotthard at one hop? The situation is a little more difficult than that―”

“It seems to me,” I say, “that the challenges in this situation are just getting started. How did I get from Norway here? Does my friend look like he can jump from India to the Saint Gotthard in one leap? The situation is a bit more complicated than that―”

“But here!” says the official, and waves what are no doubt photographic copies of the index cards.

“But here!” says the official, waving what are clearly photocopies of the index cards.

“But we are not those individuals!”

“But we are not those people!”

“You are those individuals.”

“You're those individuals.”

“You will see,” I say.

"You'll see," I say.

He dabs his finger argumentatively upon the thumb-marks. “I see now,” he says.

He taps his finger on the thumbprints. “I get it now,” he says.

“There is a mistake,” I maintain, “an unprecedented mistake. There's the difficulty. If you inquire you will find it begin to unravel. What reason is there for us to remain casual workmen here, when you allege we are men of position in the world, if there isn't something wrong? We shall stick to this wood-carving work you have found us here, and meanwhile I think you ought to inquire again. That's how the thing shapes to me.”

“There’s a mistake,” I insist, “an unusual mistake. That’s the issue. If you look into it, you’ll see it start to unravel. Why should we stay here as casual workers when you say we’re people of significance in the world, unless there’s something off? We’ll keep at this wood-carving job you’ve found for us, but in the meantime, I think you should investigate further. That’s how I see it.”

“Your case will certainly have to be considered further,” he says, with the faintest of threatening notes in his tone. “But at the same time”—hand out to those copies from the index again—“there you are, you know!”

“Your case will definitely need to be looked at more closely,” he says, with a barely noticeable hint of a threat in his voice. “But at the same time”—handing those copies from the index out again—“there you go, you know!”

§ 8

When my botanist and I have talked over and exhausted every possibility of our immediate position, we should turn, I think, to more general questions.

When my botanist and I have discussed and considered every possibility of our current situation, I believe we should shift our focus to broader questions.

I should tell him the thing that was becoming more and more apparent in my own mind. Here, I should say, is a world, obviously on the face of it well organised. Compared with our world, it is like a well-oiled engine beside a scrap-heap. It has even got this confounded visual organ swivelling about in the most alert and lively fashion. But that's by the way.... You have only to look at all these houses below. (We should be sitting on a seat on the Gütsch and looking down on the Lucerne of Utopia, a Lucerne that would, I insist, quite arbitrarily, still keep the Wasserthurm and the Kapellbrucke.) You have only to mark the beauty, the simple cleanliness and balance of this world, you have only to see the free carriage, the unaffected graciousness of even the common people, to understand how fine and complete the arrangements of this world must be. How are they made so? We of the twentieth century are not going to accept the sweetish, faintly nasty slops of Rousseauism that so gratified our great-great-grandparents in the eighteenth. We know that order and justice do not come by Nature—“if only the policeman would go away.” These things mean intention, will, carried to a scale that our poor vacillating, hot and cold earth has never known. What I am really seeing more and more clearly is the will beneath this visible Utopia. Convenient houses, admirable engineering that is no offence amidst natural beauties, beautiful bodies, and a universally gracious carriage, these are only the outward and visible signs of an inward and spiritual grace. Such an order means discipline. It means triumph over the petty egotisms and vanities that keep men on our earth apart; it means devotion and a nobler hope; it cannot exist without a gigantic process of inquiry, trial, forethought and patience in an atmosphere of mutual trust and concession. Such a world as this Utopia is not made by the chance occasional co-operations of self-indulgent men, by autocratic rulers or by the bawling wisdom of the democratic leader. And an unrestricted competition for gain, an enlightened selfishness, that too fails us....

I should share with him what’s becoming increasingly clear to me. Here’s a world that, on the surface, seems really well organized. Compared to our world, it’s like a finely tuned machine next to a junkyard. It even has this annoying visual organ swiveling around in a very alert and lively way. But that’s beside the point... Just look at all these houses below. (We should be sitting on a bench on the Gütsch and looking down at the Lucerne of Utopia, a Lucerne that would, I insist, still keep the Wasserthurm and the Kapellbrucke.) You can see the beauty, the simple cleanliness, and the balance of this world; you can notice the graceful way even the common people move, and you’ll understand how well-structured and complete this world has to be. But how did they achieve that? We in the twentieth century aren’t going to accept the sugary, slightly unpleasant ideas of Rousseauism that pleased our great-great-grandparents in the eighteenth century. We understand that order and justice don’t just come naturally—“if only the policeman would go away.” These things require intention and a level of willpower that our unstable, fluctuating world has never experienced. What I’m increasingly realizing is the will behind this visible Utopia. Comfortable houses, impressive engineering that fits well with natural beauty, beautiful bodies, and a universally gracious way of moving—these are just the visible signs of an inner spiritual grace. Such order requires discipline. It means overcoming the petty egotisms and vanities that keep people apart on our planet; it calls for devotion and a higher hope; it can’t exist without a massive process of inquiry, trial, foresight, and patience in an environment of mutual trust and compromise. A world like this Utopia isn’t created by the random, occasional efforts of self-indulgent individuals, by authoritarian leaders, or by the loud proclamations of a democratic leader. And an unrestricted pursuit of profit, an enlightened selfishness, that fails us as well...

I have compared the system of indexing humanity we have come upon to an eye, an eye so sensitive and alert that two strangers cannot appear anywhere upon the planet without discovery. Now an eye does not see without a brain, an eye does not turn round and look without a will and purpose. A Utopia that deals only with appliances and arrangements is a dream of superficialities; the essential problem here, the body within these garments, is a moral and an intellectual problem. Behind all this material order, these perfected communications, perfected public services and economic organisations, there must be men and women willing these things. There must be a considerable number and a succession of these men and women of will. No single person, no transitory group of people, could order and sustain this vast complexity. They must have a collective if not a common width of aim, and that involves a spoken or written literature, a living literature to sustain the harmony of their general activity. In some way they must have put the more immediate objects of desire into a secondary place, and that means renunciation. They must be effectual in action and persistent in will, and that means discipline. But in the modern world in which progress advances without limits, it will be evident that whatever common creed or formula they have must be of the simplest sort; that whatever organisation they have must be as mobile and flexible as a thing alive. All this follows inevitably from the general propositions of our Utopian dream. When we made those, we bound ourselves helplessly to come to this....

I’ve compared our system of indexing humanity to an eye—an eye so sensitive and aware that no two strangers can appear anywhere on Earth without being noticed. But an eye can’t see without a brain; it doesn’t turn around and look without intent and purpose. A Utopia focused only on tools and arrangements is merely a dream of superficialities; the core issue here, the essence beneath these external layers, is a moral and intellectual challenge. Behind all this material organization, these perfected communications, efficient public services, and economic systems, there must be individuals willing these things into existence. There must be a significant number of these determined individuals over time. No single person or fleeting group could manage and maintain this immense complexity. They need to share a collective, if not common, vision, which requires a spoken or written culture, a vibrant literature to support the harmony of their collective efforts. Somehow, they must prioritize longer-term goals over immediate desires, which entails sacrifice. They need to be effective in action and persistent in will, which means discipline. However, in today’s world, where progress is limitless, it will be clear that any shared belief or formula must be very simple; that any organization must be as flexible and dynamic as a living thing. All of this naturally follows from the foundational ideas of our Utopian vision. When we established those ideas, we committed ourselves to this path....

The botanist would nod an abstracted assent.

The botanist would nod in agreement, lost in thought.

I should cease to talk. I should direct my mind to the confused mass of memories three days in Utopia will have given us. Besides the personalities with whom we have come into actual contact, our various hosts, our foreman and work-fellows, the blond man, the public officials and so on, there will be a great multitude of other impressions. There will be many bright snapshots of little children, for example, of girls and women and men, seen in shops and offices and streets, on quays, at windows and by the wayside, people riding hither and thither and walking to and fro. A very human crowd it has seemed to me. But among them were there any who might be thought of as having a wider interest than the others, who seemed in any way detached from the rest by a purpose that passed beyond the seen?

I should stop talking. I should focus my mind on the jumble of memories that three days in Utopia will have given us. Besides the people we've interacted with—our various hosts, our foreman and coworkers, the blond guy, the public officials, and so on—there will be a ton of other impressions. There will be plenty of vivid snapshots of little kids, for example, girls, women, and men, seen in shops, offices, and streets, on docks, at windows, and by the roadside, people going here and there and walking back and forth. It seemed like a very human crowd to me. But among them, were there any who stood out as having a broader purpose than the others, who seemed in any way separate from the rest because of a goal that went beyond what was visible?

Then suddenly I recall that clean-shaven man who talked with us for a little while in the public office at Wassen, the man who reminded me of my boyish conception of a Knight Templar, and with him come momentary impressions of other lithe and serious-looking people dressed after the same manner, words and phrases we have read in such scraps of Utopian reading as have come our way, and expressions that fell from the loose mouth of the man with the blond hair....

Then suddenly I remember that clean-shaven guy who chatted with us for a bit at the public office in Wassen, the guy who made me think of my young idea of a Knight Templar. Along with him come brief memories of other slender and serious-looking people dressed similarly, words and phrases we've seen in bits of Utopian literature that have crossed our path, and comments that slipped out of the loose mouth of the guy with the blond hair...

CHAPTER THE SIXTH
Women in a Modern Utopia

§ 1

But though I have come to a point where the problem of a Utopia has resolved itself very simply into the problem of government and direction, I find I have not brought the botanist with me. Frankly he cannot think so steadily onward as I can. I feel to think, he thinks to feel. It is I and my kind that have the wider range, because we can be impersonal as well as personal. We can escape ourselves. In general terms, at least, I understand him, but he does not understand me in any way at all. He thinks me an incomprehensible brute because his obsession is merely one of my incidental interests, and wherever my reasoning ceases to be explicit and full, the slightest ellipsis, the most transitory digression, he evades me and is back at himself again. He may have a personal liking for me, though I doubt it, but also he hates me pretty distinctly, because of this bias he cannot understand. My philosophical insistence that things shall be reasonable and hang together, that what can be explained shall be explained, and that what can be done by calculation and certain methods shall not be left to chance, he loathes. He just wants adventurously to feel. He wants to feel the sunset, and he thinks that on the whole he would feel it better if he had not been taught the sun was about ninety-two million miles away. He wants to feel free and strong, and he would rather feel so than be so. He does not want to accomplish great things, but to have dazzling things occur to him. He does not know that there are feelings also up in the clear air of the philosophic mountains, in the long ascents of effort and design. He does not know that thought itself is only a finer sort of feeling than his—good hock to the mixed gin, porter and treacle of his emotions, a perception of similitudes and oppositions that carries even thrills. And naturally he broods on the source of all his most copious feelings and emotions, women, and particularly upon the woman who has most made him feel. He forces me also to that.

But even though I've reached a point where the idea of a Utopia has simplified for me into just the issue of governance and leadership, I realize I haven't managed to bring the botanist along with me. Honestly, he doesn’t think as consistently as I do. I feel to think, while he thinks to feel. It’s people like me who have a broader perspective because we can be both impersonal and personal. We can step outside ourselves. Generally speaking, I get him, but he doesn't understand me at all. He sees me as an incomprehensible brute because his obsession is just a minor interest of mine, and whenever my reasoning isn't completely clear or detailed, even the slightest omission or brief diversion sends him back to his own thoughts. He might have a personal liking for me, though I'm skeptical, but he also distinctly hates me because of this bias he can't grasp. My insistence on reason and coherence, that what can be explained should be explained, and that calculations and certain methods shouldn’t be left to chance, disgusts him. He simply wants to feel adventurous. He wants to experience the sunset and believes he’d appreciate it more if he didn’t know the sun is about ninety-two million miles away. He desires to feel free and empowered, and he would prefer to feel that way than actually be that way. He isn’t interested in achieving great things, but in having captivating moments happen to him. He doesn’t realize there are feelings up in the clear air of philosophical heights, amidst the long climbs of effort and design. He doesn’t see that thought itself is just a more refined form of feeling than his—like good wine compared to the mix of gin, porter, and treacle that comprises his emotions, a perception of similarities and contrasts that can even create thrills. Naturally, he reflects on the source of all his abundant emotions: women, particularly the one who has made him feel the most. He compels me toward that too.

Our position is unfortunate for me. Our return to the Utopian equivalent of Lucerne revives in him all the melancholy distresses that so preoccupied him when first we were transferred to this better planet. One day, while we are still waiting there for the public office to decide about us, he broaches the matter. It is early evening, and we are walking beside the lake after our simple dinner. “About here,” he says, “the quays would run and all those big hotels would be along here, looking out on the lake. It's so strange to have seen them so recently, and now not to see them at all.... Where have they gone?”

Our situation is unfortunate for me. Going back to the Utopian version of Lucerne brings up all the sad feelings that consumed him when we first moved to this better planet. One day, while we're still waiting for the public office to make a decision about us, he brings it up. It’s early evening, and we’re walking by the lake after our simple dinner. “Around here,” he says, “the docks would be lined with those big hotels overlooking the lake. It’s so weird to have seen them not long ago, and now they’re just gone... Where did they go?”

“Vanished by hypothesis.”

"Disappeared by assumption."

“What?”

“What?”

“Oh! They're there still. It's we that have come hither.”

“Oh! They're still there. It's us who've come here.”

“Of course. I forgot. But still― You know, there was an avenue of little trees along this quay with seats, and she was sitting looking out upon the lake.... I hadn't seen her for ten years.”

"Of course. I forgot. But still— You know, there was a row of little trees along this quay with benches, and she was sitting there, looking out at the lake.... I hadn’t seen her in ten years."

He looks about him still a little perplexed. “Now we are here,” he says, “it seems as though that meeting and the talk we had must have been a dream.”

He looks around, still a bit confused. “Now that we’re here,” he says, “it feels like that meeting and the conversation we had must have been a dream.”

He falls musing.

He falls deep in thought.

Presently he says: “I knew her at once. I saw her in profile. But, you know, I didn't speak to her directly. I walked past her seat and on for a little way, trying to control myself.... Then I turned back and sat down beside her, very quietly. She looked up at me. Everything came back—everything. For a moment or so I felt I was going to cry....”

Presently he says: “I recognized her immediately. I saw her in profile. But, you know, I didn't talk to her directly. I walked past her seat and kept going for a bit, trying to hold myself together.... Then I turned around and sat down next to her, very quietly. She looked up at me. Everything came flooding back—everything. For a moment, I felt like I was going to cry....”

That seems to give him a sort of satisfaction even in the reminiscence.

That seems to give him a kind of satisfaction even in the memory.

“We talked for a time just like casual acquaintances—about the view and the weather, and things like that.”

“We chatted for a bit like casual acquaintances—about the view, the weather, and stuff like that.”

He muses again.

He reflects again.

“In Utopia everything would have been different,” I say.

“In Utopia, everything would have been different,” I say.

“I suppose it would.”

"I guess it would."

He goes on before I can say anything more.

He moves on before I can say anything else.

“Then, you know, there was a pause. I had a sort of intuition that the moment was coming. So I think had she. You may scoff, of course, at these intuitions―”

“Then, you know, there was a pause. I had a kind of feeling that the moment was approaching. I think she did too. You might laugh, of course, at these feelings―”

I don't, as a matter of fact. Instead, I swear secretly. Always this sort of man keeps up the pretence of highly distinguished and remarkable mental processes, whereas—have not I, in my own composition, the whole diapason of emotional fool? Is not the suppression of these notes my perpetual effort, my undying despair? And then, am I to be accused of poverty?

I actually don’t. Instead, I secretly curse. This type of guy always pretends to have impressive and sophisticated thoughts, but don’t I have a complete range of emotional foolishness in my own writing? Am I not constantly trying to suppress these feelings, which is my ongoing struggle and endless despair? And then, am I really supposed to be blamed for being poor?

But to his story.

But to his story.

“She said, quite abruptly, ‘I am not happy,’ and I told her, ‘I knew that the instant I saw you.’ Then, you know, she began to talk to me very quietly, very frankly, about everything. It was only afterwards I began to feel just what it meant, her talking to me like that.”

“She said, pretty suddenly, ‘I’m not happy,’ and I told her, ‘I knew that the moment I saw you.’ Then, she started to open up to me really quietly and honestly about everything. It was only later that I started to realize what it meant that she was talking to me like that.”

I cannot listen to this!

I can’t listen to this!

“Don't you understand,” I cry, “that we are in Utopia. She may be bound unhappily upon earth and you may be bound, but not here. Here I think it will be different. Here the laws that control all these things will be humane and just. So that all you said and did, over there, does not signify here—does not signify here!”

“Don't you get it,” I shout, “that we are in Utopia. She may be stuck unhappily on earth and you may be stuck too, but not here. Here I believe it will be different. Here the rules that govern everything will be fair and compassionate. So everything you said and did back there doesn’t matter here—doesn’t matter here!”

He looks up for a moment at my face, and then carelessly at my wonderful new world.

He glances at my face for a moment and then casually surveys my amazing new world.

“Yes,” he says, without interest, with something of the tone of an abstracted elder speaking to a child, “I dare say it will be all very fine here.” And he lapses, thwarted from his confidences, into musing.

“Yes,” he says, disinterestedly, sounding a bit like an older person talking to a child, “I suppose it will all be very nice here.” Then he falls silent, cut off from his thoughts, lost in his own reflections.

There is something almost dignified in this withdrawal into himself. For a moment I entertain an illusion that really I am unworthy to hear the impalpable inconclusiveness of what he said to her and of what she said to him.

There’s something almost dignified about his retreat into himself. For a moment, I convince myself that I’m not worthy of knowing the vague uncertainty of what he said to her and what she said to him.

I am snubbed. I am also amazed to find myself snubbed. I become breathless with indignation. We walk along side by side, but now profoundly estranged.

I feel ignored. I'm also shocked to realize I'm being ignored. I get so frustrated I'm almost breathless. We walk next to each other, but now we're deeply disconnected.

I regard the façade of the Utopian public offices of Lucerne—I had meant to call his attention to some of the architectural features of these—with a changed eye, with all the spirit gone out of my vision. I wish I had never brought this introspective carcass, this mental ingrate, with me.

I look at the front of the ideal public buildings in Lucerne—I had intended to point out some of their architectural details to him—with a different perspective, feeling completely drained. I wish I had never brought this self-reflective burden, this ungrateful mind, with me.

I incline to fatalistic submission. I suppose I had no power to leave him behind.... I wonder and I wonder. The old Utopists never had to encumber themselves with this sort of man.

I tend to accept things as they come. I guess I had no choice but to stay with him.... I keep wondering and wondering. The old Utopians never had to deal with this kind of person.

§ 2

How would things be “different” in the Modern Utopia? After all it is time we faced the riddle of the problems of marriage and motherhood....

How would things be “different” in the Modern Utopia? After all, it’s time we confronted the challenge of the issues surrounding marriage and motherhood....

The Modern Utopia is not only to be a sound and happy World State, but it is to be one progressing from good to better. But as Malthus [Footnote: Essay on the Principles of Population.] demonstrated for all time, a State whose population continues to increase in obedience to unchecked instinct, can progress only from bad to worse. From the view of human comfort and happiness, the increase of population that occurs at each advance in human security is the greatest evil of life. The way of Nature is for every species to increase nearly to its possible maximum of numbers, and then to improve through the pressure of that maximum against its limiting conditions by the crushing and killing of all the feebler individuals. The way of Nature has also been the way of humanity so far, and except when a temporary alleviation is obtained through an expansion of the general stock of sustenance by invention or discovery, the amount of starvation and of the physical misery of privation in the world, must vary almost exactly with the excess of the actual birth-rate over that required to sustain population at a number compatible with a universal contentment. Neither has Nature evolved, nor has man so far put into operation, any device by which paying this price of progress, this misery of a multitude of starved and unsuccessful lives can be evaded. A mere indiscriminating restriction of the birth-rate—an end practically attained in the homely, old-fashioned civilisation of China by female infanticide, involves not only the cessation of distresses but stagnation, and the minor good of a sort of comfort and social stability is won at too great a sacrifice. Progress depends essentially on competitive selection, and that we may not escape.

The Modern Utopia isn't just meant to be a healthy and happy World State; it's supposed to evolve from good to better. However, as Malthus demonstrated, a State with a continuously increasing population driven by unchecked instincts can only decline. From the perspective of human comfort and happiness, the population growth that happens with each increase in security is the biggest problem we face. Nature's way is for every species to grow close to its maximum capacity, then improve by eliminating the weaker members through natural selection. Humanity has followed this pattern, and unless we temporarily alleviate it through innovations or discoveries that expand our resources, the suffering from hunger and deprivation will directly correlate to the gap between the birth rate and the number needed to sustain a society where everyone is satisfied. Nature hasn’t provided, nor has humanity implemented, any method to avoid paying the cost of progress, which is the suffering of countless undernourished and unsuccessful lives. Simply restricting the birth rate—something traditional cultures like China have done through female infanticide—leads not only to the end of suffering but also to stagnation, where the minor benefits of comfort and stability come at too high a cost. Progress fundamentally relies on competitive selection, and there's no way around that.

But it is a conceivable and possible thing that this margin of futile struggling, pain and discomfort and death might be reduced to nearly nothing without checking physical and mental evolution, with indeed an acceleration of physical and mental evolution, by preventing the birth of those who would in the unrestricted interplay of natural forces be born to suffer and fail. The method of Nature “red in tooth and claw” is to degrade, thwart, torture, and kill the weakest and least adapted members of every species in existence in each generation, and so keep the specific average rising; the ideal of a scientific civilisation is to prevent those weaklings being born. There is no other way of evading Nature's punishment of sorrow. The struggle for life among the beasts and uncivilised men means misery and death for the inferior individuals, misery and death in order that they may not increase and multiply; in the civilised State it is now clearly possible to make the conditions of life tolerable for every living creature, provided the inferiors can be prevented from increasing and multiplying. But this latter condition must be respected. Instead of competing to escape death and wretchedness, we may compete to give birth and we may heap every sort of consolation prize upon the losers in that competition. The modern State tends to qualify inheritance, to insist upon education and nurture for children, to come in more and more in the interests of the future between father and child. It is taking over the responsibility of the general welfare of the children more and more, and as it does so, its right to decide which children it will shelter becomes more and more reasonable.

But it’s possible to reduce the amount of pointless struggle, pain, discomfort, and death to almost nothing without stalling physical and mental evolution. In fact, we could speed up both by preventing the birth of those who, through natural processes, would be born to suffer and fail. Nature's method, which is often harsh, is to weaken, frustrate, torture, and kill the least adapted individuals in every species each generation, thus raising the average. The ideal of a scientific society is to stop those weaker individuals from being born. There’s no other way to avoid Nature's punishment of sorrow. The struggle for survival among animals and uncivilized people leads to misery and death for the weaker individuals, misery and death that ensure they don’t reproduce. In a civilized society, it’s now clearly possible to make life tolerable for every living creature, as long as we can prevent the less capable from multiplying. But this requirement must be upheld. Instead of competing merely to avoid death and suffering, we can compete to give life, and we can offer all kinds of consolation prizes to those who don’t succeed in that competition. The modern state tends to regulate inheritance, insists on education and care for children, and increasingly intervenes in the interests of the future between parents and their children. As it takes on more responsibility for the general well-being of children, its right to decide which children it will support becomes more justified.

How far will such conditions be prescribed? how far can they be prescribed in a Modern Utopia?

How far will these conditions be set? How far can they be set in a Modern Utopia?

Let us set aside at once all nonsense of the sort one hears in certain quarters about the human stud farm. [Footnote: See Mankind in the Making, Ch. II.] State breeding of the population was a reasonable proposal for Plato to make, in view of the biological knowledge of his time and the purely tentative nature of his metaphysics; but from anyone in the days after Darwin, it is preposterous. Yet we have it given to us as the most brilliant of modern discoveries by a certain school of sociological writers, who seem totally unable to grasp the modification of meaning “species” and “individual” have undergone in the last fifty years. They do not seem capable of the suspicion that the boundaries of species have vanished, and that individuality now carries with it the quality of the unique! To them individuals are still defective copies of a Platonic ideal of the species, and the purpose of breeding no more than an approximation to that perfection. Individuality is indeed a negligible difference to them, an impertinence, and the whole flow of modern biological ideas has washed over them in vain.

Let's immediately dismiss all the nonsense you hear in certain circles about human breeding programs. [Footnote: See Mankind in the Making, Ch. II.] State-controlled breeding of the population was a reasonable suggestion for Plato to make, considering the biological understanding of his time and the purely experimental nature of his philosophy; but for anyone after Darwin, it’s absurd. Yet, some modern sociological writers present it as the pinnacle of contemporary thought, seeming completely unaware of how the meanings of “species” and “individual” have changed in the last fifty years. They don’t seem to realize that the boundaries between species have disappeared, and that individuality now implies unique qualities! To them, individuals are still flawed replicas of a Platonic ideal of the species, and the goal of breeding is merely to get closer to that perfection. Individuality seems like an insignificant difference to them, just a nuisance, and the entire wave of modern biological concepts has rolled over them without leaving a mark.

But to the modern thinker individuality is the significant fact of life, and the idea of the State, which is necessarily concerned with the average and general, selecting individualities in order to pair them and improve the race, an absurdity. It is like fixing a crane on the plain in order to raise the hill tops. In the initiative of the individual above the average, lies the reality of the future, which the State, presenting the average, may subserve but cannot control. And the natural centre of the emotional life, the cardinal will, the supreme and significant expression of individuality, should lie in the selection of a partner for procreation.

But for modern thinkers, individuality is what really matters in life, and the concept of the State, which focuses on the average and general by selecting individual traits to pair people up and improve society, is ridiculous. It's like trying to raise hilltops by placing a crane on flat land. The true future lies in the initiatives of individuals who stand out from the average, something the State, by focusing on the average, can support but not control. The core of emotional life, the essential will, and the most profound expression of individuality should be found in choosing a partner for reproduction.

But compulsory pairing is one thing, and the maintenance of general limiting conditions is another, and one well within the scope of State activity. The State is justified in saying, before you may add children to the community for the community to educate and in part to support, you must be above a certain minimum of personal efficiency, and this you must show by holding a position of solvency and independence in the world; you must be above a certain age, and a certain minimum of physical development, and free of any transmissible disease. You must not be a criminal unless you have expiated your offence. Failing these simple qualifications, if you and some person conspire and add to the population of the State, we will, for the sake of humanity, take over the innocent victim of your passions, but we shall insist that you are under a debt to the State of a peculiarly urgent sort, and one you will certainly pay, even if it is necessary to use restraint to get the payment out of you: it is a debt that has in the last resort your liberty as a security, and, moreover, if this thing happens a second time, or if it is disease or imbecility you have multiplied, we will take an absolutely effectual guarantee that neither you nor your partner offend again in this matter.

But mandatory pairing is one thing, and maintaining general standards is another, which is definitely something the State can take on. The State is justified in saying that before you can bring children into the community for them to be educated and partly supported, you need to meet a minimum level of personal capability. You must prove this by being financially stable and independent; you also need to be above a certain age, have a minimum level of physical health, and be free of any contagious diseases. You shouldn't have a criminal record unless you have served your time. If you and another person choose to expand the population in violation of these basic requirements, we will, for the sake of humanity, step in and care for the innocent outcome of your actions. However, we will require that you owe a specific and urgent debt to the State that you will definitely need to repay, even if it means we have to enforce the repayment: this debt ultimately puts your freedom at stake. Furthermore, if this situation occurs again, or if you contribute to the spread of disease or disabilities, we will ensure that neither you nor your partner can repeat this mistake.

“Harsh!” you say, and “Poor Humanity!”

“Harsh!” you exclaim, and “Poor Humanity!”

You have the gentler alternative to study in your terrestrial slums and asylums.

You have a gentler option to study in your earthly neighborhoods and care facilities.

It may be urged that to permit conspicuously inferior people to have one or two children in this way would be to fail to attain the desired end, but, indeed, this is not so. A suitably qualified permission, as every statesman knows, may produce the social effects without producing the irksome pressure of an absolute prohibition. Amidst bright and comfortable circumstances, and with an easy and practicable alternative, people will exercise foresight and self-restraint to escape even the possibilities of hardship and discomfort; and free life in Utopia is to be well worth this trouble even for inferior people. The growing comfort, self-respect, and intelligence of the English is shown, for example, in the fall in the proportion of illegitimate births from 2.2 per 1,000 in 1846-50 to 1.2 per 1,000 in 1890-1900, and this without any positive preventive laws whatever. This most desirable result is pretty certainly not the consequence of any great exaltation of our moral tone, but simply of a rising standard of comfort and a livelier sense of consequences and responsibilities. If so marked a change is possible in response to such progress as England has achieved in the past fifty years, if discreet restraint can be so effectual as this, it seems reasonable to suppose that in the ampler knowledge and the cleaner, franker atmosphere of our Utopian planet the birth of a child to diseased or inferior parents, and contrary to the sanctions of the State, will be the rarest of disasters.

It might be argued that allowing obviously less capable people to have one or two children in this way would not achieve the desired goal, but that's not true. As any politician knows, granting a carefully considered allowance can create the social outcomes we want without the annoying burden of a complete ban. In bright and comfortable conditions, and with an easy and practical alternative, people will make thoughtful choices and show self-control to avoid even the possibility of struggle and discomfort; living freely in Utopia is definitely worth the effort, even for those who are less capable. The increasing comfort, self-respect, and intelligence of the English, for instance, is reflected in the decline of illegitimate births from 2.2 per 1,000 in 1846-50 to 1.2 per 1,000 in 1890-1900, all without any strict preventive laws. This highly desirable outcome is likely not due to a significant boost in our moral standards, but simply because of a higher standard of living and a greater awareness of consequences and responsibilities. If such a significant change is possible in response to the progress England has made over the last fifty years, and if careful restraint can be this effective, it seems reasonable to think that in the broader knowledge and more honest atmosphere of our Utopian world, the birth of a child to unhealthy or less capable parents, against the state's guidelines, will be an extremely rare occurrence.

And the death of a child, too, that most tragic event, Utopia will rarely know. Children are not born to die in childhood. But in our world, at present, through the defects of our medical science and nursing methods, through defects in our organisation, through poverty and carelessness, and through the birth of children that never ought to have been born, one out of every five children born dies within five years. It may be the reader has witnessed this most distressful of all human tragedies. It is sheer waste of suffering. There is no reason why ninety-nine out of every hundred children born should not live to a ripe age. Accordingly, in any Modern Utopia, it must be insisted they will.

And the death of a child, that heartbreaking event, is something Utopia will rarely experience. Children aren't meant to die young. But in our current world, due to the flaws in our medical science and nursing practices, as well as issues in our organization, poverty, neglect, and the birth of children who shouldn't have been born at all, one out of every five children born dies before turning five. The reader may have witnessed this most painful of all human tragedies. It's a complete waste of suffering. There's no reason why ninety-nine out of every hundred children born shouldn't live to old age. Therefore, in any Modern Utopia, it must be ensured that they will.

§ 3

All former Utopias have, by modern standards, erred on the side of over regulation in these matters. The amount of State interference with the marriage and birth of the citizens of a modern Utopia will be much less than in any terrestrial State. Here, just as in relation to property and enterprise, the law will regulate only in order to secure the utmost freedom and initiative.

All previous Utopias have, by today's standards, made the mistake of over-regulating these issues. The level of government interference with the marriage and birth of citizens in a modern Utopia will be much less than in any real-world State. Here, just like with property and business, the law will only step in to ensure maximum freedom and initiative.

Up to the beginning of this chapter, our Utopian speculations, like many Acts of Parliament, have ignored the difference of sex. “He” indeed is to be read as “He and She” in all that goes before. But we may now come to the sexual aspects of the modern ideal of a constitution of society in which, for all purposes of the individual, women are to be as free as men. This will certainly be realised in the Modern Utopia, if it can be realised at all—not only for woman's sake, but for man's.

Up until the beginning of this chapter, our Utopian ideas, much like several Acts of Parliament, have overlooked the difference between genders. “He” should actually be understood as “He and She” in everything that has come before. Now we can address the sexual aspects of the modern vision of a society where, for all individual purposes, women are as free as men. This will definitely be achieved in the Modern Utopia, if it can be achieved at all—not just for women's benefit, but for men's as well.

But women may be free in theory and not in practice, and as long as they suffer from their economic inferiority, from the inability to produce as much value as a man for the same amount of work—and there can be no doubt of this inferiority—so long will their legal and technical equality be a mockery. It is a fact that almost every point in which a woman differs from a man is an economic disadvantage to her, her incapacity for great stresses of exertion, her frequent liability to slight illnesses, her weaker initiative, her inferior invention and resourcefulness, her relative incapacity for organisation and combination, and the possibilities of emotional complications whenever she is in economic dependence on men. So long as women are compared economically with men and boys they will be inferior in precisely the measure in which they differ from men. All that constitutes this difference they are supposed not to trade upon except in one way, and that is by winning or luring a man to marry, selling themselves in an almost irrevocable bargain, and then following and sharing his fortunes for “better or worse.”

But women might be free in theory but not in reality, and as long as they suffer from economic disadvantages, like not being able to create as much value as men for the same amount of work—and there's no doubt about this disadvantage—then their legal and technical equality will just be a joke. The truth is, almost every difference between a woman and a man is a setback for women: their inability to handle heavy physical stress, their tendency to get minor illnesses, their weaker initiative, their lesser creativity and resourcefulness, their relative difficulty with organization and teamwork, and the emotional complications that arise when they rely on men financially. As long as women are economically compared to men and boys, they will be disadvantaged in direct relation to how they differ from men. They are expected not to take advantage of these differences except in one way: by winning or attracting a man to marry, essentially selling themselves in a nearly unchangeable deal, and then sharing in his fortunes "for better or worse."

But—do not let the proposition in its first crudity alarm you—suppose the Modern Utopia equalises things between the sexes in the only possible way, by insisting that motherhood is a service to the State and a legitimate claim to a living; and that, since the State is to exercise the right of forbidding or sanctioning motherhood, a woman who is, or is becoming, a mother, is as much entitled to wages above the minimum wage, to support, to freedom, and to respect and dignity as a policeman, a solicitor-general, a king, a bishop in the State Church, a Government professor, or anyone else the State sustains. Suppose the State secures to every woman who is, under legitimate sanctions, becoming or likely to become a mother, that is to say who is duly married, a certain wage from her husband to secure her against the need of toil and anxiety, suppose it pays her a certain gratuity upon the birth of a child, and continues to pay at regular intervals sums sufficient to keep her and her child in independent freedom, so long as the child keeps up to the minimum standard of health and physical and mental development. Suppose it pays more upon the child when it rises markedly above certain minimum qualifications, physical or mental, and, in fact, does its best to make thoroughly efficient motherhood a profession worth following. And suppose in correlation with this it forbids the industrial employment of married women and of mothers who have children needing care, unless they are in a position to employ qualified efficient substitutes to take care of their offspring. What differences from terrestrial conditions will ensue?

But don’t let the initial roughness of this idea scare you—imagine a Modern Utopia that balances things between the sexes in the only realistic way, by treating motherhood as a service to the State and a valid claim to a livelihood. The State would have the authority to permit or restrict motherhood, and a woman who is, or is about to become, a mother would be just as entitled to earn above the minimum wage, receive support, and enjoy freedom, respect, and dignity as a policeman, a solicitor-general, a king, a bishop in the State Church, a government professor, or anyone else supported by the State. Picture the State ensuring that every woman who is legitimately becoming or likely to become a mother, meaning those who are legally married, receives a guaranteed wage from her husband to protect her from the need to work and worry. Consider that it provides her with a certain cash gift when she gives birth and continues to pay her regular amounts sufficient to keep her and her child financially independent, as long as the child maintains a minimum standard of health and physical and mental development. Imagine it giving additional support for children who significantly exceed certain basic physical or mental standards, and actively working to make competent motherhood a profession worth pursuing. Now, if it also banned the employment of married women and mothers with children needing care, unless they could hire qualified and efficient caregivers for their kids, what differences from current conditions would arise?

This extent of intervention will at least abolish two or three salient hardships and evils of the civilised life. It will abolish the hardship of the majority of widows, who on earth are poor and encumbered exactly in proportion as they have discharged the chief distinctive duty of a woman, and miserable, just in proportion as their standard of life and of education is high. It will abolish the hardship of those who do not now marry on account of poverty, or who do not dare to have children. The fear that often turns a woman from a beautiful to a mercenary marriage will vanish from life. In Utopia a career of wholesome motherhood would be, under such conditions as I have suggested, the normal and remunerative calling for a woman, and a capable woman who has borne, bred, and begun the education of eight or nine well-built, intelligent, and successful sons and daughters would be an extremely prosperous woman, quite irrespective of the economic fortunes of the man she has married. She would need to be an exceptional woman, and she would need to have chosen a man at least a little above the average as her partner in life. But his death, or misbehaviour, or misfortunes would not ruin her.

This level of intervention would eliminate two or three major challenges and problems of modern life. It would remove the struggles of most widows, who are poor and burdened precisely because they have fulfilled the primary responsibility of being a woman, and are unhappy, especially when their expectations for life and education are high. It would end the difficulties faced by those who don’t marry due to financial constraints, or who are afraid to have children. The anxiety that often drives a woman from a loving marriage to a transactional one would disappear. In this ideal society, a fulfilling motherhood would be, under the conditions I've described, the usual and well-paying career for a woman, and a capable woman who has given birth to, raised, and started educating eight or nine healthy, smart, and successful sons and daughters would be very well-off, regardless of her husband's financial situation. She would need to be an extraordinary woman and have chosen a partner who is at least somewhat above average. However, his death, poor behavior, or bad luck wouldn’t ruin her.

Now such an arrangement is merely the completed induction from the starting propositions that make some measure of education free and compulsory for every child in the State. If you prevent people making profit out of their children—and every civilised State—even that compendium of old-fashioned Individualism, the United States of America—is now disposed to admit the necessity of that prohibition—and if you provide for the aged instead of leaving them to their children's sense of duty, the practical inducements to parentage, except among very wealthy people, are greatly reduced. The sentimental factor in the case rarely leads to more than a solitary child or at most two to a marriage, and with a high and rising standard of comfort and circumspection it is unlikely that the birth-rate will ever rise very greatly again. The Utopians will hold that if you keep the children from profitable employment for the sake of the future, then, if you want any but the exceptionally rich, secure, pious, unselfish, or reckless to bear children freely, you must be prepared to throw the cost of their maintenance upon the general community.

Now, this setup is just the result of the basic idea that some level of education should be free and mandatory for every child in the State. If you stop people from profiting off their children—and even the United States, known for its old-fashioned Individualism, acknowledges the need for this prohibition—and if you take care of the elderly rather than relying on their children's sense of duty, the practical reasons for having kids, except among the very wealthy, go down significantly. The emotional aspects usually lead to only one or two kids per marriage, and with a higher and rising standard of living and caution, it’s unlikely the birth rate will rise much again. The Utopians will argue that if you keep kids from working for profit to secure a better future, you need to be ready to cover their upbringing costs if you want any but the exceptionally rich, stable, caring, selfless, or reckless people to have children freely.

In short, Utopia will hold that sound childbearing and rearing is a service done, not to a particular man, but to the whole community, and all its legal arrangements for motherhood will be based on that conception.

In short, Utopia will affirm that healthy childbirth and child-rearing is a service provided, not just for an individual man, but for the entire community, and all its laws regarding motherhood will be built on that idea.

§ 4

And after these preliminaries we must proceed to ask, first, what will be the Utopian marriage law, and then what sort of customs and opinions are likely to be superadded to that law?

And after these introductions, we need to ask, first, what the Utopian marriage law will be, and then what kinds of customs and beliefs are likely to be added to that law?

The trend of our reasoning has brought us to the conclusion that the Utopian State will feel justified in intervening between men and women on two accounts, first on account of paternity, and secondly on account of the clash of freedoms that may otherwise arise. The Utopian State will effectually interfere with and prescribe conditions for all sorts of contract, and for this sort of contract in particular it will be in agreement with almost every earthly State, in defining in the completest fashion what things a man or woman may be bound to do, and what they cannot be bound to do. From the point of view of a statesman, marriage is the union of a man and woman in a manner so intimate as to involve the probability of offspring, and it is of primary importance to the State, first in order to secure good births, and secondly good home conditions, that these unions should not be free, nor promiscuous, nor practically universal throughout the adult population.

The way we've been thinking has led us to believe that the Utopian State will find it necessary to step in between men and women for two main reasons: first, regarding paternity, and second, to prevent potential conflicts over individual freedoms. The Utopian State will actively regulate and set conditions for all types of contracts, especially this type of contract, and it will collaborate with nearly every other state in clearly outlining what obligations a man or woman can and cannot be held to. From a politician's perspective, marriage is the close union of a man and woman that likely results in having children, and it’s crucial for the State to ensure these unions are not freely entered into, nor promiscuous, nor widespread among adults.

Prolific marriage must be a profitable privilege. It must occur only under certain obvious conditions, the contracting parties must be in health and condition, free from specific transmissible taints, above a certain minimum age, and sufficiently intelligent and energetic to have acquired a minimum education. The man at least must be in receipt of a net income above the minimum wage, after any outstanding charges against him have been paid. All this much it is surely reasonable to insist upon before the State becomes responsible for the prospective children. The age at which men and women may contract to marry is difficult to determine. But if we are, as far as possible, to put women on an equality with men, if we are to insist upon a universally educated population, and if we are seeking to reduce the infantile death-rate to zero, it must be much higher than it is in any terrestrial State. The woman should be at least one-and-twenty; the man twenty-six or twenty-seven.

Prolific marriage should be a beneficial privilege. It should happen only under certain clear conditions: the people involved must be healthy, free from specific transmissible diseases, above a certain minimum age, and smart enough to have received a minimum level of education. At the very least, the man should earn above the minimum wage after paying off any debts. It's totally reasonable to demand all this before the state takes on responsibility for any children that might be born. Determining the age at which men and women can marry is tricky. However, if we want to put women on equal footing with men, ensure a universally educated population, and aim to eliminate infant mortality completely, that age has to be much higher than it is in any country today. The woman should be at least 21, and the man should be 26 or 27.

One imagines the parties to a projected marriage first obtaining licenses which will testify that these conditions are satisfied. From the point of view of the theoretical Utopian State, these licenses are the feature of primary importance. Then, no doubt, that universal register at Paris would come into play. As a matter of justice, there must be no deception between the two people, and the State will ensure that in certain broad essentials this is so. They would have to communicate their joint intention to a public office after their personal licenses were granted, and each would be supplied with a copy of the index card of the projected mate, on which would be recorded his or her age, previous marriages, legally important diseases, offspring, domiciles, public appointments, criminal convictions, registered assignments of property, and so forth. Possibly it might be advisable to have a little ceremony for each party, for each in the absence of the other, in which this record could be read over in the presence of witnesses, together with some prescribed form of address of counsel in the matter. There would then be a reasonable interval for consideration and withdrawal on the part of either spouse. In the event of the two people persisting in their resolution, they would after this minimum interval signify as much to the local official and the necessary entry would be made in the registers. These formalities would be quite independent of any religious ceremonial the contracting parties might choose, for with religious belief and procedure the modern State has no concern.

One imagines that people planning to marry would first get licenses to confirm that all conditions are met. From the perspective of an ideal Utopian State, these licenses are the most important part. Then, obviously, the universal register in Paris would be involved. To ensure fairness, there should be no deception between the two individuals, and the State will make sure that this is true in essential ways. They would need to inform a public office of their joint intention after receiving their personal licenses, and each would receive a copy of the index card of their future spouse, which would detail their age, previous marriages, significant medical conditions, children, addresses, public positions, criminal records, property assignments, and more. It might also be wise to hold a brief ceremony for each person, separately, where this information could be presented to witnesses, along with some required statements from legal counsel. After this, there would be a reasonable period for either person to reflect and reconsider. If both still wanted to proceed after this waiting period, they would then inform the local official, and the necessary details would be recorded in the registers. These formalities would operate independently of any religious ceremonies the couple might choose, as the modern State does not concern itself with religious beliefs or practices.

So much for the preliminary conditions of matrimony. For those men and women who chose to ignore these conditions and to achieve any sort of union they liked the State would have no concern, unless offspring were born illegitimately. In that case, as we have already suggested, it would be only reasonable to make the parents chargeable with every duty, with maintenance, education, and so forth, that in the normal course of things would fall to the State. It would be necessary to impose a life assurance payment upon these parents, and to exact effectual guarantees against every possible evasion of the responsibility they had incurred. But the further control of private morality, beyond the protection of the immature from corruption and evil example, will be no concern of the State's. When a child comes in, the future of the species comes in; and the State comes in as the guardian of interests wider than the individual's; but the adult's private life is the entirely private life into which the State may not intrude.

So much for the basic requirements of marriage. For those men and women who decide to ignore these requirements and form whatever kind of union they wish, the State has no concern, unless children are born outside of marriage. In that case, as we've already mentioned, it would be reasonable to hold the parents responsible for all duties, such as support, education, and so on, that would normally be the State's responsibility. It would be necessary to require a life insurance payment from these parents and to enforce effective guarantees against any possible avoidance of the responsibilities they have taken on. However, the State will not take further control over private morality, apart from protecting minors from corruption and negative influences. When a child is born, the future of the species is involved; the State then acts as the guardian of broader interests beyond the individual’s; but an adult's private life remains completely private, and the State should not interfere.

Now what will be the nature of the Utopian contract of matrimony?

Now what will the Utopian marriage agreement look like?

From the first of the two points of view named above, that of parentage, it is obvious that one unavoidable condition will be the chastity of the wife. Her infidelity being demonstrated, must at once terminate the marriage and release both her husband and the State from any liability for the support of her illegitimate offspring. That, at any rate, is beyond controversy; a marriage contract that does not involve that, is a triumph of metaphysics over common sense. It will be obvious that under Utopian conditions it is the State that will suffer injury by a wife's misconduct, and that a husband who condones anything of the sort will participate in her offence. A woman, therefore, who is divorced on this account will be divorced as a public offender, and not in the key of a personal quarrel; not as one who has inflicted a private and personal wrong. This, too, lies within the primary implications of marriage.

From the first of the two perspectives mentioned above, that of parentage, it's clear that one unavoidable condition is the wife's fidelity. If she's proven to be unfaithful, it must immediately end the marriage and free both her husband and the State from any responsibility for the support of her illegitimate children. That is, at least, beyond dispute; a marriage agreement that doesn't include that is a victory of abstract reasoning over common sense. It's clear that under ideal conditions, the State is the one harmed by a wife's infidelity, and a husband who overlooks any of that shares in her wrongdoing. Therefore, a woman who is divorced for this reason will be regarded as a public offender, rather than just someone in a personal dispute; not as someone who has committed a private and personal wrong. This, too, falls within the basic implications of marriage.

Beyond that, what conditions should a marriage contract in Utopia involve?

Beyond that, what conditions should a marriage contract in Utopia have?

A reciprocal restraint on the part of the husband is clearly of no importance whatever, so far as the first end of matrimony goes, the protection of the community from inferior births. It is no wrong to the State. But it does carry with it a variable amount of emotional offence to the wife; it may wound her pride and cause her violent perturbations of jealousy; it may lead to her neglect, her solitude and unhappiness, and it may even work to her physical injury. There should be an implication that it is not to occur. She has bound herself to the man for the good of the State, and clearly it is reasonable that she should look to the State for relief if it does occur. The extent of the offence given her is the exact measure of her injury; if she does not mind nobody minds, and if her self-respect does not suffer nothing whatever is lost to the world; and so it should rest with her to establish his misconduct, and, if she thinks fit, to terminate the marriage.

A mutual commitment from the husband doesn't really matter when it comes to the main purpose of marriage, which is to protect the community from poor offspring. It doesn’t harm the State. However, it can cause varying degrees of emotional hurt to the wife; it might hurt her pride and trigger intense jealousy; it might lead to her feeling neglected, alone, and unhappy, and it could even harm her physically. There should be an understanding that this shouldn’t happen. She has committed to the man for the sake of the State, so it’s reasonable for her to seek help from the State if it does happen. The degree of offense she feels reflects her injury; if she’s okay with it, then no one else should care, and if her self-respect isn’t damaged, nothing significant is lost. Ultimately, it should be up to her to prove his wrongdoing and, if she chooses, to end the marriage.

A failure on either side to perform the elementary duties of companionship, desertion, for example, should obviously give the other mate the right to relief, and clearly the development of any disqualifying habit, drunkenness, or drug-taking, or the like, or any serious crime or acts of violence, should give grounds for a final release. Moreover, the modern Utopian State intervenes between the sexes only because of the coming generation, and for it to sustain restrictions upon conduct in a continually fruitless marriage is obviously to lapse into purely moral intervention. It seems reasonable, therefore, to set a term to a marriage that remains childless, to let it expire at the end of three or four or five unfruitful years, but with no restriction upon the right of the husband and wife to marry each other again.

If either partner fails to fulfill basic responsibilities in a relationship, like abandonment, the other partner should definitely have the right to seek relief. Similarly, developing any disqualifying habits, such as alcoholism or drug abuse, or committing serious crimes or acts of violence, should provide grounds for ending the marriage. Additionally, the modern ideal society only intervenes between partners for the sake of future generations. To maintain restrictions on behavior in a marriage that is consistently unproductive is essentially just moral interference. Therefore, it makes sense to set a limit on childless marriages, allowing them to end after three, four, or five unproductive years, while not restricting the couple's right to remarry each other.

These are the fairly easy primaries of this question. We now come to the more difficult issues of the matter. The first of these is the question of the economic relationships of husband and wife, having regard to the fact that even in Utopia women, at least until they become mothers, are likely to be on the average poorer than men. The second is the question of the duration of a marriage. But the two interlock, and are, perhaps, best treated together in one common section. And they both ramify in the most complicated manner into the consideration of the general morale of the community.

These are the relatively straightforward primary issues of this question. Now, we turn to the more complex aspects of the matter. The first is about the economic relationships between husbands and wives, considering that even in an ideal society, women, at least until they become mothers, are generally poorer than men. The second issue is the length of a marriage. However, these two are interconnected and might be best discussed together in one common section. Both also branch out in a very complicated way into the consideration of the overall morale of the community.

§ 5

This question of marriage is the most complicated and difficult in the whole range of Utopian problems. But it is happily not the most urgent necessity that it should be absolutely solved. The urgent and necessary problem is the ruler. With rulers rightly contrived and a provisional defective marriage law a Utopia may be conceived as existing and studying to perfect itself, but without rulers a Utopia is impossible though the theory of its matrimony be complete. And the difficulty in this question is not simply the difficulty of a complicated chess problem, for example, in which the whole tangle of considerations does at least lie in one plane, but a series of problems upon different levels and containing incommensurable factors.

The issue of marriage is the most complex and challenging among all Utopian questions. Fortunately, it's not the most pressing need for a complete resolution. The urgent and essential issue is the ruler. With the right rulers in place and a temporary, flawed marriage law, a Utopia can be envisioned as emerging and striving for improvement. However, without rulers, a Utopia is unachievable, even if the theory of marriage is perfect. The challenge here isn’t merely like a complicated chess problem, where all the factors are on the same level, but rather a series of problems on different levels that include unmatched and incomparable elements.

It is very easy to repeat our initial propositions, to recall that we are on another planet, and that all the customs and traditions of the earth are set aside, but the faintest realisation of that demands a feat of psychological insight. We have all grown up into an invincible mould of suggestion about sexual things; we regard this with approval, that with horror, and this again with contempt, very largely because the thing has always been put to us in this light or that. The more emancipated we think ourselves the more subtle are our bonds. The disentanglement of what is inherent in these feelings from what is acquired is an extraordinary complex undertaking. Probably all men and women have a more or less powerful disposition to jealousy, but what exactly they will be jealous about and what exactly they will suffer seems part of the superposed factor. Probably all men and women are capable of ideal emotions and wishes beyond merely physical desires, but the shape these take are almost entirely a reaction to external images. And you really cannot strip the external off; you cannot get your stark natural man, jealous, but not jealous about anything in particular, imaginative without any imaginings, proud at large. Emotional dispositions can no more exist without form than a man without air. Only a very observant man who had lived all over the planet Earth, in all sorts of social strata, and with every race and tongue, and who was endowed with great imaginative insight, could hope to understand the possibilities and the limitations of human plasticity in this matter, and say what any men and any women could be induced to do willingly, and just exactly what no man and no woman could stand, provided one had the training of them. Though very young men will tell you readily enough. The proceedings of other races and other ages do not seem to carry conviction; what our ancestors did, or what the Greeks or Egyptians did, though it is the direct physical cause of the modern young man or the modern young lady, is apt to impress these remarkable consequences merely as an arrangement of quaint, comical or repulsive proceedings.

It's really easy to repeat our initial thoughts, to remember that we're on another planet, and that all the customs and traditions of Earth don’t apply here, but actually grasping that requires some deep psychological insight. We've all grown up with strong influences about sexual matters; we view some things positively, others negatively, and some with disdain, largely because we’ve always been presented with these perspectives. The more free we think we are, the more subtle our constraints are. Untangling what is natural in these feelings from what is learned is a really complex task. Most people have a basic tendency toward jealousy, but what exactly they will be jealous about and what they will endure seems to depend on external factors. Most people can have ideal emotions and desires beyond just physical attraction, but the way these manifest is mostly a response to outside influences. You really can’t strip away those external influences; you can’t get a basic, natural human who feels jealousy but isn’t jealous about anything specific, is imaginative without any specific thoughts, or is proud in general. Emotional tendencies can’t exist without a form, just like a person can't live without air. Only someone very observant who has lived all over the Earth, among various social classes and cultures, and who has great imaginative insight, could hope to understand the possibilities and limitations of human flexibility in this area, and be able to say what any man or woman could be encouraged to do willingly, and exactly what no man or woman could tolerate, as long as they had the right training. Although young men are usually quick to share their thoughts. The experiences of other races and times don’t seem convincing; what our ancestors did, or what the Greeks or Egyptians did—which is the direct physical cause of the modern young man or woman—often comes across to these young people as just a collection of strange, funny, or disgusting practices.

But there emerges to the modern inquirer certain ideals and desiderata that at least go some way towards completing and expanding the crude primaries of a Utopian marriage law set out in § 4.

But there are certain ideals and desires that come to the attention of the modern inquirer, which at least help to complete and expand the basic principles of a Utopian marriage law outlined in § 4.

The sound birth being assured, does there exist any valid reason for the persistence of the Utopian marriage union?

The sound birth being assured, is there any valid reason for the continuation of the ideal marriage union?

There are two lines of reasoning that go to establish a longer duration for marriage. The first of these rests upon the general necessity for a home and for individual attention in the case of children. Children are the results of a choice between individuals; they grow well, as a rule, only in relation to sympathetic and kindred individualities, and no wholesale character-ignoring method of dealing with them has ever had a shadow of the success of the individualised home. Neither Plato nor Socrates, who repudiated the home, seems ever to have had to do with anything younger than a young man. Procreation is only the beginning of parentage, and even where the mother is not the direct nurse and teacher of her child, even where she delegates these duties, her supervision is, in the common case, essential to its welfare. Moreover, though the Utopian State will pay the mother, and the mother only, for the being and welfare of her legitimate children, there will be a clear advantage in fostering the natural disposition of the father to associate his child's welfare with his individual egotism, and to dispense some of his energies and earnings in supplementing the common provision of the State. It is an absurd disregard of a natural economy to leave the innate philoprogenitiveness of either sex uncultivated. Unless the parents continue in close relationship, if each is passing through a series of marriages, the dangers of a conflict of rights, and of the frittering away of emotions, become very grave. The family will lose homogeneity, and its individuals will have for the mother varied and perhaps incompatible emotional associations. The balance of social advantage is certainly on the side of much more permanent unions, on the side of an arrangement that, subject to ample provisions for a formal divorce without disgrace in cases of incompatibility, would bind, or at least enforce ideals that would tend to bind, a man and woman together for the whole term of her maternal activity, until, that is, the last born of her children was no longer in need of her help.

There are two main reasons for why marriages tend to last longer. The first involves the fundamental need for a home and individual attention for children. Children come from the choices made by individuals and generally thrive best in environments with supportive and caring relationships; no broad, impersonal approach to raising them has ever been as effective as a personalized home life. Neither Plato nor Socrates, who rejected the idea of the home, seemed to engage with anyone younger than a young adult. Having children is just the start of being a parent, and even when a mother isn’t directly caring for her child—whether by hiring help or delegating tasks—her oversight usually remains crucial for the child’s well-being. Furthermore, while a Utopian state may financially support mothers for the existence and care of their legitimate children, there’s a clear benefit in encouraging fathers to connect their child’s well-being to their personal interests, motivating them to invest their time and resources beyond what the state provides. It’s quite unreasonable to ignore the natural nurturing instinct in both genders. If parents don’t maintain a close relationship and each goes through multiple marriages, the risk of conflicting rights and emotional exhaustion increases significantly. The family will lose its unity, and children may have mixed and possibly conflicting emotional ties to their mother. The social benefits certainly favor more stable unions, and relationships that, while allowing for a respectful divorce in cases of incompatibility, compel a man and woman to stay together through the entire period of her motherhood, until the youngest child no longer requires her support.

The second system of considerations arises out of the artificiality of woman's position. It is a less conclusive series than the first, and it opens a number of interesting side vistas.

The second set of considerations comes from the constructed nature of a woman's role. It's a less definitive series than the first, and it presents several intriguing side perspectives.

A great deal of nonsense is talked about the natural equality or inferiority of women to men. But it is only the same quality that can be measured by degrees and ranged in ascending and descending series, and the things that are essentially feminine are different qualitatively from and incommensurable with the distinctly masculine things. The relationship is in the region of ideals and conventions, and a State is perfectly free to determine that men and women shall come to intercourse on a footing of conventional equality or with either the man or woman treated as the predominating individual. Aristotle's criticism of Plato in this matter, his insistence upon the natural inferiority of slaves and women, is just the sort of confusion between inherent and imposed qualities that was his most characteristic weakness. The spirit of the European people, of almost all the peoples now in the ascendant, is towards a convention of equality; the spirit of the Mahometan world is towards the intensification of a convention that the man alone is a citizen and that the woman is very largely his property. There can be no doubt that the latter of these two convenient fictions is the more primitive way of regarding this relationship. It is quite unfruitful to argue between these ideals as if there were a demonstrable conclusion, the adoption of either is an arbitrary act, and we shall simply follow our age and time if we display a certain bias for the former.

A lot of nonsense is talked about the natural equality or inferiority of women compared to men. However, it’s only the same quality that can be measured in degrees and ranked in order, and the things that are fundamentally feminine are qualitatively different from and incomparable to the distinctly masculine things. The relationship exists in the realm of ideals and conventions, and a State is perfectly entitled to decide that men and women interact on a basis of conventional equality or with either the man or woman being considered the dominant individual. Aristotle’s critique of Plato on this issue, where he insisted on the natural inferiority of slaves and women, represents that same confusion between inherent and imposed qualities, which was his most notable flaw. The mindset of the European people, and almost all the peoples currently in the spotlight, leans towards a convention of equality; meanwhile, the mindset of the Muslim world pushes for a convention where only men are seen as citizens, and women are largely viewed as their property. There’s no doubt that the latter of these two convenient ideas is a more primitive way of looking at this relationship. It’s pointless to argue between these ideals as if there’s a clear conclusion; adopting either is an arbitrary decision, and we will simply reflect our era if we show a preference for the former.

If one looks closely into the various practical expansions of these ideas, we find their inherent falsity works itself out in a very natural way so soon as reality is touched. Those who insist upon equality work in effect for assimilation, for a similar treatment of the sexes. Plato's women of the governing class, for example, were to strip for gymnastics like men, to bear arms and go to war, and follow most of the masculine occupations of their class. They were to have the same education and to be assimilated to men at every doubtful point. The Aristotelian attitude, on the other hand, insists upon specialisation. The men are to rule and fight and toil; the women are to support motherhood in a state of natural inferiority. The trend of evolutionary forces through long centuries of human development has been on the whole in this second direction, has been towards differentiation. [Footnote: See Havelock Ellis's Man and Woman.] An adult white woman differs far more from a white man than a negress or pigmy woman from her equivalent male. The education, the mental disposition, of a white or Asiatic woman, reeks of sex; her modesty, her decorum is not to ignore sex but to refine and put a point to it; her costume is clamorous with the distinctive elements of her form. The white woman in the materially prosperous nations is more of a sexual specialist than her sister of the poor and austere peoples, of the prosperous classes more so than the peasant woman. The contemporary woman of fashion who sets the tone of occidental intercourse is a stimulant rather than a companion for a man. Too commonly she is an unwholesome stimulant turning a man from wisdom to appearance, from beauty to beautiful pleasures, from form to colour, from persistent aims to belief and stirring triumphs. Arrayed in what she calls distinctly “dress,” scented, adorned, displayed, she achieves by artifice a sexual differentiation profounder than that of any other vertebrated animal. She outshines the peacock's excess above his mate, one must probe among the domestic secrets of the insects and crustacea to find her living parallel. And it is a question by no means easy and yet of the utmost importance, to determine how far the wide and widening differences between the human sexes is inherent and inevitable, and how far it is an accident of social development that may be converted and reduced under a different social regimen. Are we going to recognise and accentuate this difference and to arrange our Utopian organisation to play upon it, are we to have two primary classes of human being, harmonising indeed and reacting, but following essentially different lives, or are we going to minimise this difference in every possible way?

If you look closely at the various practical applications of these ideas, you'll see that their intrinsic falsehood reveals itself quite naturally as soon as reality is addressed. Those who demand equality essentially push for assimilation, advocating for uniform treatment of the genders. For instance, Plato's women in the ruling class were meant to exercise like men, carry weapons, go to war, and take on most of the male-dominated roles in their class. They were to receive the same education and be integrated with men at every uncertain point. In contrast, Aristotle's perspective insists on specialization. Men are to lead, fight, and labor, while women are meant to embrace motherhood in a state of natural inferiority. Over long centuries of human development, evolutionary forces overall have leaned toward this second viewpoint, which emphasizes differentiation. [Footnote: See Havelock Ellis's Man and Woman.] An adult white woman is much more different from a white man than a Black woman or a pygmy woman is from her male counterpart. The education and mentality of a white or Asian woman are heavily influenced by gender; her modesty and decorum don't ignore gender but refine and emphasize it; her clothing is loud with the distinctive aspects of her form. The white woman in affluent societies is a more pronounced sexual specialist than her counterpart from poorer, simpler societies, and she's more so than a peasant woman. The fashionable modern woman who shapes Western social interactions acts more as a stimulant than a companion for men. Too often, she serves as an unhealthy stimulus, diverting men from wisdom to mere appearances, from beauty to superficial pleasures, from substance to style, and from enduring goals to transient triumphs. Dressed in what she calls "fashion," smelling good, decorated, and on display, she creates a sexual differentiation deeper than that of any other vertebrate. She exceeds the peacock in flamboyance above his mate; one must explore the private lives of insects and crustaceans to find a comparable example. It poses a complex yet crucial question to determine how much of the widening differences between sexes is inherent and unavoidable, and how much is a social development accident that could be changed with a different societal structure. Are we going to recognize and emphasize this difference and structure our ideal society around it, creating two main classes of humanity that harmonize and interact but lead fundamentally different lives, or will we strive to minimize this difference in every way possible?

The former alternative leads either to a romantic organisation of society in which men will live and fight and die for wonderful, beautiful, exaggerated creatures, or it leads to the hareem. It would probably lead through one phase to the other. Women would be enigmas and mysteries and maternal dignitaries that one would approach in a state of emotional excitement and seclude piously when serious work was in hand. A girl would blossom from the totally negligible to the mystically desirable at adolescence, and boys would be removed from their mother's educational influence at as early an age as possible. Whenever men and women met together, the men would be in a state of inflamed competition towards one another, and the women likewise, and the intercourse of ideas would be in suspense. Under the latter alternative the sexual relation would be subordinated to friendship and companionship; boys and girls would be co-educated—very largely under maternal direction, and women, disarmed of their distinctive barbaric adornments, the feathers, beads, lace, and trimmings that enhance their clamorous claim to a directly personal attention would mingle, according to their quality, in the counsels and intellectual development of men. Such women would be fit to educate boys even up to adolescence. It is obvious that a marriage law embodying a decision between these two sets of ideas would be very different according to the alternative adopted. In the former case a man would be expected to earn and maintain in an adequate manner the dear delight that had favoured him. He would tell her beautiful lies about her wonderful moral effect upon him, and keep her sedulously from all responsibility and knowledge. And, since there is an undeniably greater imaginative appeal to men in the first bloom of a woman's youth, she would have a distinct claim upon his energies for the rest of her life. In the latter case a man would no more pay for and support his wife than she would do so for him. They would be two friends, differing in kind no doubt but differing reciprocally, who had linked themselves in a matrimonial relationship. Our Utopian marriage so far as we have discussed it, is indeterminate between these alternatives.

The first option either results in a romantic society where men will live, fight, and die for amazing, beautiful, and exaggerated beings, or it leads to a harem. It would probably transition from one phase to the other. Women would be seen as enigmas and mysteries and respected matriarchs, approached with emotional excitement and then set aside when serious tasks needed to be tackled. A girl would transform from being completely overlooked to being mysteriously desirable during adolescence, and boys would be distanced from their mothers’ influence as early as possible. Whenever men and women gathered, competition among the men would be intense, and the same would apply to the women, resulting in a stifling of the exchange of ideas. In the second scenario, the sexual relationship would take a backseat to friendship and companionship; boys and girls would be educated together—mostly under maternal guidance, and women, stripped of their distinctive and flashy adornments like feathers, beads, lace, and trimmings that draw personal attention, would mix according to their abilities in the discussions and intellectual growth of men. Such women would be qualified to educate boys up to adolescence. It's clear that a marriage law reflecting a choice between these two concepts would differ significantly based on the option chosen. In the first case, a man would be expected to earn and provide adequately for the beloved companion who had chosen him. He would tell her sweet lies about her positive moral influence on him and keep her shielded from any responsibility or knowledge. And, since there is undeniably a stronger imaginative allure for men in the early years of a woman's youth, she would deserve his energy for the rest of her life. In the second case, a man wouldn’t more financially support his wife than she would him. They would be two friends, different in many ways but still equal, who had chosen to enter a marriage together. Our ideal marriage, as we've discussed it, remains unclear between these two options.

We have laid it down as a general principle that the private morals of an adult citizen are no concern for the State. But that involves a decision to disregard certain types of bargain. A sanely contrived State will refuse to sustain bargains wherein there is no plausibly fair exchange, and if private morality is really to be outside the scope of the State then the affections and endearments most certainly must not be regarded as negotiable commodities. The State, therefore, will absolutely ignore the distribution of these favours unless children, or at least the possibility of children, is involved. It follows that it will refuse to recognise any debts or transfers of property that are based on such considerations. It will be only consistent, therefore, to refuse recognition in the marriage contract to any financial obligation between husband and wife, or any settlements qualifying that contract, except when they are in the nature of accessory provision for the prospective children. [Footnote: Unqualified gifts for love by solvent people will, of course, be quite possible and permissible, unsalaried services and the like, provided the standard of life is maintained and the joint income of the couple between whom the services hold does not sink below twice the minimum wage.] So far the Utopian State will throw its weight upon the side of those who advocate the independence of women and their conventional equality with men.

We have established a general rule that the personal morals of an adult citizen are not the concern of the State. However, this means deciding to ignore certain types of agreements. A well-functioning State will not support deals where there is no reasonably fair exchange, and if personal morality is genuinely outside the State's domain, then affection and love certainly must not be treated as negotiable assets. Therefore, the State will completely overlook the distribution of these affections unless children, or at least the potential for children, are involved. Consequently, it will not recognize any debts or property transfers based on such issues. Thus, it will be consistent to deny recognition in the marriage contract of any financial obligations between husband and wife, or any settlements related to that contract, except when they are meant for the benefit of potential children. [Footnote: Unconditional gifts given out of love by financially stable individuals will, of course, be entirely possible and allowed, as well as unpaid services, as long as the standard of living is maintained and the combined income of the couple involved does not drop below twice the minimum wage.] Up to this point, the ideal State will support those who promote women's independence and their equal standing with men.

But to any further definition of the marriage relation the World State of Utopia will not commit itself. The wide range of relationships that are left possible, within and without the marriage code, are entirely a matter for the individual choice and imagination. Whether a man treat his wife in private as a goddess to be propitiated, as a “mystery” to be adored, as an agreeable auxiliary, as a particularly intimate friend, or as the wholesome mother of his children, is entirely a matter for their private intercourse: whether he keep her in Oriental idleness or active co-operation, or leave her to live her independent life, rests with the couple alone, and all the possible friendship and intimacies outside marriage also lie quite beyond the organisation of the modern State. Religious teaching and literature may affect these; customs may arise; certain types of relationship may involve social isolation; the justice of the statesman is blind to such things. It may be urged that according to Atkinson's illuminating analysis [Footnote: See Lang and Atkinson's Social Origins and Primal Law.] the control of love-making was the very origin of the human community. In Utopia, nevertheless, love-making is no concern of the State's beyond the province that the protection of children covers. [Footnote: It cannot be made too clear that though the control of morality is outside the law the State must maintain a general decorum, a systematic suppression of powerful and moving examples, and of incitations and temptations of the young and inexperienced, and to that extent it will, of course, in a sense, exercise a control over morals. But this will be only part of a wider law to safeguard the tender mind. For example, lying advertisements, and the like, when they lean towards adolescent interests, will encounter a specially disagreeable disposition in the law, over and above the treatment of their general dishonesty.] Change of function is one of the ruling facts in life, the sac that was in our remotest ancestors a swimming bladder is now a lung, and the State which was once, perhaps, no more than the jealous and tyrannous will of the strongest male in the herd, the instrument of justice and equality. The State intervenes now only where there is want of harmony between individuals—individuals who exist or who may presently come into existence.

But the World State of Utopia won't define the marriage relationship any further. The variety of relationships that are possible, both within and outside the marriage code, is completely up to individual choice and imagination. A man can treat his wife in private as a goddess to be worshipped, as a "mystery" to be cherished, as a supportive partner, as a close friend, or as the nurturing mother of his children—it's entirely up to them. Whether he keeps her in a state of leisure or encourages her active participation, or allows her to live independently, is a decision for the couple alone, and all possible friendships and connections outside of marriage are beyond the scope of the modern State. Religious teachings and literature may influence these choices; customs may develop; certain types of relationships might lead to social isolation; the fairness of the statesman is indifferent to such matters. It can be argued that, as per Atkinson's insightful analysis [Footnote: See Lang and Atkinson's Social Origins and Primal Law.], the regulation of romance was the very foundation of human society. However, in Utopia, romance is not the State's concern beyond ensuring the protection of children. [Footnote: It cannot be emphasized enough that while controlling morality falls outside of legal boundaries, the State must uphold a general standard of decorum, systematically suppressing strong examples and temptations for the young and inexperienced, and to that extent, it will exercise some control over morals. This, however, will only be part of a broader law designed to protect sensitive minds. For example, misleading advertisements that target adolescent interests will face particular disapproval in the law, in addition to being treated as generally dishonest.] Functional change is a fundamental aspect of life; the sac that served as a swimming bladder for our distant ancestors is now a lung, and the State, which once might have been merely the jealous and oppressive will of the strongest male in the group, now serves as an instrument of justice and equality. The State intervenes only when there is a lack of harmony among individuals—those who exist or may come into being.

§ 6

It must be reiterated that our reasoning still leaves Utopian marriage an institution with wide possibilities of variation. We have tried to give effect to the ideal of a virtual equality, an equality of spirit between men and women, and in doing so we have overridden the accepted opinion of the great majority of mankind. Probably the first writer to do as much was Plato. His argument in support of this innovation upon natural human feeling was thin enough—a mere analogy to illustrate the spirit of his propositions; it was his creative instinct that determined him. In the atmosphere of such speculations as this, Plato looms very large indeed, and in view of what we owe to him, it seems reasonable that we should hesitate before dismissing as a thing prohibited and evil, a type of marriage that he made almost the central feature in the organisation of the ruling class, at least, of his ideal State. He was persuaded that the narrow monogamic family is apt to become illiberal and anti-social, to withdraw the imagination and energies of the citizen from the services of the community as a whole, and the Roman Catholic Church has so far endorsed and substantiated his opinion as to forbid family relations to its priests and significant servants. He conceived of a poetic devotion to the public idea, a devotion of which the mind of Aristotle, as his criticisms of Plato show, was incapable, as a substitute for the warm and tender but illiberal emotions of the home. But while the Church made the alternative to family ties celibacy [Footnote: The warm imagination of Campanella, that quaint Calabrian monastic, fired by Plato, reversed this aspect of the Church.] and participation in an organisation, Plato was far more in accordance with modern ideas in perceiving the disadvantage that would result from precluding the nobler types of character from offspring. He sought a way to achieve progeny, therefore, without the narrow concentration of the sympathies about the home, and he found it in a multiple marriage in which every member of the governing class was considered to be married to all the others. But the detailed operation of this system he put tentatively and very obscurely. His suggestions have the experimental inconsistency of an enquiring man. He left many things altogether open, and it is unfair to him to adopt Aristotle's forensic method and deal with his discussion as though it was a fully-worked-out project. It is clear that Plato intended every member of his governing class to be so “changed at birth” as to leave paternity untraceable; mothers were not to know their children, nor children their parents, but there is nothing to forbid the supposition that he intended these people to select and adhere to congenial mates within the great family. Aristotle's assertion that the Platonic republic left no scope for the virtue of continence shows that he had jumped to just the same conclusions a contemporary London errand boy, hovering a little shamefacedly over Jowett in a public library, might be expected to reach.

It’s important to emphasize that our reasoning still allows for a wide range of variations in Utopian marriage. We have tried to embody the ideal of a practical equality, a balance of spirit between men and women, and in doing so, we have gone against the accepted views of most people. Plato was probably the first writer to do this. His argument supporting this shift from natural human feelings was quite shallow—a simple analogy meant to illustrate his ideas; it was his creative instinct that motivated him. In the realm of such speculations, Plato stands out significantly, and considering what we owe to him, it makes sense to reconsider dismissing a type of marriage he positioned as a central aspect of the ruling class in his ideal State as something forbidden and wrong. He believed that the narrow monogamous family tends to become intolerant and anti-social, pulling individuals away from engaging with the larger community. The Roman Catholic Church has partly supported this view by banning family relationships for its priests and important servants. Plato imagined a poetic dedication to the public good, a commitment that Aristotle, as shown by his critiques of Plato, couldn't grasp, serving as a replacement for the warm yet narrow emotions tied to home life. While the Church presented celibacy as the alternative to family connections, along with participating in an organization, Plato aligned more closely with modern ideas by recognizing the drawbacks of excluding noble character types from having children. He looked for a way to create descendants without the restricted focus on home and found it in multiple marriage, where every member of the ruling class was considered married to all the others. However, he presented the specifics of this system tentatively and ambiguously. His ideas have the experimental uncertainty of someone curious and open to exploration. He left many aspects open-ended, and it’s unfair to apply Aristotle's argumentative approach and treat his discussions as a fully developed plan. It’s clear that Plato intended for every member of his ruling class to be “changed at birth” so that parenthood was untraceable; mothers were not to know their children, nor children their parents, but it doesn’t rule out the possibility that he meant for these individuals to choose and connect with compatible partners within the large family. Aristotle’s claim that the Platonic republic did not allow for the virtue of self-restraint suggests that he arrived at conclusions similar to what a contemporary London delivery boy, feeling a bit embarrassed at the library with Jowett, might also reach.

Aristotle obscures Plato's intention, it may be accidentally, by speaking of his marriage institution as a community of wives. When reading Plato he could not or would not escape reading in his own conception of the natural ascendency of men, his idea of property in women and children. But as Plato intended women to be conventionally equal to men, this phrase belies him altogether; community of husbands and wives would be truer to his proposal. Aristotle condemns Plato as roundly as any commercial room would condemn him to-day, and in much the same spirit; he asserts rather than proves that such a grouping is against the nature of man. He wanted to have women property just as he wanted to have slaves property, he did not care to ask why, and it distressed his conception of convenience extremely to imagine any other arrangement. It is no doubt true that the natural instinct of either sex is exclusive of participators in intimacy during a period of intimacy, but it was probably Aristotle who gave Plato an offensive interpretation in this matter. No one would freely submit to such a condition of affairs as multiple marriage carried out, in the spirit of the Aristotelian interpretation, to an obscene completeness, but that is all the more reason why the modern Utopia should not refuse a grouped marriage to three or more freely consenting persons. There is no sense in prohibiting institutions which no sane people could ever want to abuse. It is claimed—though the full facts are difficult to ascertain—that a group marriage of over two hundred persons was successfully organised by John Humphrey Noyes at Oneida Creek. [Footnote: See John H. Noyes's History of American Socialisms and his writings generally. The bare facts of this and the other American experiments are given, together with more recent matter, by Morris Hillquirt, in The History of Socialism in the United States.] It is fairly certain in the latter case that there was no “promiscuity,” and that the members mated for variable periods, and often for life, within the group. The documents are reasonably clear upon that point. This Oneida community was, in fact, a league of two hundred persons to regard their children as “common.” Choice and preference were not abolished in the community, though in some cases they were set aside—just as they are by many parents under our present conditions. There seems to have been a premature attempt at “stirpiculture,” at what Mr. Francis Galton now calls “Eugenics,” in the mating of the members, and there was also a limitation of offspring. Beyond these points the inner secrets of the community do not appear to be very profound; its atmosphere was almost commonplace, it was made up of very ordinary people. There is no doubt that it had a career of exceptional success throughout the whole lifetime of its founder, and it broke down with the advent of a new generation, with the onset of theological differences, and the loss of its guiding intelligence. The Anglo-Saxon spirit, it has been said by one of the ablest children of the experiment, is too individualistic for communism. It is possible to regard the temporary success of this complex family as a strange accident, as the wonderful exploit of what was certainly a very exceptional man. Its final disintegration into frankly monogamic couples—it is still a prosperous business association—may be taken as an experimental verification of Aristotle's common-sense psychology, and was probably merely the public acknowledgment of conditions already practically established.

Aristotle unintentionally clouds Plato's intention by describing his marriage model as a community of wives. When reading Plato, he could not or would not overlook his own views on the natural dominance of men and his perspective on property concerning women and children. However, since Plato aimed for women to be traditionally equal to men, this term misrepresents him; a community of husbands and wives would align better with his idea. Aristotle criticizes Plato as harshly as any business might today, asserting without evidence that such a system goes against human nature. He wanted women to be treated as property just like slaves, without questioning why, and it greatly troubled his sense of convenience to consider any alternative. It’s true that there’s a natural tendency for exclusivity in intimacy, but Aristotle likely distorted Plato's views in this respect. Nobody would willingly agree to a setup where multiple marriages, viewed through Aristotle's lens, reach an offensive conclusion; however, that shouldn't mean that modern society should reject a grouped marriage involving three or more consenting individuals. There's no reason to ban institutions that sane people would never want to exploit. It’s reported—though details are hard to confirm—that John Humphrey Noyes successfully organized a group marriage of over two hundred people at Oneida Creek. [Footnote: See John H. Noyes's History of American Socialisms and his writings generally. The basic facts of this and other American experiments are presented alongside more recent information by Morris Hillquit in The History of Socialism in the United States.] In this case, it seems there was no "promiscuity," as members paired for varying durations, often for life, within the group. The records are quite clear on this point. The Oneida community was essentially a collective of two hundred people who viewed their children as "common." Choices and preferences weren't eliminated within the community, though they were sometimes put aside—similar to how many parents act today. There seemed to be an early attempt at “stirpiculture,” akin to what Mr. Francis Galton now calls “Eugenics,” regarding member pairings, and there were limits on offspring. Other than these points, the internal workings of the community don’t appear to be very complex; its atmosphere was almost ordinary, filled with very typical individuals. It undoubtedly thrived exceptionally well during its founder's lifetime but collapsed with the emergence of a new generation, theological disagreements, and a loss of leadership. One skilled observer of the experiment noted that the Anglo-Saxon spirit is too individualistic for communism. The temporary success of this intricate family could be viewed as a curious coincidence, an extraordinary achievement for what was surely a very remarkable individual. Its eventual transformation into standard monogamous couples—yet still functioning as a profitable business—might be seen as a practical confirmation of Aristotle's straightforward psychology and likely represented an official recognition of conditions already in place.

Out of respect for Plato we cannot ignore this possibility of multiple marriage altogether in our Utopian theorising, but even if we leave this possibility open we are still bound to regard it as a thing so likely to be rare as not to come at all under our direct observation during our Utopian journeyings. But in one sense, of course, in the sense that the State guarantees care and support for all properly born children, our entire Utopia is to be regarded as a comprehensive marriage group. [Footnote: The Thelema of Rabelais, with its principle of “Fay ce que vouldras” within the limits of the order, is probably intended to suggest a Platonic complex marriage after the fashion of our interpretation.]

Out of respect for Plato, we can’t completely dismiss the idea of multiple marriages in our Utopian thoughts. However, even if we keep this possibility open, we still have to see it as something that’s likely to be so rare that we won’t observe it during our Utopian explorations. In one way, of course, since the State ensures care and support for all properly born children, we can consider our entire Utopia as a complete marriage group. [Footnote: The Thelema of Rabelais, with its principle of “Do what you will” within the limits of the order, likely suggests a Platonic complex marriage in line with our interpretation.]

It must be remembered that a modern Utopia must differ from the Utopias of any preceding age in being world-wide; it is not, therefore, to be the development of any special race or type of culture, as Plato's developed an Athenian-Spartan blend, or More, Tudor England. The modern Utopia is to be, before all things, synthetic. Politically and socially, as linguistically, we must suppose it a synthesis; politically it will be a synthesis of once widely different forms of government; socially and morally, a synthesis of a great variety of domestic traditions and ethical habits. Into the modern Utopia there must have entered the mental tendencies and origins that give our own world the polygamy of the Zulus and of Utah, the polyandry of Tibet, the latitudes of experiment permitted in the United States, and the divorceless wedlock of Comte. The tendency of all synthetic processes in matters of law and custom is to reduce and simplify the compulsory canon, to admit alternatives and freedoms; what were laws before become traditions of feeling and style, and in no matter will this be more apparent than in questions affecting the relations of the sexes.

It’s important to remember that a modern Utopia must be different from the Utopias of previous eras because it should be global; it's not meant to be based on any specific race or type of culture, like how Plato's was a mix of Athenian and Spartan influences, or More's was based on Tudor England. The modern Utopia should be, above all else, a synthesis. Politically, socially, and even linguistically, we have to think of it as a combination; politically, it will merge various forms of government that were once very different; socially and morally, it will blend many domestic traditions and ethical customs. The modern Utopia will incorporate the mental tendencies and backgrounds that reflect our own world’s diversity, like the polygamy practiced by the Zulus and in Utah, the polyandry seen in Tibet, the freedoms allowed in the United States, and the divorceless marriage concept of Comte. The trend in all synthetic approaches to law and customs is to reduce and simplify the mandatory rules, allowing for alternatives and freedoms; what were once strict laws become traditions of feeling and style, and this will be especially clear in matters regarding relationships between the sexes.

CHAPTER THE SEVENTH
A Few Utopian Impressions

§ 1

But now we are in a better position to describe the houses and ways of the Utopian townships about the Lake of Lucerne, and to glance a little more nearly at the people who pass. You figure us as curiously settled down in Utopia, as working for a low wage at wood-carving, until the authorities at the central registry in Paris can solve the perplexing problem we have set them. We stay in an inn looking out upon the lake, and go to and fro for our five hours' work a day, with a curious effect of having been born Utopians. The rest of our time is our own.

But now we’re in a better place to describe the houses and lifestyles of the Utopian townships around Lake Lucerne, and to take a closer look at the people who pass by. You imagine us as strangely settled in Utopia, working for a low wage in wood-carving, while the authorities at the central registry in Paris try to figure out the complicated problem we've presented them. We’re staying in an inn that overlooks the lake, and we go back and forth for our five hours of work each day, creating the odd impression that we were born Utopians. The rest of our time is ours to enjoy.

Our inn is one of those inns and lodging houses which have a minimum tariff, inns which are partly regulated, and, in the default of private enterprise, maintained and controlled by the World State throughout the entire world. It is one of several such establishments in Lucerne. It possesses many hundreds of practically self-cleaning little bedrooms, equipped very much after the fashion of the rooms we occupied in the similar but much smaller inn at Hospenthal, differing only a little in the decoration. There is the same dressing-room recess with its bath, the same graceful proportion in the succinct simplicity of its furniture. This particular inn is a quadrangle after the fashion of an Oxford college; it is perhaps forty feet high, and with about five stories of bedrooms above its lower apartments; the windows of the rooms look either outward or inward to the quadrangle, and the doors give upon artificially-lit passages with staircases passing up and down. These passages are carpeted with a sort of cork carpet, but are otherwise bare. The lower story is occupied by the equivalent of a London club, kitchens and other offices, dining-room, writing-room, smoking and assembly rooms, a barber's shop, and a library. A colonnade with seats runs about the quadrangle, and in the middle is a grass-plot. In the centre of this a bronze figure, a sleeping child, reposes above a little basin and fountain, in which water lilies are growing. The place has been designed by an architect happily free from the hampering traditions of Greek temple building, and of Roman and Italian palaces; it is simple, unaffected, gracious. The material is some artificial stone with the dull surface and something of the tint of yellow ivory; the colour is a little irregular, and a partial confession of girders and pillars breaks this front of tender colour with lines and mouldings of greenish gray, that blend with the tones of the leaden gutters and rain pipes from the light red roof. At one point only does any explicit effort towards artistic effect appear, and that is in the great arched gateway opposite my window. Two or three abundant yellow roses climb over the face of the building, and when I look out of my window in the early morning—for the usual Utopian working day commences within an hour of sunrise—I see Pilatus above this outlook, rosy in the morning sky.

Our inn is one of those inns and lodges that have a minimum rate, inns that are partly regulated and, in the absence of private enterprise, maintained and controlled by the World State all over the globe. It’s one of several such establishments in Lucerne. It features hundreds of nearly self-cleaning little bedrooms, designed similarly to the rooms we stayed in at the smaller inn in Hospenthal, differing only slightly in decoration. There’s the same dressing area with a bath, the same elegant simplicity in its furniture. This particular inn is arranged in a quadrangle like an Oxford college; it’s about forty feet high, with around five stories of bedrooms above the lower levels. The windows of the rooms face either outward or inward toward the quadrangle, and the doors open onto artificially lit corridors with staircases going up and down. These corridors have a kind of cork carpet but are otherwise bare. The ground floor is home to a London-style club, kitchens, and other facilities, a dining room, a writing room, smoking and gathering rooms, a barber shop, and a library. There's a colonnade with seating around the quadrangle, and in the center is a grassy area. In the middle of this, a bronze statue of a sleeping child rests above a small basin and fountain where water lilies grow. The place was designed by an architect who is thankfully free from the restrictive traditions of Greek temple architecture and Roman and Italian palaces; it’s simple, unpretentious, and elegant. The material is some artificial stone with a dull surface and a tint resembling yellow ivory; the color is slightly irregular, and partial exposure of girders and pillars breaks up this soft color with lines and moldings of greenish-gray that blend with the tones of the leaden gutters and rain pipes from the light red roof. Only in one spot is there any clear attempt at artistic effect, which is in the large arched entrance opposite my window. Two or three abundant yellow roses climb over the building’s exterior, and when I look out my window in the early morning—since the typical Utopian workday starts about an hour after sunrise—I see Pilatus rising above this view, glowing in the morning sky.

This quadrangle type of building is the prevalent element in Utopian Lucerne, and one may go from end to end of the town along corridors and covered colonnades without emerging by a gateway into the open roads at all. Small shops are found in these colonnades, but the larger stores are usually housed in buildings specially adapted to their needs. The majority of the residential edifices are far finer and more substantial than our own modest shelter, though we gather from such chance glimpses as we get of their arrangements that the labour-saving ideal runs through every grade of this servantless world; and what we should consider a complete house in earthly England is hardly known here.

This type of quadrangle building is the main feature in Utopian Lucerne, allowing people to walk from one end of the town to the other through corridors and covered walkways without ever stepping out onto the open streets. You can find small shops in these walkways, but the bigger stores are generally located in buildings specifically designed for them. Most of the residential buildings are much nicer and more substantial than our own simple homes, although from the glimpses we get of their layouts, it’s clear that the focus on labor-saving design is present in every level of this servant-free society; what we would consider a complete house in England is hardly found here.

The autonomy of the household has been reduced far below terrestrial conditions by hotels and clubs, and all sorts of co-operative expedients. People who do not live in hotels seem usually to live in clubs. The fairly prosperous Utopian belongs, in most cases, to one or two residential clubs of congenial men and women. These clubs usually possess in addition to furnished bedrooms more or less elaborate suites of apartments, and if a man prefers it one of these latter can be taken and furnished according to his personal taste. A pleasant boudoir, a private library and study, a private garden plot, are among the commonest of such luxuries. Devices to secure roof gardens, loggias, verandahs, and such-like open-air privacies to the more sumptuous of these apartments, give interest and variety to Utopian architecture. There are sometimes little cooking corners in these flats—as one would call them on earth—but the ordinary Utopian would no more think of a special private kitchen for his dinners than he would think of a private flour mill or dairy farm. Business, private work, and professional practice go on sometimes in the house apartments, but often in special offices in the great warren of the business quarter. A common garden, an infant school, play rooms, and a playing garden for children, are universal features of the club quadrangles.

The independence of the household has been significantly diminished by hotels, clubs, and various cooperative options. People who don’t live in hotels generally reside in clubs. The reasonably well-off Utopian usually belongs to one or two residential clubs with like-minded individuals. These clubs typically offer not only furnished bedrooms but also more or less elaborate apartment suites, and if someone prefers, they can choose one of these suites and decorate it to their liking. A cozy boudoir, a private library and study, and a small garden area are among the most common luxuries. Features like roof gardens, loggias, verandas, and other outdoor spaces add interest and variety to Utopian architecture. There are sometimes small cooking areas in these apartments—what one might call them on Earth—but a typical Utopian wouldn’t even consider having a separate private kitchen for meals any more than they would consider having their own flour mill or dairy farm. Business, personal work, and professional practices sometimes occur in the apartment, but often take place in designated offices in the busy business district. Shared gardens, an infant school, playrooms, and a play area for children are standard features of the club courtyards.

Two or three main roads with their tramways, their cyclists' paths, and swift traffic paths, will converge on the urban centre, where the public offices will stand in a group close to the two or three theatres and the larger shops, and hither, too, in the case of Lucerne, the head of the swift railway to Paris and England and Scotland, and to the Rhineland and Germany will run. And as one walks out from the town centre one will come to that mingling of homesteads and open country which will be the common condition of all the more habitable parts of the globe.

Two or three major roads with their tram lines, bike paths, and fast lanes will come together at the city center, where the public offices will be grouped close to two or three theaters and the larger stores. In the case of Lucerne, this is also where the high-speed rail line to Paris, England, Scotland, the Rhineland, and Germany will operate. As you walk away from the city center, you'll reach the blend of homes and open countryside that will be the typical feature of all the more livable areas around the world.

Here and there, no doubt, will stand quite solitary homesteads, homesteads that will nevertheless be lit and warmed by cables from the central force station, that will share the common water supply, will have their perfected telephonic connection with the rest of the world, with doctor, shop, and so forth, and may even have a pneumatic tube for books and small parcels to the nearest post-office. But the solitary homestead, as a permanent residence, will be something of a luxury—the resort of rather wealthy garden lovers; and most people with a bias for retirement will probably get as much residential solitude as they care for in the hire of a holiday châlet in a forest, by remote lagoons or high up the mountain side.

Here and there, you’ll definitely find some isolated homes, homes that will still be powered and heated by cables from the central power station, that will share the common water supply, will have an upgraded phone connection with the rest of the world, including doctors, shops, and more, and might even have a pneumatic tube for sending books and small packages to the nearest post office. But living in one of these isolated homes as a permanent residence will be more of a luxury—appealing mainly to wealthy gardening enthusiasts; most people who prefer solitude will likely find as much peace as they want by renting a holiday cabin in a forest, by quiet lagoons, or high up in the mountains.

The solitary house may indeed prove to be very rare indeed in Utopia. The same forces, the same facilitation of communications that will diffuse the towns will tend to little concentrations of the agricultural population over the country side. The field workers will probably take their food with them to their work during the day, and for the convenience of an interesting dinner and of civilised intercourse after the working day is over, they will most probably live in a college quadrangle with a common room and club. I doubt if there will be any agricultural labourers drawing wages in Utopia. I am inclined to imagine farming done by tenant associations, by little democratic unlimited liability companies working under elected managers, and paying not a fixed rent but a share of the produce to the State. Such companies could reconstruct annually to weed out indolent members. [Footnote: Schemes for the co-operative association of producers will be found in Dr. Hertzka's Freeland.] A minimum standard of efficiency in farming would be insured by fixing a minimum beneath which the rent must not fall, and perhaps by inspection. The general laws respecting the standard of life would, of course, apply to such associations. This type of co-operation presents itself to me as socially the best arrangement for productive agriculture and horticulture, but such enterprises as stock breeding, seed farming and the stocking and loan of agricultural implements are probably, and agricultural research and experiment certainly, best handled directly by large companies or the municipality or the State.

The solitary house is likely to be quite rare in Utopia. The same forces and improved communication that will spread towns will also lead to small clusters of agricultural workers in the countryside. Field workers will probably bring their meals to work during the day, and for the sake of an enjoyable dinner and social interaction after work, they will likely live in a college-style quadrangle with a common room and club. I doubt there will be any agricultural laborers on wages in Utopia. I imagine farming will be managed by tenant associations or small democratic companies with unlimited liability, led by elected managers, and paying a share of the produce to the State instead of a fixed rent. These companies could reorganize yearly to let go of underperforming members. [Footnote: Schemes for the cooperative association of producers can be found in Dr. Hertzka's Freeland.] A minimum standard of efficiency in farming would be ensured by setting a minimum rent that must be met, and possibly through inspections. The general laws regarding the standard of living would also apply to these associations. I think this type of cooperation is the best setup for productive agriculture and horticulture, but businesses like livestock breeding, seed farming, and the provision and lending of agricultural equipment are probably better handled by large companies, municipalities, or the State, particularly when it comes to agricultural research and experimentation.

But I should do little to investigate this question; these are presented as quite incidental impressions. You must suppose that for the most part our walks and observations keep us within the more urban quarters of Lucerne. From a number of beautifully printed placards at the street corners, adorned with caricatures of considerable pungency, we discover an odd little election is in progress. This is the selection, upon strictly democratic lines, with a suffrage that includes every permanent resident in the Lucerne ward over the age of fifteen, of the ugliest local building. The old little urban and local governing bodies, we find, have long since been superseded by great provincial municipalities for all the more serious administrative purposes, but they still survive to discharge a number of curious minor functions, and not the least among these is this sort of æsthetic ostracism. Every year every minor local governing body pulls down a building selected by local plebiscite, and the greater Government pays a slight compensation to the owner, and resumes possession of the land it occupies. The idea would strike us at first as simply whimsical, but in practice it appears to work as a cheap and practical device for the æsthetic education of builders, engineers, business men, opulent persons, and the general body of the public. But when we come to consider its application to our own world we should perceive it was the most Utopian thing we had so far encountered.

But I shouldn't spend too much time looking into this issue; these are just incidental observations. You should assume that most of our walks and observations keep us in the more urban areas of Lucerne. From a number of beautifully printed posters at the street corners, featuring quite sharp caricatures, we discover that a quirky little election is taking place. This is the selection, following strictly democratic principles, where every permanent resident in the Lucerne ward over the age of fifteen can vote for the ugliest local building. We find that the old local governing bodies have long been replaced by larger provincial municipalities for more serious administrative tasks, but they still exist to handle a few curious minor functions, one of which is this form of aesthetic ostracism. Each year, every small local governing body demolishes a building chosen by local vote, and the greater Government pays a small compensation to the owner and takes back the land it occupied. At first, this idea might seem whimsical, but in practice, it turns out to be an inexpensive and effective way to educate builders, engineers, businesspeople, wealthy individuals, and the general public about aesthetics. However, when we consider its application to our own world, we realize it's the most Utopian thing we've encountered so far.

§ 2

The factory that employs us is something very different from the ordinary earthly model. Our business is to finish making little wooden toys—bears, cattle men, and the like—for children. The things are made in the rough by machinery, and then finished by hand, because the work of unskilful but interested men—and it really is an extremely amusing employment—is found to give a personality and interest to these objects no machine can ever attain.

The factory where we work is nothing like the typical ones you see. We make small wooden toys—bears, cowboys, and things like that—for kids. The machines do the rough work, and then we finish them by hand. This way, even though we’re not experts, our interest makes these toys unique and adds a character that machines can’t replicate. It’s actually a really enjoyable job.

We carvers—who are the riffraff of Utopia—work in a long shed together, nominally by time; we must keep at the job for the length of the spell, but we are expected to finish a certain number of toys for each spell of work. The rules of the game as between employer and employed in this particular industry hang on the wall behind us; they are drawn up by a conference of the Common Council of Wages Workers with the employers, a common council which has resulted in Utopia from a synthesis of the old Trades Unions, and which has become a constitutional power; but any man who has skill or humour is presently making his own bargain with our employer more or less above that datum line.

We carvers—who are the outcasts of Utopia—work together in a long shed, mainly by time; we have to stick to the job for the duration of the shift, but we're expected to finish a certain number of toys for each work period. The rules governing the relationship between employers and employees in this particular industry are posted on the wall behind us; they are established by a meeting of the Common Council of Wage Workers along with the employers, a council that emerged in Utopia from a mix of the old Trade Unions and has become a recognized authority; however, anyone who has skill or wit is quickly striking his own deal with our employer, generally above that baseline.

Our employer is a quiet blue-eyed man with a humorous smile. He dresses wholly in an indigo blue, that later we come to consider a sort of voluntary uniform for Utopian artists. As he walks about the workshop, stopping to laugh at this production or praise that, one is reminded inevitably of an art school. Every now and then he carves a little himself or makes a sketch or departs to the machinery to order some change in the rough shapes it is turning out. Our work is by no means confined to animals. After a time I am told to specialise in a comical little Roman-nosed pony; but several of the better paid carvers work up caricature images of eminent Utopians. Over these our employer is most disposed to meditate, and from them he darts off most frequently to improve the type.

Our boss is a quiet blue-eyed guy with a funny smile. He always wears indigo blue, which we later come to see as a kind of voluntary uniform for Utopian artists. As he walks around the workshop, stopping to laugh at one piece or compliment another, it definitely feels like an art school. Every now and then, he carves a bit himself, makes a sketch, or heads over to the machines to adjust the rough shapes they’re producing. Our work isn’t just limited to animals. After a while, I'm told to focus on a funny little Roman-nosed pony, but several of the better-paid carvers create caricatures of famous Utopians. Our boss tends to ponder over these, and he frequently jumps off to refine the designs.

It is high summer, and our shed lies open at either end. On one hand is a steep mountain side down which there comes, now bridging a chasm, now a mere straight groove across a meadow, now hidden among green branches, the water-slide that brings our trees from the purple forest overhead. Above us, but nearly hidden, hums the machine shed, but we see a corner of the tank into which, with a mighty splash, the pine trees are delivered. Every now and then, bringing with him a gust of resinous smell, a white-clad machinist will come in with a basketful of crude, unwrought little images, and will turn them out upon the table from which we carvers select them.

It’s high summer, and our shed stands open at both ends. On one side, there’s a steep mountainside where water flows down, sometimes creating a bridge over a chasm, other times gliding straight across a meadow, and sometimes getting lost among green branches. This water slide brings our trees from the purple forest above. Almost hidden from view, the machine shed hums above us, but we can see a corner of the tank where the pine trees are dumped in with a big splash. Every so often, a white-clad machinist enters with a basket full of raw, unrefined little figures, and he dumps them on the table from which we carvers choose.

(Whenever I think of Utopia that faint and fluctuating smell of resin returns to me, and whenever I smell resin, comes the memory of the open end of the shed looking out upon the lake, the blue-green lake, the boats mirrored in the water, and far and high beyond floats the atmospheric fairyland of the mountains of Glarus, twenty miles away.)

(Whenever I think of Utopia, that faint and shifting smell of resin comes back to me, and every time I smell resin, I remember the open end of the shed overlooking the lake, the blue-green lake, the boats reflected in the water, and far above floats the dreamy landscape of the Glarus mountains, twenty miles away.)

The cessation of the second and last spell of work comes about midday, and then we walk home, through this beautiful intricacy of a town to our cheap hotel beside the lake.

The end of the second and final shift of work happens around noon, and then we walk home through this beautiful maze of a town to our budget hotel by the lake.

We should go our way with a curious contentment, for all that we were earning scarcely more than the minimum wage. We should have, of course, our uneasiness about the final decisions of that universal eye which has turned upon us, we should have those ridiculous sham numbers on our consciences; but that general restlessness, that brooding stress that pursues the weekly worker on earth, that aching anxiety that drives him so often to stupid betting, stupid drinking, and violent and mean offences will have vanished out of mortal experience.

We should move forward with a curious sense of contentment, even though we were earning barely more than minimum wage. Of course, we should feel some uneasiness about the ultimate decisions made by that universal force watching us; we should carry those absurd numbers in our minds. But that overall restlessness, that nagging stress that weighs on the weekly worker, that constant anxiety that often leads people to reckless gambling, excessive drinking, and petty crimes will be gone from human experience.

§ 3

I should find myself contrasting my position with my preconceptions about a Utopian visit. I had always imagined myself as standing outside the general machinery of the State—in the distinguished visitors' gallery, as it were—and getting the new world in a series of comprehensive perspective views. But this Utopia, for all the sweeping floats of generalisation I do my best to maintain, is swallowing me up. I find myself going between my work and the room in which I sleep and the place in which I dine, very much as I went to and fro in that real world into which I fell five-and-forty years ago. I find about me mountains and horizons that limit my view, institutions that vanish also without an explanation, beyond the limit of sight, and a great complexity of things I do not understand and about which, to tell the truth, I do not formulate acute curiosities. People, very unrepresentative people, people just as casual as people in the real world, come into personal relations with us, and little threads of private and immediate interest spin themselves rapidly into a thickening grey veil across the general view. I lose the comprehensive interrogation of my first arrival; I find myself interested in the grain of the wood I work, in birds among the tree branches, in little irrelevant things, and it is only now and then that I get fairly back to the mood that takes all Utopia for its picture.

I find myself comparing my current situation with my preconceived notions about visiting a Utopia. I always pictured myself standing outside the main workings of the State—like in a special visitors' gallery—observing the new world from a wide-angle perspective. But this Utopia, despite my efforts to maintain an overarching view, is engulfing me. I’m moving between my work, the room where I sleep, and the place where I eat, much like I did in that real world I entered 45 years ago. I encounter mountains and horizons that restrict my vision, institutions that disappear without explanation beyond my sight, and a complex array of things I don’t understand, and to be honest, I don’t feel a strong curiosity about them. People, very unrepresentative people, just as casual as folks in the real world, engage with us personally, and small threads of private, immediate interest quickly weave together into a dense grey veil over the bigger picture. I lose the broader inquiry I had when I first arrived; I find myself noticing the grain of the wood I work with, birds in the tree branches, and other little irrelevant details. Only occasionally do I return to the mindset that encompasses the entirety of Utopia.

We spend our first surplus of Utopian money in the reorganisation of our wardrobes upon more Utopian lines; we develop acquaintance with several of our fellow workers, and of those who share our table at the inn. We pass insensibly into acquaintanceships and the beginnings of friendships. The World Utopia, I say, seems for a time to be swallowing me up. At the thought of detail it looms too big for me. The question of government, of its sustaining ideas, of race, and the wider future, hang like the arch of the sky over these daily incidents, very great indeed, but very remote. These people about me are everyday people, people not so very far from the minimum wage, accustomed much as the everyday people of earth are accustomed to take their world as they find it. Such enquiries as I attempt are pretty obviously a bore to them, pass outside their range as completely as Utopian speculation on earth outranges a stevedore or a member of Parliament or a working plumber. Even the little things of daily life interest them in a different way. So I get on with my facts and reasoning rather slowly. I find myself looking among the pleasant multitudes of the streets for types that promise congenial conversation.

We spend our first surplus of Utopian money reorganizing our wardrobes along more Utopian lines; we get to know several of our coworkers and those who share our table at the inn. We gradually move from being acquaintances to forming the beginnings of friendships. The World of Utopia, I feel, seems to be consuming me for a while. When I think of the details, it feels overwhelming. Issues like government, its foundational ideas, race, and the broader future hang over these daily moments, very significant but also very distant. The people around me are everyday folks, not far from the minimum wage, just like the everyday people on Earth who accept their world as it is. My attempts at deeper questions seem to bore them; they fall outside their realm of concern, just like Utopian theories are beyond the thinking of a stevedore, a member of Parliament, or a working plumber on Earth. Even the small aspects of daily life engage them differently. So, I continue with my facts and reasoning at a slow pace. I find myself scanning the lively crowds in the streets for people who seem open to interesting conversations.

My sense of loneliness is increased during this interlude by the better social success of the botanist. I find him presently falling into conversation with two women who are accustomed to sit at a table near our own. They wear the loose, coloured robes of soft material that are the usual wear of common adult Utopian women; they are both dark and sallow, and they affect amber and crimson in their garments. Their faces strike me as a little unintelligent, and there is a faint touch of middle-aged coquetry in their bearing that I do not like. Yet on earth we should consider them women of exceptional refinement. But the botanist evidently sees in this direction scope for the feelings that have wilted a little under my inattention, and he begins that petty intercourse of a word, of a slight civility, of vague enquiries and comparisons that leads at last to associations and confidences. Such superficial confidences, that is to say, as he finds satisfactory.

My feeling of loneliness grows during this break because the botanist is doing much better socially. I see him striking up a conversation with two women who usually sit at a table near ours. They’re wearing loose, colorful robes made of soft fabric, which is typical for regular adult Utopian women. Both are dark-skinned and pale, and they tend to wear amber and crimson. Their faces seem a bit dull, and there's a slight hint of middle-aged flirtation in how they carry themselves, which I find unappealing. Yet, on Earth, we would consider them to be women of notable refinement. But the botanist clearly sees potential here for feelings that have been a bit starved due to my lack of attention, and he starts that trivial exchange of words, slight politeness, vague inquiries, and comparisons that eventually leads to deeper connections and shared moments. Such shallow connections, of course, as he finds satisfying.

This throws me back upon my private observations.

This brings me back to my personal observations.

The general effect of a Utopian population is vigour. Everyone one meets seems to be not only in good health but in training; one rarely meets fat people, bald people, or bent or grey. People who would be obese or bent and obviously aged on earth are here in good repair, and as a consequence the whole effect of a crowd is livelier and more invigorating than on earth. The dress is varied and graceful; that of the women reminds one most of the Italian fifteenth century; they have an abundance of soft and beautifully-coloured stuffs, and the clothes, even of the poorest, fit admirably. Their hair is very simply but very carefully and beautifully dressed, and except in very sunny weather they do not wear hats or bonnets. There is little difference in deportment between one class and another; they all are graceful and bear themselves with quiet dignity, and among a group of them a European woman of fashion in her lace and feathers, her hat and metal ornaments, her mixed accumulations of “trimmings,” would look like a barbarian tricked out with the miscellaneous plunder of a museum. Boys and girls wear much the same sort of costume—brown leather shoes, then a sort of combination of hose and close-fitting trousers that reaches from toe to waist, and over this a beltless jacket fitting very well, or a belted tunic. Many slender women wear the same sort of costume. We should see them in it very often in such a place as Lucerne, as they returned from expeditions in the mountains. The older men would wear long robes very frequently, but the greater proportion of the men would go in variations of much the same costume as the children. There would certainly be hooded cloaks and umbrellas for rainy weather, high boots for mud and snow, and cloaks and coats and furry robes for the winter. There would be no doubt a freer use of colour than terrestrial Europe sees in these days, but the costume of the women at least would be soberer and more practical, and (in harmony with our discussion in the previous chapter) less differentiated from the men's.

The overall vibe of a Utopian population is full of energy. Everyone you encounter seems not only healthy but also well-prepared; it’s rare to see overweight people, bald heads, or someone who looks bent or gray. Those who would be overweight or obviously aged on earth are here in great shape, making the crowd feel much livelier and more invigorating than on earth. The clothing is diverse and elegant; the women’s outfits most resemble those from 15th-century Italy. They have plenty of soft and beautifully colored fabrics, and even the poorest among them wear clothes that fit perfectly. Their hair is styled simply yet carefully and beautifully, and except in very sunny weather, they don’t wear hats or bonnets. There’s little distinction in behavior between classes; everyone is graceful and carries themselves with quiet dignity, making a European woman of fashion in her lace and feathers, extravagant hat, and metal ornaments look like a barbarian decked out in a hodgepodge of museum relics. Boys and girls wear a similar style—brown leather shoes and a combination of leggings and close-fitting trousers that go from toe to waist, with either a well-fitted jacket without a belt or a belted tunic. Many slender women wear the same outfit. We’d frequently see them in such attire in places like Lucerne after returning from mountain excursions. Older men often wear long robes, but most of the men would sport variations of the same outfits as the children. There would definitely be hooded cloaks and umbrellas for rainy days, high boots for mud and snow, and warm coats and furry robes for winter. There would likely be a more vibrant use of color than what we see in today’s Europe, but the women’s clothing would still be more subdued and practical, and (in line with our earlier discussion) less distinct from the men’s.

But these, of course, are generalisations. These are the mere translation of the social facts we have hypotheticated into the language of costume. There will be a great variety of costume and no compulsions. The doubles of people who are naturally foppish on earth will be foppish in Utopia, and people who have no natural taste on earth will have inartistic equivalents. Everyone will not be quiet in tone, or harmonious, or beautiful. Occasionally, as I go through the streets to my work, I shall turn round to glance again at some robe shot with gold embroidery, some slashing of the sleeves, some eccentricity of cut, or some discord or untidiness. But these will be but transient flashes in a general flow of harmonious graciousness; dress will have scarcely any of that effect of disorderly conflict, of self-assertion qualified by the fear of ridicule, that it has in the crudely competitive civilisations of earth.

But these are just generalizations. They’re simply converting the social facts we've speculated into the language of clothing. There will be a wide variety of attire and no pressures to conform. The people who are naturally flashy on earth will be flashy in Utopia, and those with no sense of style on earth will have their own unartistic versions. Not everyone will have a calm tone, be harmonious, or look beautiful. Sometimes, as I walk to work, I'll turn around to take another look at some garment adorned with gold embroidery, some eye-catching sleeves, some unique cut, or some clash or untidiness. But these will just be brief moments in a general stream of harmonious grace; clothing will hardly have that sense of chaotic conflict, that self-assertion tempered by the fear of mockery, that it has in the harshly competitive societies on earth.

I shall have the seeker's attitude of mind during those few days at Lucerne. I shall become a student of faces. I shall be, as it were, looking for someone. I shall see heavy faces, dull faces, faces with an uncongenial animation, alien faces, and among these some with an immediate quality of appeal. I should see desirable men approaching me, and I should think; “Now, if I were to speak to you?” Many of these latter I should note wore the same clothing as the man who spoke to us at Wassen; I should begin to think of it as a sort of uniform....

I’ll have the mindset of a seeker during those few days in Lucerne. I’ll turn into a student of faces. It’ll be like I’m looking for someone. I’ll encounter heavy faces, dull faces, faces that seem out of place, unfamiliar faces, and among these, some that really stand out. I’ll see attractive men coming toward me, and I’ll think, “What if I were to talk to you?” Many of these guys will be wearing the same outfits as the man who spoke to us at Wassen; I’ll start to see it as a kind of uniform...

Then I should see grave-faced girls, girls of that budding age when their bearing becomes delusively wise, and the old deception of my youth will recur to me; “Could you and I but talk together?” I should think. Women will pass me lightly, women with open and inviting faces, but they will not attract me, and there will come beautiful women, women with that touch of claustral preoccupation which forbids the thought of any near approach. They are private and secret, and I may not enter, I know, into their thoughts....

Then I would see serious-faced girls, girls at that age when they seem surprisingly wise, and the old trick of my youth would come back to me; “If only you and I could just talk?” I would think. Women would pass by me effortlessly, women with friendly and inviting faces, but they wouldn’t draw me in, and there would be beautiful women, women with an air of distant preoccupation that doesn’t allow for any closeness. They are private and mysterious, and I know I can’t enter into their thoughts...

I go as often as I can to the seat by the end of old Kapelbrucke, and watch the people passing over.

I go as often as I can to the spot at the end of the old Kapelbrucke and watch the people walk by.

I shall find a quality of dissatisfaction throughout all these days. I shall come to see this period more and more distinctly as a pause, as a waiting interlude, and the idea of an encounter with my double, which came at first as if it were a witticism, as something verbal and surprising, begins to take substance. The idea grows in my mind that after all this is the “someone” I am seeking, this Utopian self of mine. I had at first an idea of a grotesque encounter, as of something happening in a looking glass, but presently it dawns on me that my Utopian self must be a very different person from me. His training will be different, his mental content different. But between us there will be a strange link of essential identity, a sympathy, an understanding. I find the thing rising suddenly to a preponderance in my mind. I find the interest of details dwindling to the vanishing point. That I have come to Utopia is the lesser thing now; the greater is that I have come to meet myself.

I'll feel a sense of dissatisfaction throughout all these days. I'll start to see this period more clearly as a pause, a waiting period, and the idea of an encounter with my double, which initially seemed like a joke, something surprising and verbal, starts to become real. The thought grows in my mind that this might actually be the “someone” I’ve been searching for—this Utopian version of myself. At first, I imagined a grotesque encounter, like something happening in a mirror, but it soon hits me that my Utopian self must be a very different person from who I am. His experiences will be different, his thoughts different. But there will be a strange connection of essential identity between us, a mutual understanding, a sympathy. I find this idea suddenly dominating my mind. The importance of the details starts to fade away. It matters less now that I've arrived in Utopia; what really matters is that I've come to meet myself.

I spend hours trying to imagine the encounter, inventing little dialogues. I go alone to the Bureau to find if any news has come to hand from the Great Index in Paris, but I am told to wait another twenty-four hours. I cease absolutely to be interested in anything else, except so far as it leads towards intercourse with this being who is to be at once so strangely alien and so totally mine.

I spend hours trying to picture the meeting, creating little conversations in my head. I go alone to the office to see if there’s any news from the Great Index in Paris, but I’m told to wait another twenty-four hours. I completely lose interest in anything else, except as it relates to connecting with this person who is going to be both incredibly foreign and entirely mine.

§ 4

Wrapped up in these preoccupations as I am, it will certainly be the botanist who will notice the comparative absence of animals about us.

Wrapped up in these concerns as I am, it will definitely be the botanist who will notice the relative lack of animals around us.

He will put it in the form of a temperate objection to the Utopian planet.

He will express it as a reasonable objection to the Utopian planet.

He is a professed lover of dogs and there are none. We have seen no horses and only one or two mules on the day of our arrival, and there seems not a cat in the world. I bring my mind round to his suggestion. “This follows,” I say.

He claims to be a dog lover, but there are none around. We haven't seen any horses and only one or two mules since we arrived, and it seems like there isn't a single cat in sight. I start to agree with his suggestion. “This makes sense,” I say.

It is only reluctantly that I allow myself to be drawn from my secret musings into a discussion of Utopian pets.

I only reluctantly let myself be pulled away from my private thoughts to talk about Utopian pets.

I try to explain that a phase in the world's development is inevitable when a systematic world-wide attempt will be made to destroy for ever a great number of contagious and infectious diseases, and that this will involve, for a time at any rate, a stringent suppression of the free movement of familiar animals. Utopian houses, streets and drains will be planned and built to make rats, mice, and such-like house parasites impossible; the race of cats and dogs—providing, as it does, living fastnesses to which such diseases as plague, influenza, catarrhs and the like, can retreat to sally forth again—must pass for a time out of freedom, and the filth made by horses and the other brutes of the highway vanish from the face of the earth. These things make an old story to me, and perhaps explicitness suffers through my brevity.

I try to explain that a phase in the world's development is unavoidable when there will be a global effort to eliminate a large number of contagious and infectious diseases for good. This will require, at least for a while, strict restrictions on the movement of common animals. Ideal homes, streets, and drainage systems will be designed and constructed to ensure that rats, mice, and other household pests cannot thrive. The populations of cats and dogs, which provide hiding places for diseases like plague, influenza, and colds to retreat and reemerge from, must temporarily lose their freedom, and the waste created by horses and other street animals must disappear from our world. These matters feel like old news to me, and maybe my brevity leads to a lack of clarity.

My botanist fails altogether to grasp what the disappearance of diseases means. His mind has no imaginative organ of that compass. As I talk his mind rests on one fixed image. This presents what the botanist would probably call a “dear old doggie”—which the botanist would make believe did not possess any sensible odour—and it has faithful brown eyes and understands everything you say. The botanist would make believe it understood him mystically, and I figure his long white hand—which seems to me, in my more jaundiced moments, to exist entirely for picking things and holding a lens—patting its head, while the brute looked things unspeakable....

My botanist completely fails to understand what the disappearance of diseases means. His mind doesn’t have the capacity to imagine something that vast. While I talk, his mind stays stuck on one fixed image. This image is what the botanist would probably call a “dear old doggie”—which he pretends doesn’t have any noticeable smell—and it has loyal brown eyes and seems to understand everything you say. The botanist pretends this dog understands him in a mystical way, and I imagine his long white hand—which, in my more cynical moments, seems to exist solely for picking things and holding a lens—gently patting its head, while the creature looks at things beyond words....

The botanist shakes his head after my explanation and says quietly, “I do not like your Utopia, if there are to be no dogs.”

The botanist shakes his head after my explanation and says quietly, “I don’t like your Utopia if there are no dogs.”

Perhaps that makes me a little malicious. Indeed I do not hate dogs, but I care ten thousand times more for a man than for all the brutes on the earth, and I can see, what the botanist I think cannot, that a life spent in the delightful atmosphere of many pet animals may have too dear a price....

Perhaps that makes me a bit mean. I don't actually hate dogs, but I care way more about people than I do about all the animals out there. I can see something that, I think, the botanist can’t: that a life filled with the joy of having many pets might come with a cost that's just too high....

I find myself back again at the comparison of the botanist and myself. There is a profound difference in our imaginations, and I wonder whether it is the consequence of innate character or of training and whether he is really the human type or I. I am not altogether without imagination, but what imagination I have has the most insistent disposition to square itself with every fact in the universe. It hypothesises very boldly, but on the other hand it will not gravely make believe. Now the botanist's imagination is always busy with the most impossible make-believe. That is the way with all children I know. But it seems to me one ought to pass out of it. It isn't as though the world was an untidy nursery; it is a place of splendours indescribable for all who will lift its veils. It may be he is essentially different from me, but I am much more inclined to think he is simply more childish. Always it is make-believe. He believes that horses are beautiful creatures for example, dogs are beautiful creatures, that some women are inexpressibly lovely, and he makes believe that this is always so. Never a word of criticism of horse or dog or woman! Never a word of criticism of his impeccable friends! Then there is his botany. He makes believe that all the vegetable kingdom is mystically perfect and exemplary, that all flowers smell deliciously and are exquisitely beautiful, that Drosera does not hurt flies very much, and that onions do not smell. Most of the universe does not interest this nature lover at all. But I know, and I am querulously incapable of understanding why everyone else does not know, that a horse is beautiful in one way and quite ugly in another, that everything has this shot-silk quality, and is all the finer for that. When people talk of a horse as an ugly animal I think of its beautiful moments, but when I hear a flow of indiscriminate praise of its beauty I think of such an aspect as one gets for example from a dog-cart, the fiddle-shaped back, and that distressing blade of the neck, the narrow clumsy place between the ears, and the ugly glimpse of cheek. There is, indeed, no beauty whatever save that transitory thing that comes and comes again; all beauty is really the beauty of expression, is really kinetic and momentary. That is true even of those triumphs of static endeavour achieved by Greece. The Greek temple, for example, is a barn with a face that at a certain angle of vision and in a certain light has a great calm beauty.

I'm finding myself comparing the botanist and me again. There’s a big difference in our imaginations, and I can't help but wonder if it’s due to our natural traits or our upbringing, and whether he really represents the human type or I do. I'm not entirely without imagination, but mine tends to align closely with every fact in the universe. It hypothesizes very boldly, but on the other hand, it doesn't indulge in serious make-believe. The botanist's imagination, however, is always caught up in the most outlandish fantasies. That’s how all children I know are. But it seems to me that we should grow out of that. The world isn’t just a messy nursery; it’s a place of indescribable wonders for anyone willing to uncover them. Maybe he’s fundamentally different from me, but I’m more convinced he’s just more childish. It’s always about make-believe. He believes that horses are beautiful animals, for instance, that dogs are beautiful creatures, that some women are unbelievably lovely, and he pretends that this is always true. Never a word of criticism about horses, dogs, or women! Not a single critical thought about his flawless friends! Then there’s his botany. He pretends that the entire plant kingdom is mystically perfect and admirable, that all flowers smell wonderful and are incredibly beautiful, that Drosera doesn’t hurt flies much, and that onions don’t have a smell. Most of the universe doesn’t interest this nature lover at all. But I know, and I frustratingly can’t understand why others don’t see it, that a horse is beautiful in one way and pretty ugly in another, that everything has this dual quality, which makes it more interesting. When people call a horse ugly, I think of its beautiful moments, but when I hear people gushing about its beauty, I consider the not-so-appealing angles, like the awkwardly shaped back and the strange neck, the narrow, clumsy spot between the ears, and the unattractive cheek. In truth, there’s no lasting beauty except for those fleeting moments that keep coming back; all beauty is really about expression, it’s dynamic and momentary. This applies even to those great examples of static beauty from Greece. The Greek temple, for example, can seem like a barn, but at a certain angle and in the right light, it has an incredible, serene beauty.

But where are we drifting? All such things, I hold, are cases of more and less, and of the right moment and the right aspect, even the things I most esteem. There is no perfection, there is no enduring treasure. This pet dog's beautiful affection, I say, or this other sensuous or imaginative delight, is no doubt good, but it can be put aside if it is incompatible with some other and wider good. You cannot focus all good things together.

But where are we headed? I believe that everything comes down to degrees, and the right timing and perspective, even the things I value most. There’s no such thing as perfection, and no lasting treasure. This beloved pet's wonderful affection, for example, or other sensory or creative pleasures, are certainly good, but they can be set aside if they clash with some greater good. You can’t have all good things at once.

All right action and all wise action is surely sound judgment and courageous abandonment in the matter of such incompatibilities. If I cannot imagine thoughts and feelings in a dog's brain that cannot possibly be there, at least I can imagine things in the future of men that might be there had we the will to demand them....

All right action and all wise action is definitely sound judgment and brave letting go in the face of such differences. If I can't picture thoughts and feelings in a dog's mind that can't possibly exist, at least I can envision possibilities in the future of humans that could be there if we had the will to seek them out...

“I don't like this Utopia,” the botanist repeats. “You don't understand about dogs. To me they're human beings—and more! There used to be such a jolly old dog at my aunt's at Frognal when I was a boy―”

“I don't like this Utopia,” the botanist repeats. “You don't understand about dogs. To me, they're human beings—and even more! There used to be such a cheerful old dog at my aunt's in Frognal when I was a kid—”

But I do not heed his anecdote. Something—something of the nature of conscience—has suddenly jerked back the memory of that beer I drank at Hospenthal, and puts an accusing finger on the memory.

But I ignore his story. Something—like a sense of guilt—has suddenly pulled back the memory of that beer I had in Hospenthal and points an accusing finger at it.

I never have had a pet animal, I confess, though I have been fairly popular with kittens. But with regard to a certain petting of myself―?

I’ve never owned a pet, I admit, although I’ve gotten along pretty well with kittens. But when it comes to a certain kind of affection for myself—?

Perhaps I was premature about that beer. I have had no pet animals, but I perceive if the Modern Utopia is going to demand the sacrifice of the love of animals, which is, in its way, a very fine thing indeed, so much the more readily may it demand the sacrifice of many other indulgences, some of which are not even fine in the lowest degree.

Perhaps I was too hasty about that beer. I haven’t had any pets, but I can see that if the Modern Utopia is going to require giving up the love of animals, which is a truly valuable thing, then it can just as easily ask for the sacrifice of many other pleasures, some of which aren’t even worthwhile at all.

It is curious this haunting insistence upon sacrifice and discipline!

It’s interesting how this constant focus on sacrifice and discipline persists!

It is slowly becoming my dominant thought that the sort of people whose will this Utopia embodies must be people a little heedless of small pleasures. You cannot focus all good things at the same time. That is my chief discovery in these meditations at Lucerne. Much of the rest of this Utopia I had in a sort of way anticipated, but not this. I wonder if I shall see my Utopian self for long and be able to talk to him freely....

It’s gradually becoming my main thought that the kind of people who embody this Utopia must be somewhat careless about minor pleasures. You can’t concentrate on all good things at once. That’s my biggest insight from these reflections in Lucerne. I had somewhat expected much of the other aspects of this Utopia, but not this one. I wonder if I’ll be able to see my Utopian self for a long time and talk to him openly...

We lie in the petal-strewn grass under some Judas trees beside the lake shore, as I meander among these thoughts, and each of us, disregardful of his companion, follows his own associations.

We’re lying in the grass covered with petals under some Judas trees by the lake, and as I drift through my thoughts, each of us, ignoring the other, follows our own trains of thought.

“Very remarkable,” I say, discovering that the botanist has come to an end with his story of that Frognal dog.

“Very interesting,” I say, realizing that the botanist has finished his story about that Frognal dog.

“You'd wonder how he knew,” he says.

“You would wonder how he knew,” he says.

“You would.”

"You would."

I nibble a green blade.

I nibble on a green blade.

“Do you realise quite,” I ask, “that within a week we shall face our Utopian selves and measure something of what we might have been?”

“Do you realize,” I ask, “that in a week we’ll confront our ideal selves and assess what we could have become?”

The botanist's face clouds. He rolls over, sits up abruptly and puts his lean hands about his knees.

The botanist's expression darkens. He turns over, sits up suddenly, and puts his slim hands around his knees.

“I don't like to think about it,” he says. “What is the good of reckoning ... might have beens?”

“I don't like to think about it,” he says. “What’s the point of worrying about ... what could have been?”

§ 5

It is pleasant to think of one's puzzling the organised wisdom of so superior a planet as this Utopia, this moral monster State my Frankenstein of reasoning has made, and to that pitch we have come. When we are next in the presence of our Lucerne official, he has the bearing of a man who faces a mystification beyond his powers, an incredible disarrangement of the order of Nature. Here, for the first time in the records of Utopian science, are two cases—not simply one but two, and these in each other's company!—of duplicated thumb-marks. This, coupled with a cock-and-bull story of an instantaneous transfer from some planet unknown to Utopian astronomy. That he and all his world exists only upon a hypothesis that would explain everyone of these difficulties absolutely, is scarcely likely to occur to his obviously unphilosophic mind.

It's nice to think about how I’m challenging the organized knowledge of such a superior planet as this Utopia, this moral monstrosity my Frankenstein of reasoning has created, and how far we’ve come. When we next encounter our Lucerne official, he gives off the vibe of someone confronting a mystery beyond his understanding, an unbelievable disruption of the natural order. Here, for the first time in Utopian scientific records, we have two cases—not just one but two, and they’re together!—of duplicated thumbprints. This, combined with a far-fetched story of an instant transport from some unknown planet in Utopian astronomy. The idea that he and his entire world exist solely on a hypothesis that could easily explain all these issues probably doesn’t even cross his obviously unphilosophical mind.

The official eye is more eloquent than the official lips and asks almost urgently, “What in this immeasurable universe have you managed to do to your thumbs? And why?” But he is only a very inferior sort of official indeed, a mere clerk of the post, and he has all the guarded reserve of your thoroughly unoriginal man. “You are not the two persons I ascertained you were,” he says, with the note of one resigned to communion with unreason; “because you”—he indicates me—“are evidently at your residence in London.” I smile. “That gentleman”—he points a pen at the botanist in a manner that is intended to dismiss my smile once for all—“will be in London next week. He will be returning next Friday from a special mission to investigate the fungoid parasites that have been attacking the cinchona trees in Ceylon.”

The official gaze speaks volumes more than his words, almost urgently asking, “What have you done to your thumbs in this vast universe? And why?” But he’s really just a low-level official, a mere postal clerk, and he has all the restrained demeanor of someone who lacks originality. “You’re not the two people I thought you were,” he says, sounding like someone who has accepted the absurdity of the situation; “because you”—he points at me—“are clearly at your home in London.” I smile. “That gentleman”—he jabs a pen at the botanist in a way that seems to try to erase my smile completely—“will be in London next week. He’ll be back next Friday from a special mission to study the fungal parasites that have been attacking the cinchona trees in Ceylon.”

The botanist blesses his heart.

The botanist has a kind heart.

“Consequently”—the official sighs at the burthen of such nonsense, “you will have to go and consult with—the people you ought to be.”

“Therefore”—the official sighs at the burden of such nonsense, “you will need to go and talk to—the people you should be.”

I betray a faint amusement.

I show a faint amusement.

“You will have to end by believing in our planet,” I say.

“You will have to finish by believing in our planet,” I say.

He waggles a negation with his head. He would intimate his position is too responsible a one for jesting, and both of us in our several ways enjoy the pleasure we poor humans have in meeting with intellectual inferiority. “The Standing Committee of Identification,” he says, with an eye on a memorandum, “has remitted your case to the Research Professor of Anthropology in the University of London, and they want you to go there, if you will, and talk to him.”

He shakes his head in disagreement. He suggests that his role is too serious for joking around, and we both, in our own ways, take comfort in the enjoyment we humans find in encountering lesser intelligence. “The Standing Committee of Identification,” he says, glancing at a memo, “has referred your case to the Research Professor of Anthropology at the University of London, and they’d like you to go there, if you’re willing, and speak with him.”

“What else can we do?” says the botanist.

“What else can we do?” says the botanist.

“There's no positive compulsion,” he remarks, “but your work here will probably cease. Here―” he pushed the neat slips of paper towards us—“are your tickets for London, and a small but sufficient supply of money,”—he indicates two piles of coins and paper on either hand of him—“for a day or so there.” He proceeds in the same dry manner to inform us we are invited to call at our earliest convenience upon our doubles, and upon the Professor, who is to investigate our case.

“There's no real pressure,” he says, “but your work here will likely come to an end. Here—” he slid the neat slips of paper towards us—“are your tickets to London, along with a small but adequate amount of money,”—he points to two piles of coins and bills beside him—“to last for a day or so there.” He continues in the same dull tone to let us know we are welcome to visit our doubles and the Professor, who will be looking into our situation, at our earliest convenience.

“And then?”

"So, what happens next?"

He pulls down the corners of his mouth in a wry deprecatory smile, eyes us obliquely under a crumpled brow, shrugs his shoulders, and shows us the palms of his hands.

He pulls the corners of his mouth into a sarcastic, self-deprecating smile, glances at us sideways beneath a wrinkled brow, shrugs his shoulders, and displays the palms of his hands.

On earth, where there is nationality, this would have been a Frenchman—the inferior sort of Frenchman—the sort whose only happiness is in the routine security of Government employment.

On earth, where there are nationalities, this would have been a Frenchman—the lesser kind of Frenchman—the type whose only happiness comes from the predictable safety of a government job.

§ 6

London will be the first Utopian city centre we shall see.

London will be the first ideal city center we will see.

We shall find ourselves there with not a little amazement. It will be our first experience of the swift long distance travel of Utopia, and I have an idea—I know not why—that we should make the journey by night. Perhaps I think so because the ideal of long-distance travel is surely a restful translation less suitable for the active hours.

We’ll find ourselves there with quite a bit of amazement. It will be our first experience of the fast long-distance travel of Utopia, and I have a feeling—I’m not sure why—that we should make the trip at night. Maybe I think this because the idea of long-distance travel is definitely a more relaxing activity that’s less fitting for the daytime.

We shall dine and gossip and drink coffee at the pretty little tables under the lantern-lit trees, we shall visit the theatre, and decide to sup in the train, and so come at last to the station. There we shall find pleasant rooms with seats and books—luggage all neatly elsewhere—and doors that we shall imagine give upon a platform. Our cloaks and hats and such-like outdoor impedimenta will be taken in the hall and neatly labelled for London, we shall exchange our shoes for slippers there, and we shall sit down like men in a club. An officious little bell will presently call our attention to a label “London” on the doorway, and an excellent phonograph will enforce that notice with infinite civility. The doors will open, and we shall walk through into an equally comfortable gallery.

We'll have dinner, chat, and drink coffee at the cute little tables under the lantern-lit trees. We'll go to the theater and decide to grab a late-night meal on the train, eventually arriving at the station. There, we'll find cozy rooms with seats and books—our luggage neatly stored away elsewhere—and doors that we'll imagine lead to a platform. Our coats, hats, and other outdoor gear will be taken in the hall and properly tagged for London; we'll swap our shoes for slippers there and sit down like gentlemen in a club. A handy little bell will soon catch our attention with a sign reading "London" on the doorway, and an excellent phonograph will reinforce that notice with utmost politeness. The doors will open, and we'll walk through into an equally comfortable gallery.

“Where is the train for London?” we shall ask a uniformed fellow Utopian.

“Where is the train to London?” we will ask a uniformed guy.

“This is the train for London,” he will say.

“This is the train to London,” he will say.

There will be a shutting of doors, and the botanist and I, trying not to feel too childish, will walk exploring through the capacious train.

There will be a shutting of doors, and the botanist and I, trying not to feel too childish, will walk exploring through the spacious train.

The resemblance to a club will strike us both. “A good club,” the botanist will correct me.

The similarity to a club will catch us both off guard. “A good club,” the botanist will correct me.

When one travels beyond a certain speed, there is nothing but fatigue in looking out of a window, and this corridor train, twice the width of its poor terrestrial brother, will have no need of that distraction. The simple device of abandoning any but a few windows, and those set high, gives the wall space of the long corridors to books; the middle part of the train is indeed a comfortable library with abundant armchairs and couches, each with its green-shaded light, and soft carpets upon the soundproof floor. Further on will be a news-room, with a noiseless but busy tape at one corner, printing off messages from the wires by the wayside, and further still, rooms for gossip and smoking, a billiard room, and the dining car. Behind we shall come to bedrooms, bathrooms, the hairdresser, and so forth.

When you travel beyond a certain speed, looking out of a window just brings fatigue, and this corridor train, which is twice as wide as its poor counterpart on land, won’t need that distraction. By only having a few high-set windows, the long corridors can be used for books; the central part of the train is actually a cozy library with plenty of armchairs and couches, each with its own green-shaded light, and soft carpets on the soundproof floor. Further along, there will be a news room, featuring a quiet but active tape in one corner, printing out messages from the wires along the route, and beyond that, there are rooms for chatting and smoking, a billiard room, and the dining car. At the back, you'll find bedrooms, bathrooms, a hairdresser, and so on.

“When shall we start?” I ask presently, as we return, rather like bashful yokels, to the library, and the old gentleman reading the Arabian Nights in the armchair in the corner glances up at me with a sudden curiosity.

"When are we going to start?" I ask now, as we go back, a bit like shy country folks, to the library, and the old man reading the Arabian Nights in the armchair in the corner looks up at me with a sudden interest.

The botanist touches my arm and nods towards a pretty little lead-paned window, through which we see a village sleeping under cloudy moonlight go flashing by. Then a skylit lake, and then a string of swaying lights, gone with the leap of a camera shutter.

The botanist touches my arm and points to a charming lead-paned window, through which we see a village resting under the cloudy moonlight that quickly passes by. Then a skylit lake, followed by a series of swaying lights, all disappearing with the snap of a camera shutter.

Two hundred miles an hour!

200 miles per hour!

We resort to a dignified Chinese steward and secure our berths. It is perhaps terrestrial of us that we do not think of reading the Utopian literature that lines the middle part of the train. I find a bed of the simple Utopian pattern, and lie for a time thinking—quite tranquilly—of this marvellous adventure.

We turn to a respectable Chinese steward and get our seats. It’s probably a bit shortsighted of us that we don’t consider reading the Utopian literature displayed in the middle section of the train. I find a simple Utopian-style bed and lie down for a while, calmly reflecting on this incredible adventure.

I wonder why it is that to lie securely in bed, with the light out, seems ever the same place, wherever in space one may chance to be? And asleep, there is no space for us at all. I become drowsy and incoherent and metaphysical....

I wonder why lying comfortably in bed, with the lights off, feels like the same place no matter where you are? And when we're asleep, there’s no space at all for us. I get sleepy and scattered and philosophical....

The faint and fluctuating drone of the wheels below the car, re-echoed by the flying track, is more perceptible now, but it is not unpleasantly loud, merely a faint tinting of the quiet....

The soft and intermittent hum of the wheels beneath the car, echoed by the moving track, is more noticeable now, but it's not uncomfortably loud, just a subtle hint of noise in the silence....

No sea crossing breaks our journey; there is nothing to prevent a Channel tunnel in that other planet; and I wake in London.

No sea crossing interrupts our journey; nothing stops a Channel tunnel on that other planet; and I wake up in London.

The train has been in London some time when I awake, for these marvellous Utopians have discovered that it is not necessary to bundle out passengers from a train in the small hours, simply because they have arrived. A Utopian train is just a peculiar kind of hotel corridor that flies about the earth while one sleeps.

The train has been in London for a while when I wake up, because these amazing Utopians have figured out that it’s unnecessary to shove passengers off a train in the middle of the night just because they’ve arrived. A Utopian train is basically a unique kind of hotel hallway that moves around the world while you sleep.

§ 7

How will a great city of Utopia strike us?

How will an amazing city of Utopia impress us?

To answer that question well one must needs be artist and engineer, and I am neither. Moreover, one must employ words and phrases that do not exist, for this world still does not dream of the things that may be done with thought and steel, when the engineer is sufficiently educated to be an artist, and the artistic intelligence has been quickened to the accomplishment of an engineer. How can one write of these things for a generation which rather admires that inconvenient and gawky muddle of ironwork and Flemish architecture, the London Tower Bridge. When before this, temerarious anticipators have written of the mighty buildings that might someday be, the illustrator has blended with the poor ineffectual splutter of the author's words, his powerful suggestion that it amounted simply to something bulbous, florid and fluent in the vein of the onion, and L'Art Nouveau. But here, it may be, the illustrator will not intervene.

To answer that question properly, you have to be both an artist and an engineer, and I'm neither. Plus, you need to use words and concepts that don’t exist yet, because this world still doesn’t envision what can be achieved with creativity and technology, when engineers are educated enough to be artists and artistic minds are inspired to achieve engineering feats. How can you write about these ideas for a generation that admires the clunky and awkward combination of ironwork and Flemish architecture, like the London Tower Bridge? In the past, bold visionaries have written about the incredible buildings that could someday be built, but illustrators have mixed their powerful depictions with the author's weak attempts, suggesting simply that it would turn out to be something bulbous, overly ornate, and smooth like an onion, and L'Art Nouveau. But perhaps here, the illustrator won’t step in.

Art has scarcely begun in the world.

Art has just barely started in the world.

There have been a few forerunners and that is all. Leonardo, Michael Angelo; how they would have exulted in the liberties of steel! There are no more pathetic documents in the archives of art than Leonardo's memoranda. In these, one sees him again and again reaching out as it were, with empty desirous hands, towards the unborn possibilities of the engineer. And Dürer, too, was a Modern, with the same turn towards creative invention. In our times these men would have wanted to make viaducts, to bridge wild and inaccessible places, to cut and straddle great railways athwart the mountain masses of the world. You can see, time after time, in Dürer's work, as you can see in the imaginary architectural landscape of the Pompeian walls, the dream of structures, lighter and bolder than stone or brick can yield.... These Utopian town buildings will be the realisation of such dreams.

There have been a few pioneers, and that’s about it. Leonardo, Michelangelo; how they would have celebrated the freedoms of modern engineering! There are no more heartbreaking documents in the history of art than Leonardo's notes. In these, you see him constantly reaching out, as if with empty, eager hands, toward the unrealized possibilities of engineering. And Dürer was also a modern, with the same inclination for creative innovation. In today’s world, these men would have aimed to build viaducts, connecting wild and remote areas, and to create extensive railways across the rugged mountain ranges. You can observe, time and again, in Dürer’s work, just as in the imagined architectural landscapes of the Pompeian walls, the yearning for structures that are lighter and bolder than what stone or brick can provide.... These visionary town designs will be the realization of such dreams.

Here will be one of the great meeting places of mankind. Here—I speak of Utopian London—will be the traditional centre of one of the great races in the commonalty of the World State—and here will be its social and intellectual exchange. There will be a mighty University here, with thousands of professors and tens of thousands of advanced students, and here great journals of thought and speculation, mature and splendid books of philosophy and science, and a glorious fabric of literature will be woven and shaped, and with a teeming leisureliness, put forth. Here will be stupendous libraries, and a mighty organisation of museums. About these centres will cluster a great swarm of people, and close at hand will be another centre, for I who am an Englishman must needs stipulate that Westminster shall still be a seat of world Empire, one of several seats, if you will—where the ruling council of the world assembles. Then the arts will cluster round this city, as gold gathers about wisdom, and here Englishmen will weave into wonderful prose and beautiful rhythms and subtly atmospheric forms, the intricate, austere and courageous imagination of our race.

This will be one of the great gathering places for humanity. Here—I’m talking about Utopian London—will be the traditional center of one of the major cultures in the World State’s common society—and here will be where social and intellectual exchanges happen. There will be a huge university here, with thousands of professors and tens of thousands of advanced students, and here great journals of thought and speculation, sophisticated and impressive books of philosophy and science, along with a rich tapestry of literature will be created and published with abundant care. There will be massive libraries and an extensive network of museums. Around these centers will gather a large crowd of people, and not far away will be another center, for as an Englishman, I must insist that Westminster remains a seat of global power, one of several locations, if you prefer—where the world’s ruling council meets. The arts will flourish around this city, just as gold collects around wisdom, and here Englishmen will weave into stunning prose and beautiful rhythms, along with subtly atmospheric forms, the complex, austere, and bold imagination of our culture.

One will come into this place as one comes into a noble mansion. They will have flung great arches and domes of glass above the wider spaces of the town, the slender beauty of the perfect metal-work far overhead will be softened to a fairy-like unsubstantiality by the mild London air. It will be the London air we know, clear of filth and all impurity, the same air that gives our October days their unspeakable clarity and makes every London twilight mysteriously beautiful. We shall go along avenues of architecture that will be emancipated from the last memories of the squat temple boxes of the Greek, the buxom curvatures of Rome; the Goth in us will have taken to steel and countless new materials as kindly as once he took to stone. The gay and swiftly moving platforms of the public ways will go past on either hand, carrying sporadic groups of people, and very speedily we shall find ourselves in a sort of central space, rich with palms and flowering bushes and statuary. We shall look along an avenue of trees, down a wide gorge between the cliffs of crowded hotels, the hotels that are still glowing with internal lights, to where the shining morning river streams dawnlit out to sea.

One will enter this place like stepping into an impressive mansion. Great arches and glass domes will span the spacious areas of the city, and the delicate elegance of the flawless metalwork far above will be softened to a dreamlike lightness by the gentle London air. It will be the familiar London air we know, free of dirt and pollution, the same air that gives our October days their indescribable clarity and makes every London twilight mysteriously beautiful. We will stroll along avenues of architecture that have moved beyond the last remnants of the squat temple boxes of the Greeks and the curvy grandeur of Rome; our modern Goth spirit will have embraced steel and countless new materials just as readily as he once embraced stone. The vibrant and fast-moving platforms of the streets will pass by on either side, carrying scattered groups of people, and soon we will find ourselves in a central area filled with palms, flowering shrubs, and sculptures. We will look down an avenue of trees, through a wide gap between the towering hotels crowded around us, hotels still shining with interior lights, towards the sparkling morning river flowing out to sea.

Great multitudes of people will pass softly to and fro in this central space, beautiful girls and youths going to the University classes that are held in the stately palaces about us, grave and capable men and women going to their businesses, children meandering along to their schools, holiday makers, lovers, setting out upon a hundred quests; and here we shall ask for the two we more particularly seek. A graceful little telephone kiosk will put us within reach of them, and with a queer sense of unreality I shall find myself talking to my Utopian twin. He has heard of me, he wants to see me and he gives me clear directions how to come to him.

Huge crowds of people will move gently back and forth in this central space, attractive girls and young men heading to the university classes held in the grand buildings around us, serious and skilled men and women heading to their jobs, kids wandering off to their schools, vacationers, lovers, setting off on a hundred adventures; and here we will ask for the two people we’re especially looking for. A charming little phone booth will help us connect with them, and with a strange sense of unreality, I’ll find myself talking to my ideal counterpart. He has heard about me, he wants to meet me, and he gives me clear directions on how to get to him.

I wonder if my own voice sounds like that.

I wonder if my voice sounds like that.

“Yes,” I say, “then I will come as soon as we have been to our hotel.”

“Yes,” I say, “then I’ll come as soon as we’ve been to our hotel.”

We indulge in no eloquence upon this remarkable occasion. Yet I feel an unusual emotional stir. I tremble greatly, and the telephonic mouthpiece rattles as I replace it.

We won't get all flowery about this amazing moment. Still, I feel a strange emotional wave. I'm shaking a lot, and the phone receiver shakes as I put it down.

And thence the botanist and I walk on to the apartments that have been set aside for us, and into which the poor little rolls of the property that has accumulated about us in Utopia, our earthly raiment, and a change of linen and the like, have already been delivered. As we go I find I have little to say to my companion, until presently I am struck by a transitory wonder that he should have so little to say to me.

And then the botanist and I walk to the rooms that have been set aside for us, where the few items we've collected in Utopia—our clothes, a change of linens, and so on—have already been delivered. As we walk, I realize I have very little to say to my companion, until I’m suddenly surprised by how little he has to say to me as well.

“I can still hardly realise,” I say, “that I am going to see myself—as I might have been.”

“I can still barely grasp,” I say, “that I’m about to see myself—as I could have been.”

“No,” he says, and relapses at once into his own preoccupation.

“No,” he says, and immediately goes back to his own thoughts.

For a moment my wonder as to what he should be thinking about brings me near to a double self-forgetfulness.

For a moment, my curiosity about what he might be thinking leads me to a kind of double self-absorption.

I realise we are at the entrance of our hotel before I can formulate any further remark.

I realize we are at the entrance of our hotel before I can think of anything else to say.

“This is the place,” I say.

“This is the spot,” I say.

CHAPTER THE EIGHTH
My Utopian Self

§ 1

It falls to few of us to interview our better selves. My Utopian self is, of course, my better self—according to my best endeavours—and I must confess myself fully alive to the difficulties of the situation. When I came to this Utopia I had no thought of any such intimate self-examination.

It’s rare for any of us to talk to our better selves. My ideal self is, of course, my best self—based on my highest aspirations—and I have to admit I’m completely aware of how challenging this situation is. When I arrived in this Utopia, I had no intention of any deep self-reflection.

The whole fabric of that other universe sways for a moment as I come into his room, into his clear and ordered work-room. I am trembling. A figure rather taller than myself stands against the light.

The entire atmosphere of that other universe shifts for a moment as I enter his room, his neat and organized workspace. I'm shaking. A figure slightly taller than me stands in front of the light.

He comes towards me, and I, as I advance to meet him, stumble against a chair. Then, still without a word, we are clasping hands.

He walks toward me, and as I step forward to greet him, I trip over a chair. Then, still without saying a word, we shake hands.

I stand now so that the light falls upon him, and I can see his face better. He is a little taller than I, younger looking and sounder looking; he has missed an illness or so, and there is no scar over his eye. His training has been subtly finer than mine; he has made himself a better face than mine.... These things I might have counted upon. I can fancy he winces with a twinge of sympathetic understanding at my manifest inferiority. Indeed, I come, trailing clouds of earthly confusion and weakness; I bear upon me all the defects of my world. He wears, I see, that white tunic with the purple band that I have already begun to consider the proper Utopian clothing for grave men, and his face is clean shaven. We forget to speak at first in the intensity of our mutual inspection. When at last I do gain my voice it is to say something quite different from the fine, significant openings of my premeditated dialogues.

I stand now to let the light shine on him so I can see his face better. He’s a bit taller than me, looks younger and healthier; he’s managed to avoid some illnesses, and there’s no scar over his eye. His training has been subtly better than mine; he’s crafted a nicer face than I have... These are things I might have expected. I can imagine he flinches a bit with a pang of understanding at my obvious shortcomings. In truth, I come carrying the weight of earthly confusion and weakness; I carry all the flaws of my world. I see he’s wearing that white tunic with the purple band that I’ve already started to think of as the right Utopian attire for serious men, and his face is clean-shaven. At first, we forget to speak in the intensity of our mutual observation. When I finally find my voice, it’s to say something completely different from the meaningful openings I had planned for our dialogues.

“You have a pleasant room,” I remark, and look about a little disconcerted because there is no fireplace for me to put my back against, or hearthrug to stand upon. He pushes me a chair, into which I plump, and we hang over an immensity of conversational possibilities.

“You have a nice room,” I say, looking around a bit flustered because there’s no fireplace for me to lean against or a rug to stand on. He scoots a chair over to me, and I sink into it as we hover over a huge range of conversational topics.

“I say,” I plunge, “what do you think of me? You don't think I'm an impostor?”

“I mean,” I dive in, “what do you think of me? You don't think I'm a fraud, do you?”

“Not now that I have seen you. No.”

“Not now that I've seen you. No.”

“Am I so like you?”

“Am I really like you?”

“Like me and your story—exactly.”

“Just like me and your story.”

“You haven't any doubt left?” I ask.

“You don't have any doubts left?” I ask.

“Not in the least, since I saw you enter. You come from the world beyond Sirius, twin to this. Eh?”

“Not at all, since I saw you come in. You’re from the world beyond Sirius, the twin of this one. Right?”

“And you don't want to know how I got here?”

“And you really don’t want to know how I ended up here?”

“I've ceased even to wonder how I got here,” he says, with a laugh that echoes mine.

“I've stopped even wondering how I ended up here,” he says, laughing in a way that reflects my own laughter.

He leans back in his chair, and I in mine, and the absurd parody of our attitude strikes us both.

He leans back in his chair, and I do the same in mine, and we both find the ridiculous way we're acting funny.

“Well?” we say, simultaneously, and laugh together.

"Well?" we say at the same time and laugh together.

I will confess this meeting is more difficult even than I anticipated.

I have to admit, this meeting is more challenging than I expected.

§ 2

Our conversation at that first encounter would do very little to develop the Modern Utopia in my mind. Inevitably, it would be personal and emotional. He would tell me how he stood in his world, and I how I stood in mine. I should have to tell him things, I should have to explain things―.

Our chat during that first meeting wouldn’t really help me shape the Modern Utopia in my mind. It was bound to be personal and emotional. He would share his perspective on his world, and I would share mine. I would need to tell him things; I would need to explain things—.

No, the conversation would contribute nothing to a modern Utopia.

No, the conversation wouldn’t add anything to a modern Utopia.

And so I leave it out.

And so I’ll leave it out.

§ 3

But I should go back to my botanist in a state of emotional relaxation. At first I should not heed the fact that he, too, had been in some manner stirred. “I have seen him,” I should say, needlessly, and seem to be on the verge of telling the untellable. Then I should fade off into: “It's the strangest thing.”

But I should return to my botanist feeling emotionally calm. At first, I shouldn’t pay attention to the fact that he, too, had been somewhat affected. “I’ve seen him,” I would say unnecessarily, and seem ready to share something impossible to express. Then I would trail off into, “It’s the strangest thing.”

He would interrupt me with his own preoccupation. “You know,” he would say, “I've seen someone.”

He would interrupt me with his own thoughts. “You know,” he would say, “I’ve seen someone.”

I should pause and look at him.

I should stop and look at him.

“She is in this world,” he says.

“She is in this world,” he says.

“Who is in this world?”

“Who’s in this world?”

“Mary!”

“Hey, Mary!”

I have not heard her name before, but I understand, of course, at once.

I haven't heard her name before, but I get it right away.

“I saw her,” he explains.

"I saw her," he says.

“Saw her?”

"Did you see her?"

“I'm certain it was her. Certain. She was far away across those gardens near here—and before I had recovered from my amazement she had gone! But it was Mary.”

“I'm sure it was her. Sure. She was over there in those gardens nearby—and before I could wrap my head around it, she was gone! But it was Mary.”

He takes my arm. “You know I did not understand this,” he says. “I did not really understand that when you said Utopia, you meant I was to meet her—in happiness.”

He takes my arm. “You know I didn’t get this,” he says. “I didn’t really understand that when you said Utopia, you meant I was supposed to meet her—in happiness.”

“I didn't.”

"I didn't."

“It works out at that.”

"It adds up to that."

“You haven't met her yet.”

“You haven't met her yet.”

“I shall. It makes everything different. To tell you the truth I've rather hated this Utopia of yours at times. You mustn't mind my saying it, but there's something of the Gradgrind―”

“I will. It changes everything. Honestly, there have been times when I've really disliked this Utopia of yours. You shouldn't take it the wrong way, but there's something about it that's a bit like Gradgrind—”

Probably I should swear at that.

Probably I should curse at that.

“What?” he says.

“What?” he asks.

“Nothing.”

“Nothing.”

“But you spoke?”

"But you talked?"

“I was purring. I'm a Gradgrind—it's quite right—anything you can say about Herbert Spencer, vivisectors, materialistic Science or Atheists, applies without correction to me. Begbie away! But now you think better of a modern Utopia? Was the lady looking well?”

“I was purring. I'm a Gradgrind—it's totally true—everything you can say about Herbert Spencer, vivisectors, materialistic Science, or Atheists applies to me, no changes needed. Begbie out of here! But now, do you think a modern Utopia is better? Was the lady looking good?”

“It was her real self. Yes. Not the broken woman I met—in the real world.”

“It was her true self. Yes. Not the shattered woman I encountered—in real life.”

“And as though she was pining for you.”

“And it’s like she was longing for you.”

He looks puzzled.

He looks confused.

“Look there!” I say.

"Check that out!" I say.

He looks.

He’s looking.

We are standing high above the ground in the loggia into which our apartments open, and I point across the soft haze of the public gardens to a tall white mass of University buildings that rises with a free and fearless gesture, to lift saluting pinnacles against the clear evening sky. “Don't you think that rather more beautiful than—say—our National Gallery?”

We are standing high above the ground in the loggia that leads to our apartments, and I point through the soft haze of the public gardens to a tall, white cluster of University buildings that rises confidently, lifting its prominent peaks against the clear evening sky. “Don't you think that's much more beautiful than—let's say—our National Gallery?”

He looks at it critically. “There's a lot of metal in it,” he objects. “What?”

He examines it closely. “There's a lot of metal in this,” he says. “What?”

I purred. “But, anyhow, whatever you can't see in that, you can, I suppose, see that it is different from anything in your world—it lacks the kindly humanity of a red-brick Queen Anne villa residence, with its gables and bulges, and bow windows, and its stained glass fanlight, and so forth. It lacks the self-complacent unreasonableness of Board of Works classicism. There's something in its proportions—as though someone with brains had taken a lot of care to get it quite right, someone who not only knew what metal can do, but what a University ought to be, somebody who had found the Gothic spirit enchanted, petrified, in a cathedral, and had set it free.”

I purred. “But anyway, whatever you can't see in that, you can, I guess, see that it's different from anything in your world—it doesn't have the friendly charm of a red-brick Queen Anne house, with its gables and bulges, bow windows, and stained glass fanlight, and so on. It doesn’t have the self-satisfied absurdity of Board of Works classicism. There’s something about its proportions—as if someone smart took a lot of care to get it just right, someone who not only understood what metal can do, but also what a university should be, someone who discovered the Gothic spirit enchanted, frozen in a cathedral, and managed to set it free.”

“But what has this,” he asks, “to do with her?”

“But what does this,” he asks, “have to do with her?”

“Very much,” I say. “This is not the same world. If she is here, she will be younger in spirit and wiser. She will be in many ways more refined―”

“Definitely,” I say. “This isn’t the same world. If she’s here, she’ll have a younger spirit and more wisdom. In many ways, she’ll be more refined—”

“No one―” he begins, with a note of indignation.

“No one—” he starts, sounding indignant.

“No, no! She couldn't be. I was wrong there. But she will be different. Grant that at any rate. When you go forward to speak to her, she may not remember—very many things you may remember. Things that happened at Frognal—dear romantic walks through the Sunday summer evenings, practically you two alone, you in your adolescent silk hat and your nice gentlemanly gloves.... Perhaps that did not happen here! And she may have other memories—of things—that down there haven't happened. You noted her costume. She wasn't by any chance one of the samurai?”

“No, no! She couldn't be. I was wrong about that. But she will be different. At least, accept that. When you go to talk to her, she might not remember—there are plenty of things you might recall. Things that happened at Frognal—those sweet, romantic walks on Sunday summer evenings, almost just the two of you, you in your teenage silk hat and your nice gentlemanly gloves.... Maybe that didn’t happen here! And she might have other memories—of things—that haven’t happened down there. You noticed her outfit. Was she by any chance one of the samurai?”

He answers, with a note of satisfaction, “No! She wore a womanly dress of greyish green.”

He replies, with a hint of satisfaction, “No! She wore a feminine dress in a grayish-green color.”

“Probably under the Lesser Rule.”

“Probably under the Minor Rule.”

“I don't know what you mean by the Lesser Rule. She wasn't one of the samurai.”

“I don't know what you mean by the Lesser Rule. She wasn't one of the samurai.”

“And, after all, you know—I keep on reminding you, and you keep on losing touch with the fact, that this world contains your double.”

“And, after all, you know—I keep reminding you, and you keep forgetting that this world has your double.”

He pales, and his countenance is disturbed. Thank Heaven, I've touched him at last!

He turns pale, and his face shows distress. Thank goodness, I've finally reached him!

“This world contains your double. But, conceivably, everything may be different here. The whole romantic story may have run a different course. It was as it was in our world, by the accidents of custom and proximity. Adolescence is a defenceless plastic period. You are a man to form great affections,—noble, great affections. You might have met anyone almost at that season and formed the same attachment.”

“This world has your counterpart. But, it's possible that everything is different here. The whole romantic story could have taken a different direction. It was the way it was in our world, due to the quirks of habit and closeness. Adolescence is a vulnerable and flexible time. You are at a point where you can develop deep feelings—noble, significant feelings. You could have met anyone back then and developed the same bond.”

For a time he is perplexed and troubled by this suggestion.

For a while, he is confused and disturbed by this idea.

“No,” he says, a little doubtfully. “No. It was herself.” ... Then, emphatically, “No!

“No,” he says, a bit uncertain. “No. It was her.” ... Then, firmly, “No!

§ 4

For a time we say no more, and I fall musing about my strange encounter with my Utopian double. I think of the confessions I have just made to him, the strange admissions both to him and myself. I have stirred up the stagnations of my own emotional life, the pride that has slumbered, the hopes and disappointments that have not troubled me for years. There are things that happened to me in my adolescence that no discipline of reason will ever bring to a just proportion for me, the first humiliations I was made to suffer, the waste of all the fine irrecoverable loyalties and passions of my youth. The dull base caste of my little personal tragi-comedy—I have ostensibly forgiven, I have for the most part forgotten—and yet when I recall them I hate each actor still. Whenever it comes into my mind—I do my best to prevent it—there it is, and these detestable people blot out the stars for me.

For a while, I say nothing more, and I start thinking about my weird encounter with my Utopian counterpart. I reflect on the confessions I just made to him, the strange truths both to him and to myself. I’ve stirred up the stagnation in my emotional life, the pride that’s been asleep, the hopes and disappointments that haven’t bothered me for years. There are things that happened to me during my teenage years that no amount of rational thinking will ever put into perspective—those first humiliations I had to endure, the loss of all the deep, irreplaceable loyalties and passions of my youth. The dull, underlying mess of my little personal tragedy—I have seemingly forgiven, I have mostly forgotten—but whenever I remember them, I still despise each person involved. Whenever it pops into my head—I try my best to stop it—there it is, and these horrible people overshadow everything for me.

I have told all that story to my double, and he has listened with understanding eyes. But for a little while those squalid memories will not sink back into the deeps.

I’ve shared that whole story with my double, and he listened with understanding. But for a little while, those grim memories won’t fade away.

We lean, side by side, over our balcony, lost in such egotistical absorptions, quite heedless of the great palace of noble dreams to which our first enterprise has brought us.

We lean next to each other over our balcony, caught up in our own thoughts, completely unaware of the magnificent palace of noble dreams that our initial endeavor has led us to.

§ 5

I can understand the botanist this afternoon; for once we are in the same key. My own mental temper has gone for the day, and I know what it means to be untempered. Here is a world and a glorious world, and it is for me to take hold of it, to have to do with it, here and now, and behold! I can only think that I am burnt and scarred, and there rankles that wretched piece of business, the mean unimaginative triumph of my antagonist―

I can relate to the botanist this afternoon; for once, we’re on the same wavelength. My own mindset has faded for the day, and I understand what it means to feel unsettled. Here is a vibrant world, a beautiful world, and it’s my responsibility to grasp it, to engage with it, here and now. But all I can think about is that I feel burned and scarred, and that terrible situation keeps nagging at me, the pathetic and dull victory of my opponent—

I wonder how many men have any real freedom of mind, are, in truth, unhampered by such associations, to whom all that is great and noble in life does not, at times at least, if not always, seem secondary to obscure rivalries and considerations, to the petty hates that are like germs in the blood, to the lust for self-assertion, to dwarfish pride, to affections they gave in pledge even before they were men.

I wonder how many men truly have freedom of thought, who aren't affected by such connections, and for whom everything great and noble in life doesn't occasionally, if not always, seem less important than hidden rivalries and motivations, than the petty grudges that are like germs in the bloodstream, than the desire for self-assertion, than childish pride, than attachments they committed to even before they became men.

The botanist beside me dreams, I know, of vindications for that woman.

The botanist next to me dreams, I know, of justifications for that woman.

All this world before us, and its order and liberty, are no more than a painted scene before which he is to meet Her at last, freed from “that scoundrel.”

All this world in front of us, and its order and freedom, is just a painted backdrop where he will finally meet Her, free from “that jerk.”

He expects “that scoundrel” really to be present and, as it were, writhing under their feet....

He really expects “that scoundrel” to be there and, in a way, squirming under their feet....

I wonder if that man was a scoundrel. He has gone wrong on earth, no doubt, has failed and degenerated, but what was it sent him wrong? Was his failure inherent, or did some net of cross purposes tangle about his feet? Suppose he is not a failure in Utopia!...

I wonder if that man was a scoundrel. He has definitely messed up during his time on earth, has failed and declined, but what caused him to go wrong? Was his failure something built into him, or did some mix of conflicting goals trip him up? What if he isn’t actually a failure in Utopia!...

I wonder that this has never entered the botanist's head.

I can't believe this has never occurred to the botanist.

He, with his vaguer mind, can overlook—spite of my ruthless reminders—all that would mar his vague anticipations. That, too, if I suggested it, he would overcome and disregard. He has the most amazing power of resistance to uncongenial ideas; amazing that is, to me. He hates the idea of meeting his double, and consequently so soon as I cease to speak of that, with scarcely an effort of his will, it fades again from his mind.

He, with his unclear thinking, can ignore—despite my harsh reminders—all that would ruin his unclear expectations. Even if I brought it up, he would push it aside and forget it. He has an incredible ability to resist ideas he dislikes; incredible, at least, to me. He hates the thought of encountering someone like himself, and as soon as I stop talking about it, it quickly fades from his mind with hardly any effort on his part.

Down below in the gardens two children pursue one another, and one, near caught, screams aloud and rouses me from my reverie.

Down in the gardens, two kids are chasing each other, and one, almost caught, screams out and snaps me out of my daydream.

I follow their little butterfly antics until they vanish beyond a thicket of flowering rhododendra, and then my eyes go back to the great façade of the University buildings.

I watch their little butterfly antics until they disappear beyond a thicket of flowering rhododendrons, and then my gaze returns to the grand façade of the University buildings.

But I am in no mood to criticise architecture.

But I’m not in the mood to criticize architecture.

Why should a modern Utopia insist upon slipping out of the hands of its creator and becoming the background of a personal drama—of such a silly little drama?

Why should a modern Utopia let go of its creator and become the backdrop for a personal drama—such a trivial little drama?

The botanist will not see Utopia in any other way. He tests it entirely by its reaction upon the individual persons and things he knows; he dislikes it because he suspects it of wanting to lethal chamber his aunt's “dear old doggie,” and now he is reconciled to it because a certain “Mary” looks much younger and better here than she did on earth. And here am I, near fallen into the same way of dealing!

The botanist will see Utopia only through his own perspective. He evaluates it based solely on how it affects the people and things he knows; he initially dislikes it because he thinks it wants to execute his aunt’s “sweet old dog,” but now he’s come to accept it because a certain “Mary” looks much younger and healthier here than she did back on Earth. And here I am, almost falling into the same trap!

We agreed to purge this State and all the people in it of traditions, associations, bias, laws, and artificial entanglements, and begin anew; but we have no power to liberate ourselves. Our past, even its accidents, its accidents above all, and ourselves, are one.

We agreed to cleanse this State and everyone in it of traditions, associations, biases, laws, and unnecessary complications, and start fresh; but we lack the power to free ourselves. Our past, especially its mishaps, and ourselves are intertwined.

CHAPTER THE NINTH
The Samurai

§ 1

Neither my Utopian double nor I love emotion sufficiently to cultivate it, and my feelings are in a state of seemly subordination when we meet again. He is now in possession of some clear, general ideas about my own world, and I can broach almost at once the thoughts that have been growing and accumulating since my arrival in this planet of my dreams. We find our interest in a humanised state-craft, makes us, in spite of our vast difference in training and habits, curiously akin.

Neither my ideal counterpart nor I have enough love for emotion to really nurture it, and my feelings are appropriately restrained when we meet again. He now has some clear, general ideas about my world, and I can quickly start sharing the thoughts that have been building up since I arrived in this dream world. Our interest in a more humane approach to governance makes us, despite our significant differences in training and habits, surprisingly similar.

I put it to him that I came to Utopia with but very vague ideas of the method of government, biassed, perhaps, a little in favour of certain electoral devices, but for the rest indeterminate, and that I have come to perceive more and more clearly that the large intricacy of Utopian organisation demands more powerful and efficient method of control than electoral methods can give. I have come to distinguish among the varied costumes and the innumerable types of personality Utopia presents, certain men and women of a distinctive costume and bearing, and I know now that these people constitute an order, the samurai, the “voluntary nobility,” which is essential in the scheme of the Utopian State. I know that this order is open to every physically and mentally healthy adult in the Utopian State who will observe its prescribed austere rule of living, that much of the responsible work of the State is reserved for it, and I am inclined now at the first onset of realisation to regard it as far more significant than it really is in the Utopian scheme, as being, indeed, in itself and completely the Utopian scheme. My predominant curiosity concerns the organisation of this order. As it has developed in my mind, it has reminded me more and more closely of that strange class of guardians which constitutes the essential substance of Plato's Republic, and it is with an implicit reference to Plato's profound intuitions that I and my double discuss this question.

I told him that I came to Utopia with only vague ideas about the government, maybe slightly biased towards certain voting methods, but overall unsure. I've started to realize more clearly that the complex structure of Utopian society needs a stronger and more effective way to maintain control than just voting. I've begun to notice among the different outfits and countless personalities in Utopia some men and women with a unique style and demeanor, and I now understand that these people form an order, the samurai, the “voluntary nobility,” which is crucial in the Utopian framework. I know that this order is open to any physically and mentally healthy adult in the Utopian State who follows its strict rules of living, and that much of the State's important work is allocated to it. I'm starting to think, in the early stages of this realization, that this order is far more important than it actually is in the Utopian plan and that it might even represent the plan entirely. My main curiosity is about how this order is organized. As I think about it, it increasingly reminds me of that peculiar class of guardians that forms the core of Plato's Republic, and this is a crucial reference point for my double and me as we discuss this topic.

To clarify our comparison he tells me something of the history of Utopia, and incidentally it becomes necessary to make a correction in the assumptions upon which I have based my enterprise. We are assuming a world identical in every respect with the real planet Earth, except for the profoundest differences in the mental content of life. This implies a different literature, a different philosophy, and a different history, and so soon as I come to talk to him I find that though it remains unavoidable that we should assume the correspondence of the two populations, man for man—unless we would face unthinkable complications—we must assume also that a great succession of persons of extraordinary character and mental gifts, who on earth died in childhood or at birth, or who never learnt to read, or who lived and died amidst savage or brutalising surroundings that gave their gifts no scope, did in Utopia encounter happier chances, and take up the development and application of social theory—from the time of the first Utopists in a steady onward progress down to the present hour. [Footnote: One might assume as an alternative to this that amidst the four-fifths of the Greek literature now lost to the world, there perished, neglected, some book of elementary significance, some earlier Novum Organum, that in Utopia survived to achieve the profoundest consequences.] The differences of condition, therefore, had widened with each successive year. Jesus Christ had been born into a liberal and progressive Roman Empire that spread from the Arctic Ocean to the Bight of Benin, and was to know no Decline and Fall, and Mahomet, instead of embodying the dense prejudices of Arab ignorance, opened his eyes upon an intellectual horizon already nearly as wide as the world.

To clarify our comparison, he tells me a bit about the history of Utopia, and it turns out I need to correct some of the assumptions I used as the basis for my project. We're assuming a world that is exactly like our real planet Earth, except for significant differences in the mental content of life. This means there would be a different literature, a different philosophy, and a different history. As soon as I start talking to him, I realize that while we have to assume the populations correspond, person for person—unless we want to deal with unimaginable complications—we also have to accept that many exceptional individuals who died young on Earth, or who never learned to read, or who lived in harsh, brutal environments that stifled their talents, ended up with much better opportunities in Utopia. They were able to further develop and apply social theory—from the time of the first Utopians, continuously advancing up to today. [Footnote: One could consider as an alternative that among the four-fifths of Greek literature now lost to us, there might have been some neglected book of basic importance, perhaps an earlier Novum Organum, that survived in Utopia and had significant impact.] Therefore, the differences in circumstances widened each year. Jesus Christ was born into a liberal and progressive Roman Empire that stretched from the Arctic Ocean to the Bight of Benin and experienced no Decline and Fall, while Mahomet, instead of being confined by the deep prejudices of Arab ignorance, was born into a world that was already rich in intellectual horizons.

And through this empire the flow of thought, the flow of intention, poured always more abundantly. There were wars, but they were conclusive wars that established new and more permanent relations, that swept aside obstructions, and abolished centres of decay; there were prejudices tempered to an ordered criticism, and hatreds that merged at last in tolerant reactions. It was several hundred years ago that the great organisation of the samurai came into its present form. And it was this organisation's widely sustained activities that had shaped and established the World State in Utopia.

And throughout this empire, the exchange of ideas and intentions flowed more freely than ever. There were wars, but they were decisive wars that created new and lasting relationships, removed barriers, and eliminated sources of decline; there were biases that were refined into structured critiques, and animosities that eventually blended into accepting responses. It was several hundred years ago that the great organization of the samurai took on its current structure. And it was this organization's ongoing efforts that helped shape and establish the World State in Utopia.

This organisation of the samurai was a quite deliberate invention. It arose in the course of social and political troubles and complications, analogous to those of our own time on earth, and was, indeed, the last of a number of political and religious experiments dating back to the first dawn of philosophical state-craft in Greece. That hasty despair of specialisation for government that gave our poor world individualism, democratic liberalism, and anarchism, and that curious disregard of the fund of enthusiasm and self-sacrifice in men, which is the fundamental weakness of worldly economics, do not appear in the history of Utopian thought. All that history is pervaded with the recognition of the fact that self-seeking is no more the whole of human life than the satisfaction of hunger; that it is an essential of a man's existence no doubt, and that under stress of evil circumstances it may as entirely obsess him as would the food hunt during famine, but that life may pass beyond to an illimitable world of emotions and effort. Every sane person consists of possibilities beyond the unavoidable needs, is capable of disinterested feeling, even if it amounts only to enthusiasm for a sport or an industrial employment well done, for an art, or for a locality or class. In our world now, as in the Utopian past, this impersonal energy of a man goes out into religious emotion and work, into patriotic effort, into artistic enthusiasms, into games and amateur employments, and an enormous proportion of the whole world's fund of effort wastes itself in religious and political misunderstandings and conflicts, and in unsatisfying amusements and unproductive occupations. In a modern Utopia there will, indeed, be no perfection; in Utopia there must also be friction, conflicts and waste, but the waste will be enormously less than in our world. And the co-ordination of activities this relatively smaller waste will measure, will be the achieved end for which the order of the samurai was first devised.

This organization of the samurai was a deliberate creation. It emerged during a time of social and political difficulties similar to those of our own era and was actually the last in a series of political and religious experiments tracing back to the early days of philosophical governance in Greece. The rushed despair over specialization in government that gave rise to individualism, democratic liberalism, and anarchism in our troubled world, along with the curious neglect of human enthusiasm and self-sacrifice—which are the key weaknesses of earthly economics—are not evident in the history of Utopian thought. That history is marked by the acknowledgment that self-interest is not the entirety of human existence, just as hunger is not the sole aspect of life. While it is certainly a part of existence, and under dire circumstances it can consume someone like the desperate search for food during famine, life can extend into an infinite realm of emotions and endeavors. Every rational person is full of potential beyond basic needs and can experience selfless feelings, even if it’s just passion for a sport, a job well done, an art form, or for a place or community. In our world today, as in the Utopian past, this impersonal energy drives people into religious feelings and actions, patriotic efforts, artistic passions, recreational activities, and a significant portion of global effort is wasted on religious and political misunderstandings and conflicts, as well as unfulfilling pastimes and nonproductive tasks. In a modern Utopia, there will indeed be no perfection; Utopia must also include friction, conflicts, and waste, but that waste will be far less than what we experience now. The coordination of activities that this relatively smaller waste will indicate will be the ultimate goal for which the order of the samurai was originally created.

Inevitably such an order must have first arisen among a clash of social forces and political systems as a revolutionary organisation. It must have set before itself the attainment of some such Utopian ideal as this modern Utopia does, in the key of mortal imperfection, realise. At first it may have directed itself to research and discussion, to the elaboration of its ideal, to the discussion of a plan of campaign, but at some stage it must have assumed a more militant organisation, and have prevailed against and assimilated the pre-existing political organisations, and to all intents and purposes have become this present synthesised World State. Traces of that militancy would, therefore, pervade it still, and a campaigning quality—no longer against specific disorders, but against universal human weaknesses, and the inanimate forces that trouble man—still remain as its essential quality.

Inevitably, such an order must have first emerged from a clash of social forces and political systems as a revolutionary organization. It must have aimed at achieving some Utopian ideal, similar to what this modern Utopia seeks to realize, acknowledging human imperfection. Initially, it might have focused on research and discussion, developing its ideal and planning its strategy. However, at some point, it must have taken on a more militant structure, overcoming and integrating existing political organizations, ultimately transforming into the current synthesized World State. Thus, remnants of that militancy would still be present, and a campaigning spirit—no longer targeting specific issues, but rather addressing universal human weaknesses and the inanimate forces that challenge humanity—remains its core characteristic.

“Something of this kind,” I should tell my double, “had arisen in our thought”—I jerk my head back to indicate an infinitely distant planet—“just before I came upon these explorations. The idea had reached me, for example, of something to be called a New Republic, which was to be in fact an organisation for revolution something after the fashion of your samurai, as I understand them—only most of the organisation and the rule of life still remained to be invented. All sorts of people were thinking of something in that way about the time of my coming. The idea, as it reached me, was pretty crude in several respects. It ignored the high possibility of a synthesis of languages in the future; it came from a literary man, who wrote only English, and, as I read him—he was a little vague in his proposals—it was to be a purely English-speaking movement. And his ideas were coloured too much by the peculiar opportunism of his time; he seemed to have more than half an eye for a prince or a millionaire of genius; he seemed looking here and there for support and the structural elements of a party. Still, the idea of a comprehensive movement of disillusioned and illuminated men behind the shams and patriotisms, the spites and personalities of the ostensible world was there.”

“Something like this,” I should tell my double, “had come up in our minds”—I point my head back to indicate an incredibly distant planet—“just before I stumbled upon these explorations. The idea had come to me, for example, of something called a New Republic, which was actually going to be an organization for revolution, somewhat like your samurai, as I understand them—only most of the structure and the rules of life still needed to be developed. A lot of people were thinking along those lines around the time I arrived. The idea, as it reached me, was pretty rough around the edges in several ways. It overlooked the strong possibility of blending languages in the future; it came from a literary guy who only wrote in English, and, as I interpreted him—he was a bit vague in his suggestions—it was supposed to be a purely English-speaking movement. And his thoughts were too influenced by the specific opportunism of his era; he seemed to have more than a passing interest in finding a prince or a genius billionaire; he appeared to be searching here and there for backing and the foundational elements of a party. Still, the concept of a broad movement of disillusioned and enlightened individuals standing against the pretenses and nationalisms, the grudges and egos of the visible world was there.”

I added some particulars.

I added some details.

“Our movement had something of that spirit in the beginning,” said my Utopian double. “But while your men seem to be thinking disconnectedly, and upon a very narrow and fragmentary basis of accumulated conclusions, ours had a fairly comprehensive science of human association, and a very careful analysis of the failures of preceding beginnings to draw upon. After all, your world must be as full as ours was of the wreckage and decay of previous attempts; churches, aristocracies, orders, cults....”

“Our movement had a bit of that spirit at the start,” said my Utopian double. “But while your people seem to think in a disorganized way, and based on a very limited and fragmented set of conclusions, ours had a pretty inclusive understanding of human relationships and a detailed analysis of the failures of past efforts to learn from. After all, your world must be just as filled as ours was with the remnants and decline of previous attempts; churches, aristocracies, orders, cults....”

“Only at present we seem to have lost heart altogether, and now there are no new religions, no new orders, no new cults—no beginnings any more.”

“Right now, it feels like we've completely lost our spirit, and there are no new religions, no new movements, no new beliefs—no new beginnings anymore.”

“But that's only a resting phase, perhaps. You were saying―”

“But that's just a break, maybe. You were saying―”

“Oh!—let that distressful planet alone for a time! Tell me how you manage in Utopia.”

“Oh!—just leave that troubled planet alone for a while! Tell me how you’re doing in Utopia.”

§ 2

The social theorists of Utopia, my double explained, did not base their schemes upon the classification of men into labour and capital, the landed interest, the liquor trade, and the like. They esteemed these as accidental categories, indefinitely amenable to statesmanship, and they looked for some practical and real classification upon which to base organisation. [Footnote: In that they seem to have profited by a more searching criticism of early social and political speculations than our earth has yet undertaken. The social speculations of the Greeks, for example, had just the same primary defect as the economic speculations of the eighteenth century—they began with the assumption that the general conditions of the prevalent state of affairs were permanent.] But, on the other hand, the assumption that men are unclassifiable, because practically homogeneous, which underlies modern democratic methods and all the fallacies of our equal justice, is even more alien to the Utopian mind. Throughout Utopia there is, of course, no other than provisional classifications, since every being is regarded as finally unique, but for political and social purposes things have long rested upon a classification of temperaments, which attends mainly to differences in the range and quality and character of the individual imagination.

The social theorists of Utopia, my companion explained, didn’t base their ideas on dividing people into labor and capital, landowners, the liquor industry, and similar categories. They saw these as random classifications that could change with good governance, and they sought a practical and realistic basis for organization. [Footnote: In this respect, they seem to have benefited from a more thorough critique of early social and political theories than we have done on Earth. The social theories of the Greeks, for instance, had the same fundamental flaw as the economic theories of the eighteenth century—they started with the assumption that the current state of affairs was permanent.] However, the idea that people are unclassifiable because they are essentially similar, which underpins modern democratic systems and the misconceptions of our so-called equal justice, is even more foreign to the Utopian perspective. Throughout Utopia, there are only temporary classifications, as every individual is considered ultimately unique, but for political and social purposes, the focus has long been on classifying temperaments, mainly paying attention to the differences in the range, quality, and nature of individual imagination.

This Utopian classification was a rough one, but it served its purpose to determine the broad lines of political organisation; it was so far unscientific that many individuals fall between or within two or even three of its classes. But that was met by giving the correlated organisation a compensatory looseness of play. Four main classes of mind were distinguished, called, respectively, the Poietic, the Kinetic, the Dull, and the Base. The former two are supposed to constitute the living tissue of the State; the latter are the fulcra and resistances, the bone and cover of its body. They are not hereditary classes, nor is there any attempt to develop any class by special breeding, simply because the intricate interplay of heredity is untraceable and incalculable. They are classes to which people drift of their own accord. Education is uniform until differentiation becomes unmistakable, and each man (and woman) must establish his position with regard to the lines of this abstract classification by his own quality, choice, and development....

This Utopian classification was a rough one, but it achieved its goal of outlining the broad contours of political organization; it was somewhat unscientific because many individuals fit into or straddle two or even three of its categories. However, that was addressed by allowing the corresponding organization a flexible structure. Four main classes of mindset were identified, referred to as the Poietic, the Kinetic, the Dull, and the Base. The first two are meant to make up the living essence of the State; the latter provide the support and structure, the bones and skin of its physical form. These are not hereditary classes, and there is no effort to cultivate any class through selective breeding since the complex dynamics of heredity are unpredictable and unquantifiable. People naturally gravitate toward these classes. Education is consistent until differences become clear, and each person (man or woman) must determine their place within this abstract classification based on their own qualities, choices, and personal growth.

The Poietic or creative class of mental individuality embraces a wide range of types, but they agree in possessing imaginations that range beyond the known and accepted, and that involve the desire to bring the discoveries made in such excursions, into knowledge and recognition. The scope and direction of the imaginative excursion may vary very greatly. It may be the invention of something new or the discovery of something hitherto unperceived. When the invention or discovery is primarily beauty then we have the artistic type of Poietic mind; when it is not so, we have the true scientific man. The range of discovery may be narrowed as it is in the art of Whistler or the science of a cytologist, or it may embrace a wide extent of relevance, until at last both artist or scientific inquirer merge in the universal reference of the true philosopher. To the accumulated activities of the Poietic type, reacted upon by circumstances, are due almost all the forms assumed by human thought and feeling. All religious ideas, all ideas of what is good or beautiful, entered life through the poietic inspirations of man. Except for processes of decay, the forms of the human future must come also through men of this same type, and it is a primary essential to our modern idea of an abundant secular progress that these activities should be unhampered and stimulated.

The creative class of mental individuality includes a wide variety of types, but they all share an imagination that stretches beyond the known and accepted, along with a desire to turn discoveries made during these explorations into knowledge and recognition. The scope and direction of these imaginative pursuits can vary significantly. It might involve creating something new or discovering something that hasn’t been noticed before. When the focus is primarily on beauty, we see the artistic type of creative mind; when it isn't, we have the true scientific thinker. The range of discovery can be narrow, like in the art of Whistler or the science of a cytologist, or it can be broad, ultimately leading both the artist and the scientific investigator to merge into the universal perspective of the true philosopher. Almost all forms of human thought and feeling stem from the accumulated actions of the creative type, influenced by their circumstances. All religious ideas, as well as concepts of what is good or beautiful, entered life through the creative inspirations of people. Apart from processes of decay, the forms of the human future will also come from individuals of this same type, and it's essential to our modern notion of abundant secular progress that these activities remain unhindered and encouraged.

The Kinetic class consists of types, various, of course, and merging insensibly along the boundary into the less representative constituents of the Poietic group, but distinguished by a more restricted range of imagination. Their imaginations do not range beyond the known, experienced, and accepted, though within these limits they may imagine as vividly or more vividly than members of the former group. They are often very clever and capable people, but they do not do, and they do not desire to do, new things. The more vigorous individuals of this class are the most teachable people in the world, and they are generally more moral and more trustworthy than the Poietic types. They live,—while the Poietics are always something of experimentalists with life. The characteristics of either of these two classes may be associated with a good or bad physique, with excessive or defective energy, with exceptional keenness of the senses in some determinate direction or such-like “bent,” and the Kinetic type, just as the Poietic type, may display an imagination of restricted or of the most universal range. But a fairly energetic Kinetic is probably the nearest thing to that ideal our earthly anthropologists have in mind when they speak of the “Normal” human being. The very definition of the Poietic class involves a certain abnormality.

The Kinetic class includes various types that blend gradually into the less defining members of the Poietic group, but they are marked by a narrower range of imagination. Their creativity remains within what is known, experienced, and accepted; within these boundaries, they can imagine as vividly or even more vividly than those in the previous group. They are often smart and capable individuals, but they do not engage in or wish to try new things. The more energetic members of this class are the most teachable people in the world, and they tend to be more moral and trustworthy than the Poietic types. They tend to live a stable life, while the Poietics often act as experimentalists with life. The traits of either class can be linked to a good or poor physique, excessive or limited energy, a heightened sensitivity in specific areas, or similar inclinations, and just like the Poietic type, the Kinetic type can have either a limited or a broad imagination. However, a reasonably energetic Kinetic person is probably the closest representation to the ideal human that our earthly anthropologists envision when they refer to the "Normal" human being. The very definition of the Poietic class suggests a certain abnormality.

The Utopians distinguished two extremes of this Kinetic class according to the quality of their imaginative preferences, the Dan and Beersheba, as it were, of this division. At one end is the mainly intellectual, unoriginal type, which, with energy of personality, makes an admirable judge or administrator and without it an uninventive, laborious, common mathematician, or common scholar, or common scientific man; while at the other end is the mainly emotional, unoriginal man, the type to which—at a low level of personal energy—my botanist inclines. The second type includes, amidst its energetic forms, great actors, and popular politicians and preachers. Between these extremes is a long and wide region of varieties, into which one would put most of the people who form the reputable workmen, the men of substance, the trustworthy men and women, the pillars of society on earth.

The Utopians identified two extremes within this Kinetic class based on their imaginative preferences, akin to the Dan and Beersheba of this category. On one end is the mainly intellectual, unoriginal type, which, if they have strong personalities, makes an excellent judge or administrator, but without that energy, they become unimaginative, hard-working, ordinary mathematicians, scholars, or scientists. On the other end is the mainly emotional, unoriginal individual, the type my botanist leans towards at a lower level of personal energy. This second type features energetic forms like great actors, popular politicians, and preachers. Between these extremes lies a broad range of varieties, encompassing most of the reputable workers, successful individuals, reliable men and women, and the pillars of society.

Below these two classes in the Utopian scheme of things, and merging insensibly into them, come the Dull. The Dull are persons of altogether inadequate imagination, the people who never seem to learn thoroughly, or hear distinctly, or think clearly. (I believe if everyone is to be carefully educated they would be considerably in the minority in the world, but it is quite possible that will not be the reader's opinion. It is clearly a matter of an arbitrary line.) They are the stupid people, the incompetent people, the formal, imitative people, the people who, in any properly organised State, should, as a class, gravitate towards and below the minimum wage that qualifies for marriage. The laws of heredity are far too mysterious for such offspring as they do produce to be excluded from a fair chance in the world, but for themselves, they count neither for work nor direction in the State.

Below these two classes in the Utopian system, and blending seamlessly into them, are the Dull. The Dull are individuals with completely insufficient imagination, those who never seem to learn thoroughly, hear clearly, or think straight. (I think if everyone were to be properly educated, they would be quite the minority in the world, but that may not be the reader's view. It's clearly a matter of an arbitrary distinction.) They are the foolish people, the incompetent ones, the rigid, imitative individuals, those who, in any well-organized society, should, as a group, drift toward and below the minimum wage needed for marriage. The laws of heredity are far too complex for the offspring they produce to be denied a fair shot in the world, but for themselves, they contribute neither labor nor guidance to society.

Finally, with a bold disregard of the logician's classificatory rules, these Utopian statesmen who devised the World State, hewed out in theory a class of the Base. The Base may, indeed, be either poietic, kinetic, or dull, though most commonly they are the last, and their definition concerns not so much the quality of their imagination as a certain bias in it, that to a statesman makes it a matter for special attention. The Base have a narrower and more persistent egoistic reference than the common run of humanity; they may boast, but they have no frankness; they have relatively great powers of concealment, and they are capable of, and sometimes have an aptitude and inclination towards, cruelty. In the queer phrasing of earthly psychology with its clumsy avoidance of analysis, they have no “moral sense.” They count as an antagonism to the State organisation.

Finally, ignoring the logician’s classification rules, these Utopian leaders who created the World State developed a theoretical class known as the Base. The Base can be either creative, active, or dull, though they are most often considered the latter. Their definition doesn’t focus so much on the quality of their imagination but rather on a certain bias that draws a statesman’s special attention. The Base have a more limited and consistent self-centered perspective than most people; they may brag, but they lack honesty. They possess significant skills in deception and can show, and sometimes have a tendency toward, cruelty. In the strange terms of earthly psychology, which awkwardly avoids deeper analysis, they lack a “moral sense.” They present an opposition to the State’s organization.

Obviously, this is the rudest of classifications, and no Utopian has ever supposed it to be a classification for individual application, a classification so precise that one can say, this man is “poietic,” and that man is “base.” In actual experience these qualities mingle and vary in every possible way. It is not a classification for Truth, but a classification to an end. Taking humanity as a multitude of unique individuals in mass, one may, for practical purposes, deal with it far more conveniently by disregarding its uniquenesses and its mixed cases altogether, and supposing it to be an assembly of poietic, kinetic, dull, and base people. In many respects it behaves as if it were that. The State, dealing as it does only with non-individualised affairs, is not only justified in disregarding, but is bound to disregard, a man's special distinction, and to provide for him on the strength of his prevalent aspect as being on the whole poietic, kinetic, or what not. In a world of hasty judgments and carping criticism, it cannot be repeated too often that the fundamental ideas of a modern Utopia imply everywhere and in everything, margins and elasticities, a certain universal compensatory looseness of play.

This is obviously a very basic classification, and no one envisioning a perfect society has ever thought it could be applied to individuals in such a strict manner that you could just say, this person is “creative,” and that person is “ordinary.” In reality, these traits mix and differ in countless ways. It's not a classification for Truth but one meant for a purpose. When looking at humanity as a collection of unique individuals, it’s often more practical to overlook those unique characteristics and see it as a group of creative, active, dull, and ordinary people. In many ways, it behaves as if it were just that. The government, which only addresses non-individual issues, is both justified in ignoring and expected to ignore a person’s unique qualities and to support them based on their overall characteristics as being mostly creative, active, or something else. In a world filled with quick judgments and harsh criticisms, it’s worth emphasizing that the core concepts of a modern ideal society involve flexibility and adaptability, allowing for a kind of universal looseness in interactions.

§ 3

Now these Utopian statesmen who founded the World State put the problem of social organisation in the following fashion:—To contrive a revolutionary movement that shall absorb all existing governments and fuse them with itself, and that must be rapidly progressive and adaptable, and yet coherent, persistent, powerful, and efficient.

Now these Utopian leaders who established the World State framed the issue of social organization like this:—to create a revolutionary movement that would take over all existing governments and merge them into one, which needs to be quickly evolving and flexible, yet still coherent, consistent, strong, and effective.

The problem of combining progress with political stability had never been accomplished in Utopia before that time, any more than it has been accomplished on earth. Just as on earth, Utopian history was a succession of powers rising and falling in an alternation of efficient conservative with unstable liberal States. Just as on earth, so in Utopia, the kinetic type of men had displayed a more or less unintentional antagonism to the poietic. The general life-history of a State had been the same on either planet. First, through poietic activities, the idea of a community has developed, and the State has shaped itself; poietic men have arisen first in this department of national life, and then that, and have given place to kinetic men of a high type—for it seems to be in their nature that poietic men should be mutually repulsive, and not succeed and develop one another consecutively—and a period of expansion and vigour has set in. The general poietic activity has declined with the development of an efficient and settled social and political organisation; the statesman has given way to the politician who has incorporated the wisdom of the statesman with his own energy, the original genius in arts, letters, science, and every department of activity to the cultivated and scholarly man. The kinetic man of wide range, who has assimilated his poietic predecessor, succeeds with far more readiness than his poietic contemporary in almost every human activity. The latter is by his very nature undisciplined and experimental, and is positively hampered by precedents and good order. With this substitution of the efficient for the creative type, the State ceases to grow, first in this department of activity, and then in that, and so long as its conditions remain the same it remains orderly and efficient. But it has lost its power of initiative and change; its power of adaptation is gone, and with that secular change of conditions which is the law of life, stresses must arise within and without, and bring at last either through revolution or through defeat the release of fresh poietic power. The process, of course, is not in its entirety simple; it may be masked by the fact that one department of activity may be in its poietic stage, while another is in a phase of realisation. In the United States of America, for example, during the nineteenth century, there was great poietic activity in industrial organisation, and none whatever in political philosophy; but a careful analysis of the history of any period will show the rhythm almost invariably present, and the initial problem before the Utopian philosopher, therefore, was whether this was an inevitable alternation, whether human progress was necessarily a series of developments, collapses, and fresh beginnings, after an interval of disorder, unrest, and often great unhappiness, or whether it was possible to maintain a secure, happy, and progressive State beside an unbroken flow of poietic activity.

The challenge of balancing progress with political stability had never been achieved in Utopia before that time, just as it hasn’t been achieved on Earth. Like on Earth, Utopian history was characterized by a cycle of powers rising and falling, alternating between effective conservative states and unstable liberal ones. In both places, the more dynamic individuals often showed an unintentional conflict with the creative types. The general life cycle of a state was similar on both planets. Initially, through creative efforts, the concept of a community developed, and the state formed; creative individuals emerged first in various areas of national life, only to be replaced by highly active individuals—indicating that creative types tend to repel each other and don’t build upon one another effectively. This led to periods of growth and vitality. Over time, creative activity declined as a solid and efficient social and political structure took shape; the statesman was overshadowed by the politician, who combined the statesman's wisdom with his own drive, while the original innovators in arts, literature, science, and other fields were replaced by more cultivated and scholarly people. The highly active individual, who has absorbed the insights of his creative predecessors, tends to excel far more than his creative contemporaries in nearly every human endeavor. The latter, by nature, is undisciplined and experimental, often hindered by established precedents and order. With the shift from creative to efficient types, the state stops growing—first in one area of activity, then another—and as long as its conditions stay the same, it remains orderly and efficient. However, it loses its ability to innovate and adapt; when it can no longer adjust to the ongoing changes that are a part of life, tensions arise both internally and externally, leading to either revolution or defeat, which ultimately triggers the emergence of new creative potential. Of course, this process isn’t entirely straightforward; it can be obscured by the fact that one area of activity might be in its creative phase while another is in a phase of implementation. For example, in the United States during the nineteenth century, there was significant creative activity in industrial organization, but none in political philosophy. However, a careful examination of the history of any period will reveal a nearly constant rhythm, and the primary question for the Utopian philosopher was whether this cycle was inevitable—whether human progress must always consist of developments followed by collapses and fresh starts, marked by periods of disorder, unrest, and often significant unhappiness—or if it was possible to maintain a secure, happy, and progressive state alongside a continuous stream of creative activity.

Clearly they decided upon the second alternative. If, indeed, I am listening to my Utopian self, then they not only decided the problem could be solved, but they solved it.

Clearly, they chose the second option. If I’m really tuning into my idealistic self, then they didn’t just think the problem could be solved; they actually solved it.

He tells me how they solved it.

He tells me how they figured it out.

A modern Utopia differs from all the older Utopias in its recognition of the need of poietic activities—one sees this new consideration creeping into thought for the first time in the phrasing of Comte's insistence that “spiritual” must precede political reconstruction, and in his admission of the necessity of recurrent books and poems about Utopias—and at first this recognition appears to admit only an added complication to a problem already unmanageably complex. Comte's separation of the activities of a State into the spiritual and material does, to a certain extent, anticipate this opposition of poietic and kinetic, but the intimate texture of his mind was dull and hard, the conception slipped from him again, and his suppression of literary activities, and his imposition of a rule of life upon the poietic types, who are least able to sustain it, mark how deeply he went under. To a large extent he followed the older Utopists in assuming that the philosophical and constructive problem could be done once for all, and he worked the results out simply under an organised kinetic government. But what seems to be merely an addition to the difficulty may in the end turn out to be a simplification, just as the introduction of a fresh term to an intricate irreducible mathematical expression will at times bring it to unity.

A modern Utopia is different from all the older Utopias in its recognition of the need for creative activities—this new idea first appears in Comte's insistence that “spiritual” must come before political rebuilding, and in his acknowledgment of the need for ongoing books and poems about Utopias. Initially, this recognition seems to just complicate a problem that's already very complex. Comte’s distinction between the spiritual and material activities of a State somewhat foreshadows the contrast between creative and kinetic activities, but his mindset was blunt and rigid, leading him to lose sight of this concept again. His rejection of literary pursuits and the strict rules he imposed on creative people, who are the least capable of handling them, show how far he fell short. He largely followed the older Utopists in believing that the philosophical and constructive problems could be resolved all at once, working out the results simply under an organized kinetic government. However, what seems to just add to the complexity could ultimately simplify things, just as introducing a new term into a complicated, irreducible mathematical equation can sometimes bring it to a simple solution.

Now philosophers after my Utopian pattern, who find the ultimate significance in life in individuality, novelty and the undefined, would not only regard the poietic element as the most important in human society, but would perceive quite clearly the impossibility of its organisation. This, indeed, is simply the application to the moral and intellectual fabric of the principles already applied in discussing the State control of reproduction (in Chapter the Sixth, § 2). But just as in the case of births it was possible for the State to frame limiting conditions within which individuality plays more freely than in the void, so the founders of this modern Utopia believed it possible to define conditions under which every individual born with poietic gifts should be enabled and encouraged to give them a full development, in art, philosophy, invention, or discovery. Certain general conditions presented themselves as obviously reasonable:—to give every citizen as good an education as he or she could acquire, for example; to so frame it that the directed educational process would never at any period occupy the whole available time of the learner, but would provide throughout a marginal free leisure with opportunities for developing idiosyncrasies, and to ensure by the expedient of a minimum wage for a specified amount of work, that leisure and opportunity did not cease throughout life.

Now, philosophers following my Utopian model, who find the ultimate significance in life in individuality, novelty, and the undefined, would not only see the creative element as the most important in human society but also clearly understand the impossibility of organizing it. This is essentially applying the principles already discussed regarding state control of reproduction (in Chapter the Sixth, § 2) to the moral and intellectual fabric. However, just like it was possible for the state to create limiting conditions for births that allowed individuality to flourish more freely than in a vacuum, the founders of this modern Utopia believed it was possible to establish conditions under which every individual born with creative talents would be enabled and encouraged to fully develop them in art, philosophy, invention, or discovery. Certain general conditions appeared obviously reasonable: for example, to provide every citizen with the best education they could receive; to ensure that the directed educational process would never occupy all of the learner's available time but would include plenty of free time for developing personal interests; and to guarantee, through a minimum wage for a specified amount of work, that leisure and opportunities to explore passions continued throughout life.

But, in addition to thus making poietic activities universally possible, the founders of this modern Utopia sought to supply incentives, which was an altogether more difficult research, a problem in its nature irresolvably complex, and admitting of no systematic solution. But my double told me of a great variety of devices by which poietic men and women were given honour and enlarged freedoms, so soon as they produced an earnest of their quality, and he explained to me how great an ambition they might entertain.

But, besides making creative activities accessible to everyone, the founders of this modern Utopia aimed to provide incentives, which was a much more challenging task—an inherently complex problem without a straightforward solution. However, my double shared with me numerous ways that creative men and women were granted honor and increased freedoms as soon as they demonstrated their talents, and he explained the high ambitions they could aspire to.

There were great systems of laboratories attached to every municipal force station at which research could be conducted under the most favourable conditions, and every mine, and, indeed, almost every great industrial establishment, was saddled under its lease with similar obligations. So much for poietic ability and research in physical science. The World State tried the claims of every living contributor to any materially valuable invention, and paid or charged a royalty on its use that went partly to him personally, and partly to the research institution that had produced him. In the matter of literature and the philosophical and sociological sciences, every higher educational establishment carried its studentships, its fellowships, its occasional lectureships, and to produce a poem, a novel, a speculative work of force or merit, was to become the object of a generous competition between rival Universities. In Utopia, any author has the option either of publishing his works through the public bookseller as a private speculation, or, if he is of sufficient merit, of accepting a University endowment and conceding his copyright to the University press. All sorts of grants in the hands of committees of the most varied constitution, supplemented these academic resources, and ensured that no possible contributor to the wide flow of the Utopian mind slipped into neglect. Apart from those who engaged mainly in teaching and administration, my double told me that the world-wide House of Saloman [Footnote: The New Atlantis.] thus created sustained over a million men. For all the rarity of large fortunes, therefore, no original man with the desire and capacity for material or mental experiments went long without resources and the stimulus of attention, criticism, and rivalry.

There were extensive labs connected to every municipal police station where research could be conducted under the best conditions, and every mine, and actually nearly every major industrial facility, was obligated to fulfill similar requirements as part of its lease. This highlighted the importance of creative abilities and research in physical science. The World State evaluated the contributions of every living inventor towards valuable inventions, compensating or charging a royalty for their use, which partly went to the inventor and partly to the research institution that developed them. Regarding literature and the philosophical and sociological sciences, every higher education institution offered scholarships, fellowships, and occasional lectureships, and creating a poem, novel, or significant speculative work became a competitive goal among rival universities. In Utopia, authors could either publish their works through a public bookseller as private ventures or, if they were talented enough, accept a university grant and give their copyright to the university press. Numerous grants managed by committees of various types supplemented these academic resources, ensuring that no potential contributor to the expansive flow of Utopian thought fell into obscurity. Besides those primarily involved in teaching and administration, my counterpart told me that the global House of Saloman [Footnote: The New Atlantis.] supported over a million people. Therefore, despite the rarity of significant fortunes, no original thinker with the desire and ability for material or intellectual exploration went without resources and the encouragement of attention, criticism, and competition for long.

“And finally,” said my double, “our Rules ensure a considerable understanding of the importance of poietic activities in the majority of the samurai, in whose hands as a class all the real power of the world resides.”

“And finally,” said my double, “our Rules guarantee a deep understanding of the significance of creative activities among most of the samurai, who as a group hold all the real power in the world.”

“Ah!” said I, “and now we come to the thing that interests me most. For it is quite clear, in my mind, that these samurai form the real body of the State. All this time that I have spent going to and fro in this planet, it has been growing upon me that this order of men and women, wearing such a uniform as you wear, and with faces strengthened by discipline and touched with devotion, is the Utopian reality; but that for them, the whole fabric of these fair appearances would crumble and tarnish, shrink and shrivel, until at last, back I should be amidst the grime and disorders of the life of earth. Tell me about these samurai, who remind me of Plato's guardians, who look like Knights Templars, who bear a name that recalls the swordsmen of Japan ... and whose uniform you yourself are wearing. What are they? Are they an hereditary caste, a specially educated order, an elected class? For, certainly, this world turns upon them as a door upon its hinges.”

“Ah!” I said, “and now we get to the thing that interests me the most. It’s clear to me that these samurai are the foundation of the State. Throughout my time on this planet, I've come to realize that this group of men and women, wearing uniforms like yours, with faces shaped by discipline and touched by devotion, represents a Utopian reality. But for them, the entire structure of these beautiful appearances would fall apart, tarnish, shrink, and wither, until I would find myself back in the grime and chaos of earthly life. Tell me about these samurai, who remind me of Plato's guardians, who resemble Knights Templars, who have a name that brings to mind the swordsmen of Japan... and whose uniform you are wearing. What are they? Are they an hereditary class, a specially trained group, or an elected class? Because this world definitely revolves around them like a door on its hinges.”

§ 4

“I follow the Common Rule, as many men do,” said my double, answering my allusion to his uniform almost apologetically. “But my own work is, in its nature, poietic; there is much dissatisfaction with our isolation of criminals upon islands, and I am analysing the psychology of prison officials and criminals in general with a view to some better scheme. I am supposed to be ingenious with expedients in this direction. Typically, the samurai are engaged in administrative work. Practically the whole of the responsible rule of the world is in their hands; all our head teachers and disciplinary heads of colleges, our judges, barristers, employers of labour beyond a certain limit, practising medical men, legislators, must be samurai, and all the executive committees, and so forth, that play so large a part in our affairs are drawn by lot exclusively from them. The order is not hereditary—we know just enough of biology and the uncertainties of inheritance to know how silly that would be—and it does not require an early consecration or novitiate or ceremonies and initiations of that sort. The samurai are, in fact, volunteers. Any intelligent adult in a reasonably healthy and efficient state may, at any age after five-and-twenty, become one of the samurai, and take a hand in the universal control.”

“I follow the Common Rule, like many men do,” my double replied, almost apologetically referencing his uniform. “But my work is creative in nature; there’s a lot of dissatisfaction with isolating criminals on islands, and I'm studying the psychology of prison officials and criminals in general to come up with a better plan. I’m known for being resourceful with solutions in this area. Typically, the samurai handle administrative tasks. Almost all the responsible leadership in the world is in their hands; all our chief educators, heads of colleges, judges, barristers, employers of labor over a certain threshold, practicing doctors, and legislators must be samurai, and all the executive committees that play a major role in our affairs are selected exclusively from them. The order isn’t hereditary—we know enough about biology and the uncertainties of inheritance to understand how absurd that would be—and it doesn’t require any early initiation or ceremonies. The samurai are actually volunteers. Any intelligent adult in good health and capable condition can become one of the samurai at any age after twenty-five and participate in universal control.”

“Provided he follows the Rule.”

"Provided he follows the rules."

“Precisely—provided he follows the Rule.”

“Exactly—if he follows the Rule.”

“I have heard the phrase, ‘voluntary nobility.’”

“I’ve heard the term ‘voluntary nobility.’”

“That was the idea of our Founders. They made a noble and privileged order—open to the whole world. No one could complain of an unjust exclusion, for the only thing that could exclude from the order was unwillingness or inability to follow the Rule.”

“That was the idea of our Founders. They created a noble and privileged organization—open to everyone. No one could complain about unfair exclusion, because the only thing that could keep someone out of the organization was their unwillingness or inability to follow the rules.”

“But the Rule might easily have been made exclusive of special lineages and races.”

“But the Rule could have easily excluded specific lineages and races.”

“That wasn't their intention. The Rule was planned to exclude the dull, to be unattractive to the base, and to direct and co-ordinate all sound citizens of good intent.”

“That wasn't their intention. The Rule was designed to leave out the uninspired, to be unappealing to the unworthy, and to guide and organize all decent citizens with good intentions.”

“And it has succeeded?”

"Has it succeeded?"

“As well as anything finite can. Life is still imperfect, still a thick felt of dissatisfactions and perplexing problems, but most certainly the quality of all its problems has been raised, and there has been no war, no grinding poverty, not half the disease, and an enormous increase of the order, beauty, and resources of life since the samurai, who began as a private aggressive cult, won their way to the rule of the world.”

“As well as anything limited can. Life is still imperfect, still a heavy blanket of disappointments and confusing problems, but the quality of all its issues has definitely improved, and there’s been no war, no extreme poverty, not as much disease, and a huge increase in the order, beauty, and resources of life since the samurai, who started as a private aggressive group, gained control of the world.”

“I would like to have that history,” I said. “I expect there was fighting?” He nodded. “But first—tell me about the Rule.”

“I want to know that history,” I said. “I assume there was fighting?” He nodded. “But first—tell me about the Rule.”

“The Rule aims to exclude the dull and base altogether, to discipline the impulses and emotions, to develop a moral habit and sustain a man in periods of stress, fatigue, and temptation, to produce the maximum co-operation of all men of good intent, and, in fact, to keep all the samurai in a state of moral and bodily health and efficiency. It does as much of this as well as it can, but, of course, like all general propositions, it does not do it in any case with absolute precision. On the whole, it is so good that most men who, like myself, are doing poietic work, and who would be just as well off without obedience, find a satisfaction in adhesion. At first, in the militant days, it was a trifle hard and uncompromising; it had rather too strong an appeal to the moral prig and harshly righteous man, but it has undergone, and still undergoes, revision and expansion, and every year it becomes a little better adapted to the need of a general rule of life that all men may try to follow. We have now a whole literature, with many very fine things in it, written about the Rule.”

“The Rule aims to completely eliminate the dull and base, to control impulses and emotions, to build a moral habit, and to support a person during times of stress, fatigue, and temptation. It seeks to maximize the cooperation among all people of good intent and, in effect, to keep all the samurai in a state of moral and physical health and efficiency. It accomplishes this as well as it can, but, like all general principles, it doesn’t do so with absolute precision in every case. Overall, it’s beneficial enough that most people, like myself, who are engaged in creative work and could manage just fine without following orders, still find satisfaction in adhering to it. Initially, during the militant days, it was somewhat rigid and uncompromising; it appealed a bit too much to the morally strict and self-righteous individual. However, it has undergone and continues to experience revision and expansion, becoming a bit better suited each year to serve as a general guideline for life that everyone can try to follow. We now have an entire body of literature, with many valuable insights, written about the Rule.”

He glanced at a little book on his desk, took it up as if to show it me, then put it down again.

He looked at a small book on his desk, picked it up as if to show it to me, then put it back down again.

“The Rule consists of three parts; there is the list of things that qualify, the list of things that must not be done, and the list of things that must be done. Qualification exacts a little exertion, as evidence of good faith, and it is designed to weed out the duller dull and many of the base. Our schooling period ends now about fourteen, and a small number of boys and girls—about three per cent.—are set aside then as unteachable, as, in fact, nearly idiotic; the rest go on to a college or upper school.”

“The Rule has three parts: a list of things that qualify, a list of things that can’t be done, and a list of things that must be done. Qualification requires a bit of effort as proof of good faith, and it's meant to filter out the less capable and many of the unworthy. Our schooling wraps up around fourteen, and a small number of boys and girls—about three percent—are considered unteachable, almost idiotic; the rest move on to college or high school.”

“All your population?”

"Is this all your population?"

“With that exception.”

"Except for that."

“Free?”

"At no cost?"

“Of course. And they pass out of college at eighteen. There are several different college courses, but one or other must be followed and a satisfactory examination passed at the end—perhaps ten per cent. fail—and the Rule requires that the candidate for the samurai must have passed.”

“Of course. And they graduate from college at eighteen. There are various college courses, but one must be chosen and a satisfactory exam passed at the end—maybe ten percent fail—and the rule states that the candidate for the samurai must have passed.”

“But a very good man is sometimes an idle schoolboy.”

“But a really good man can sometimes be a lazy schoolboy.”

“We admit that. And so anyone who has failed to pass the college leaving examination may at any time in later life sit for it again—and again and again. Certain carefully specified things excuse it altogether.”

“We acknowledge that. So anyone who didn’t pass the college leaving examination can take it again at any point in their life—and keep trying as many times as needed. There are specific exceptions that completely excuse this.”

“That makes it fair. But aren't there people who cannot pass examinations?”

“That makes it fair. But aren’t there people who can’t pass exams?”

“People of nervous instability―”

"Nervous people―"

“But they may be people of great though irregular poietic gifts.”

“But they might be people with amazing but unconventional creative talents.”

“Exactly. That is quite possible. But we don't want that sort of people among our samurai. Passing an examination is a proof of a certain steadiness of purpose, a certain self-control and submission―”

“Exactly. That is definitely possible. But we don’t want that kind of people among our samurai. Passing an exam shows a certain level of determination, self-control, and discipline―”

“Of a certain ‘ordinariness.’”

"Of a certain 'everydayness.'"

“Exactly what is wanted.”

"Exactly what is needed."

“Of course, those others can follow other careers.”

“Of course, those people can pursue different careers.”

“Yes. That's what we want them to do. And, besides these two educational qualifications, there are two others of a similar kind of more debateable value. One is practically not in operation now. Our Founders put it that a candidate for the samurai must possess what they called a Technique, and, as it operated in the beginning, he had to hold the qualification for a doctor, for a lawyer, for a military officer, or an engineer, or teacher, or have painted acceptable pictures, or written a book, or something of the sort. He had, in fact, as people say, to ‘be something,’ or to have ‘done something.’ It was a regulation of vague intention even in the beginning, and it became catholic to the pitch of absurdity. To play a violin skilfully has been accepted as sufficient for this qualification. There may have been a reason in the past for this provision; in those days there were many daughters of prosperous parents—and even some sons—who did nothing whatever but idle uninterestingly in the world, and the organisation might have suffered by their invasion, but that reason has gone now, and the requirement remains a merely ceremonial requirement. But, on the other hand, another has developed. Our Founders made a collection of several volumes, which they called, collectively, the Book of the Samurai, a compilation of articles and extracts, poems and prose pieces, which were supposed to embody the idea of the order. It was to play the part for the samurai that the Bible did for the ancient Hebrews. To tell you the truth, the stuff was of very unequal merit; there was a lot of very second-rate rhetoric, and some nearly namby-pamby verse. There was also included some very obscure verse and prose that had the trick of seeming wise. But for all such defects, much of the Book, from the very beginning, was splendid and inspiring matter. From that time to this, the Book of the Samurai has been under revision, much has been added, much rejected, and some deliberately rewritten. Now, there is hardly anything in it that is not beautiful and perfect in form. The whole range of noble emotions finds expression there, and all the guiding ideas of our Modern State. We have recently admitted some terse criticism of its contents by a man named Henley.”

“Yes. That's what we want them to do. Besides these two educational qualifications, there are two more of a similar kind that are open to debate. One is almost not in use anymore. Our Founders stated that a candidate for the samurai must possess what they called a Technique. In the beginning, this meant that he had to qualify as a doctor, lawyer, military officer, engineer, or teacher, or have painted recognized artwork, written a book, or something similar. Essentially, he had to ‘be someone’ or have ‘done something.’ It was a regulation with vague intentions from the start and became so broad that it was almost ridiculous. Playing the violin skillfully has even been accepted as sufficient for this qualification. There may have been a reason for this rule in the past; back then, there were many daughters of wealthy parents—and even some sons—who did nothing but waste time in the world, and the organization could have suffered from their presence, but that reason is no longer relevant, and the requirement has become merely ceremonial. However, another requirement has emerged. Our Founders created a collection of several volumes, collectively called the Book of the Samurai, which is a compilation of articles, extracts, poems, and prose intended to embody the idea of the order. It was meant to serve the samurai as the Bible did for the ancient Hebrews. Honestly, the material varied greatly in quality; there was a lot of mediocre rhetoric and some nearly sentimental verse. It also contained some very obscure verse and prose that seemed wise. But despite these flaws, much of the Book, from the start, has been splendid and inspiring. Since then, the Book of the Samurai has been revised; much has been added, much discarded, and some deliberately rewritten. Now, hardly anything in it isn’t beautiful and perfectly crafted. The full range of noble emotions is expressed there, along with all the guiding ideas of our Modern State. Recently, we have included some terse criticism of its contents by a man named Henley.”

“Old Henley!”

"Old Henley!"

“A man who died a little time ago.”

“A man who just died.”

“I knew that man on earth. And he was in Utopia, too! He was a great red-faced man, with fiery hair, a noisy, intolerant maker of enemies, with a tender heart—and he was one of the samurai?”

“I knew that man on earth. And he was in Utopia, too! He was a big red-faced guy, with fiery hair, a loud, intolerant person who made enemies easily, but had a tender heart—and he was one of the samurai?”

“He defied the Rules.”

"He broke the rules."

“He was a great man with wine. He wrote like wine; in our world he wrote wine; red wine with the light shining through.”

“He was an amazing man with wine. He wrote with the richness of wine; in our world, he expressed wine; red wine with the light shining through.”

“He was on the Committee that revised our Canon. For the revising and bracing of our Canon is work for poietic as well as kinetic men. You knew him in your world?”

“He was on the Committee that updated our Canon. Updating and strengthening our Canon is a task for both creative and active individuals. Did you know him in your world?”

“I wish I had. But I have seen him. On earth he wrote a thing ... it would run—

“I wish I had. But I have seen him. On earth he wrote something... it would be a hit—

“Out of the night that covers me,
  Black as the pit from pole to pole,
I thank whatever Gods may be,
  For my unconquerable soul....”
“From the darkness that surrounds me,
  As dark as the abyss from one side to the other,
I’m grateful to whatever Gods may exist,
  For my unbreakable spirit....”

“We have that here. All good earthly things are in Utopia also. We put that in the Canon almost as soon as he died,” said my double.

“We have that here. All good earthly things are in Utopia too. We included that in the Canon almost right after he died,” said my double.

§ 5

“We have now a double Canon, a very fine First Canon, and a Second Canon of work by living men and work of inferior quality, and a satisfactory knowledge of both of these is the fourth intellectual qualification for the samurai.”

“We now have a double Canon, a great First Canon, and a Second Canon of work by contemporary authors and work of lesser quality, and a solid understanding of both of these is the fourth intellectual qualification for the samurai.”

“It must keep a sort of uniformity in your tone of thought.”

“It should maintain a consistent tone in your way of thinking.”

“The Canon pervades our whole world. As a matter of fact, very much of it is read and learnt in the schools.... Next to the intellectual qualification comes the physical, the man must be in sound health, free from certain foul, avoidable, and demoralising diseases, and in good training. We reject men who are fat, or thin and flabby, or whose nerves are shaky—we refer them back to training. And finally the man or woman must be fully adult.”

“The Canon is everywhere in our world. In fact, a lot of it is read and studied in schools. Next to intellectual qualifications, physical health is also important; a person must be in good health, free from certain preventable and harmful diseases, and in good shape. We turn away individuals who are overweight, underweight and weak, or who have shaky nerves—we send them back to training. And finally, the person must be fully grown.”

“Twenty-one? But you said twenty-five!”

"Twenty-one? But you said 25!"

“The age has varied. At first it was twenty-five or over; then the minimum became twenty-five for men and twenty-one for women. Now there is a feeling that it ought to be raised. We don't want to take advantage of mere boy and girl emotions—men of my way of thinking, at any rate, don't—we want to get our samurai with experiences, with a settled mature conviction. Our hygiene and regimen are rapidly pushing back old age and death, and keeping men hale and hearty to eighty and more. There's no need to hurry the young. Let them have a chance of wine, love, and song; let them feel the bite of full-bodied desire, and know what devils they have to reckon with.”

“The age has changed. At first, it was twenty-five or older; then the minimum became twenty-five for men and twenty-one for women. Now there's a belief that it should be raised. We don't want to take advantage of just youthful emotions—men who think like me, at least, don’t—we want our samurai to have experiences, with settled mature convictions. Our health practices are quickly pushing back old age and death, keeping men strong and healthy to eighty and beyond. There's no need to rush the young. Let them enjoy wine, love, and music; let them experience deep desire and understand the challenges they have to face.”

“But there is a certain fine sort of youth that knows the desirability of the better things at nineteen.”

“But there is a certain kind of young person who understands the value of better things at nineteen.”

“They may keep the Rule at any time—without its privileges. But a man who breaks the Rule after his adult adhesion at five-and-twenty is no more in the samurai for ever. Before that age he is free to break it and repent.”

“They can follow the Rule anytime—minus its privileges. But a man who breaks the Rule after he fully commits at twenty-five is no longer a samurai forever. Before that age, he can break it and still repent.”

“And now, what is forbidden?”

“And now, what’s off-limits?”

“We forbid a good deal. Many small pleasures do no great harm, but we think it well to forbid them, none the less, so that we can weed out the self-indulgent. We think that a constant resistance to little seductions is good for a man's quality. At any rate, it shows that a man is prepared to pay something for his honour and privileges. We prescribe a regimen of food, forbid tobacco, wine, or any alcoholic drink, all narcotic drugs―”

“We prohibit a lot. Many little pleasures don’t cause much harm, but we still think it’s best to ban them so we can eliminate self-indulgence. We believe that consistently resisting small temptations is good for a person’s character. At the very least, it shows that a person is willing to sacrifice something for their dignity and rights. We set strict guidelines for food, ban tobacco, wine, any alcoholic drinks, and all narcotic drugs—”

“Meat?”

"Meat?"

“In all the round world of Utopia there is no meat. There used to be. But now we cannot stand the thought of slaughter-houses. And, in a population that is all educated, and at about the same level of physical refinement, it is practically impossible to find anyone who will hew a dead ox or pig. We never settled the hygienic question of meat-eating at all. This other aspect decided us. I can still remember, as a boy, the rejoicings over the closing of the last slaughter-house.”

“In all of Utopia, there’s no meat. There used to be, but now we can’t bear the thought of slaughterhouses. In a community that is fully educated and similarly refined, it's nearly impossible to find anyone willing to butcher a dead cow or pig. We never really resolved the hygiene issues surrounding meat-eating. This other factor is what influenced our decision. I can still recall celebrating as a kid when the last slaughterhouse closed.”

“You eat fish.”

"You eat seafood."

“It isn't a matter of logic. In our barbaric past horrible flayed carcases of brutes dripping blood, were hung for sale in the public streets.” He shrugged his shoulders.

“It’s not about logic. In our savage past, horrible, skinned carcasses of beasts dripping blood were displayed for sale in the public streets.” He shrugged his shoulders.

“They do that still in London—in my world,” I said.

“They still do that in London—in my world,” I said.

He looked again at my laxer, coarser face, and did not say whatever thought had passed across his mind.

He looked again at my rougher, coarser face, and didn’t say anything about whatever thought had crossed his mind.

“Originally the samurai were forbidden usury, that is to say the lending of money at fixed rates of interest. They are still under that interdiction, but since our commercial code practically prevents usury altogether, and our law will not recognise contracts for interest upon private accommodation loans to unprosperous borrowers, it is now scarcely necessary. The idea of a man growing richer by mere inaction and at the expense of an impoverishing debtor, is profoundly distasteful to Utopian ideas, and our State insists pretty effectually now upon the participation of the lender in the borrower's risks. This, however, is only one part of a series of limitations of the same character. It is felt that to buy simply in order to sell again brings out many unsocial human qualities; it makes a man seek to enhance profits and falsify values, and so the samurai are forbidden to buy to sell on their own account or for any employer save the State, unless some process of manufacture changes the nature of the commodity (a mere change in bulk or packing does not suffice), and they are forbidden salesmanship and all its arts. Consequently they cannot be hotel-keepers, or hotel proprietors, or hotel shareholders, and a doctor—all practising doctors must be samurai—cannot sell drugs except as a public servant of the municipality or the State.”

“Originally, the samurai were not allowed to engage in usury, meaning they couldn't lend money at set interest rates. They still face this restriction, but since our commercial laws practically eliminate usury altogether, and because our legal system doesn't recognize contracts for interest on loans to struggling borrowers, it's now hardly needed. The notion of someone getting richer by doing nothing while taking advantage of a poor debtor is deeply unappealing to Utopian ideals, and our State now effectively requires lenders to share in the borrower's risks. However, this is just one part of a broader set of similar limitations. There's a belief that buying just to sell again brings out many negative human traits; it makes people try to boost profits and distort values, which is why samurai are prohibited from buying to resell for themselves or for anyone other than the State, unless a manufacturing process changes the nature of the item (a simple change in size or packaging does not count), and they are banned from salesmanship and all its practices. As a result, they cannot own or run hotels, and doctors—all practicing doctors must be samurai—cannot sell medications unless they are public servants of the municipality or the State.”

“That, of course, runs counter to all our current terrestrial ideas,” I said. “We are obsessed by the power of money. These rules will work out as a vow of moderate poverty, and if your samurai are an order of poor men―”

“That definitely goes against all our current earthly beliefs,” I said. “We’re obsessed with the power of money. These rules will end up being a commitment to simple living, and if your samurai are a group of poor men—”

“They need not be. Samurai who have invented, organised, and developed new industries, have become rich men, and many men who have grown rich by brilliant and original trading have subsequently become samurai.”

“They don't have to be. Samurai who have invented, organized, and developed new industries have become wealthy, and many individuals who became rich through innovative and original trading have later become samurai.”

“But these are exceptional cases. The bulk of your money-making business must be confined to men who are not samurai. You must have a class of rich, powerful outsiders―”

“But these are exceptional cases. The majority of your money-making business needs to focus on people who are not samurai. You need to have a group of wealthy, influential outsiders―”

Have we?”

“Have we?”

“I don't see the evidences of them.”

“I don't see the evidence of them.”

“As a matter of fact, we have such people! There are rich traders, men who have made discoveries in the economy of distribution, or who have called attention by intelligent, truthful advertisement to the possibilities of neglected commodities, for example.”

“As a matter of fact, we have people like that! There are wealthy traders, men who have made breakthroughs in distribution economics, or who have highlighted the potential of overlooked products through smart, honest advertising, for example.”

“But aren't they a power?”

“But aren't they powerful?”

“Why should they be?”

"Why would they be?"

“Wealth is power.”

“Money is power.”

I had to explain that phrase.

I had to explain that phrase.

He protested. “Wealth,” he said, “is no sort of power at all unless you make it one. If it is so in your world it is so by inadvertency. Wealth is a State-made thing, a convention, the most artificial of powers. You can, by subtle statesmanship, contrive what it shall buy and what it shall not. In your world it would seem you have made leisure, movement, any sort of freedom, life itself, purchaseable. The more fools you! A poor working man with you is a man in discomfort and fear. No wonder your rich have power. But here a reasonable leisure, a decent life, is to be had by every man on easier terms than by selling himself to the rich. And rich as men are here, there is no private fortune in the whole world that is more than a little thing beside the wealth of the State. The samurai control the State and the wealth of the State, and by their vows they may not avail themselves of any of the coarser pleasures wealth can still buy. Where, then, is the power of your wealthy man?”

He protested. “Wealth,” he said, “is not really power at all unless you make it one. If it is that way in your world, it’s just a mistake. Wealth is created by the government, a convention, the most artificial of powers. Through clever politics, you can dictate what it can buy and what it can’t. In your world, it seems you’ve made leisure, movement, any kind of freedom, even life itself, something you can buy. What fools you are! A poor worker among you is a person in discomfort and fear. It’s no surprise your rich have power. But here, a reasonable leisure and a decent life are available to every man without having to sell himself to the wealthy. And as rich as people are here, there’s no private fortune in the whole world that compares to the wealth of the State. The samurai control the State and its wealth, and by their vows, they cannot indulge in any of the coarser pleasures that wealth can still buy. So, where’s the power of your wealthy man?”

“But, then—where is the incentive―?”

“But, then—where's the incentive?”

“Oh! a man gets things for himself with wealth—no end of things. But little or no power over his fellows—unless they are exceptionally weak or self-indulgent persons.”

“Oh! a man gets whatever he wants with money—countless things. But he has little to no power over others—unless they are unusually weak or indulgent.”

I reflected. “What else may not the samurai do?”

I thought about it. “What else can't the samurai do?”

“Acting, singing, or reciting are forbidden them, though they may lecture authoritatively or debate. But professional mimicry is not only held to be undignified in a man or woman, but to weaken and corrupt the soul; the mind becomes foolishly dependent on applause, over-skilful in producing tawdry and momentary illusions of excellence; it is our experience that actors and actresses as a class are loud, ignoble, and insincere. If they have not such flamboyant qualities then they are tepid and ineffectual players. Nor may the samurai do personal services, except in the matter of medicine or surgery; they may not be barbers, for example, nor inn waiters, nor boot cleaners. But, nowadays, we have scarcely any barbers or boot cleaners; men do these things for themselves. Nor may a man under the Rule be any man's servant, pledged to do whatever he is told. He may neither be a servant nor keep one; he must shave and dress and serve himself, carry his own food from the helper's place to the table, redd his sleeping room, and leave it clean....”

“Acting, singing, or reciting are off-limits for them, though they can lecture authoritatively or debate. But professional mimicry is seen as undignified for both men and women, and it weakens and corrupts the soul; the mind becomes foolishly reliant on applause, overly skilled at creating cheap and fleeting illusions of excellence; we’ve found that actors and actresses tend to be loud, unrefined, and insincere. If they lack such flamboyant traits, they're often uninspired and ineffective performers. Furthermore, the samurai are not allowed to perform personal services, except for medicine or surgery; they can’t be barbers, inn waiters, or boot cleaners. Nowadays, though, there are hardly any barbers or boot cleaners; men do those things for themselves. A man under the Rule can't be anyone's servant, expected to do whatever he’s told. He can neither serve nor employ a servant; he must shave, dress, and tend to himself, carry his own food from the helper's area to the table, tidy his sleeping space, and keep it clean....”

“That is all easy enough in a world as ordered as yours. I suppose no samurai may bet?”

“That’s pretty easy in a world as organized as yours. I guess no samurai can place bets?”

“Absolutely not. He may insure his life and his old age for the better equipment of his children, or for certain other specified ends, but that is all his dealings with chance. And he is also forbidden to play games in public or to watch them being played. Certain dangerous and hardy sports and exercises are prescribed for him, but not competitive sports between man and man or side and side. That lesson was learnt long ago before the coming of the samurai. Gentlemen of honour, according to the old standards, rode horses, raced chariots, fought, and played competitive games of skill, and the dull, cowardly and base came in thousands to admire, and howl, and bet. The gentlemen of honour degenerated fast enough into a sort of athletic prostitute, with all the defects, all the vanity, trickery, and self-assertion of the common actor, and with even less intelligence. Our Founders made no peace with this organisation of public sports. They did not spend their lives to secure for all men and women on the earth freedom, health, and leisure, in order that they might waste lives in such folly.”

“Absolutely not. He can get life insurance and plan for his retirement to support his kids or for specific goals, but that’s the extent of his dealings with chance. He’s also not allowed to play games in public or watch them being played. There are certain tough sports and exercises he can do, but not competitive sports between individuals or teams. That lesson was learned long ago before the arrival of the samurai. Gentlemen of honor, according to the old standards, rode horses, raced chariots, fought, and played competitive skill games, while the dull, cowardly, and lowly came in droves to watch, cheer, and gamble. The gentlemen of honor quickly turned into a kind of athletic prostitute, with all the flaws, vanity, trickery, and self-importance of common actors, and even less intelligence. Our Founders did not make peace with this setup of public sports. They didn’t dedicate their lives to ensure freedom, health, and leisure for all men and women on earth just for them to waste their lives on such nonsense.”

“We have those abuses,” I said, “but some of our earthly games have a fine side. There is a game called cricket. It is a fine, generous game.”

“We have those abuses,” I said, “but some of our earthly games have a nice aspect. There is a game called cricket. It is a great, generous game.”

“Our boys play that, and men too. But it is thought rather puerile to give very much time to it; men should have graver interests. It was undignified and unpleasant for the samurai to play conspicuously ill, and impossible for them to play so constantly as to keep hand and eye in training against the man who was fool enough and cheap enough to become an expert. Cricket, tennis, fives, billiards―. You will find clubs and a class of men to play all these things in Utopia, but not the samurai. And they must play their games as games, not as displays; the price of a privacy for playing cricket, so that they could charge for admission, would be overwhelmingly high.... Negroes are often very clever at cricket. For a time, most of the samurai had their sword-play, but few do those exercises now, and until about fifty years ago they went out for military training, a fortnight in every year, marching long distances, sleeping in the open, carrying provisions, and sham fighting over unfamiliar ground dotted with disappearing targets. There was a curious inability in our world to realise that war was really over for good and all.”

“Our guys play that, and so do men. But it's considered pretty childish to spend too much time on it; men should have more serious interests. It was undignified and unpleasant for the samurai to play really badly, and impossible for them to play so often that they could keep their skills sharp against someone who was foolish and cheap enough to become an expert. Cricket, tennis, fives, billiards—You'll find clubs and a group of men playing all these things in Utopia, but not the samurai. And they must play their games for fun, not as performances; the cost of privacy for playing cricket, so they could charge for admission, would be incredibly high.... Black people are often very skilled at cricket. For a while, most of the samurai practiced their swordplay, but few do those exercises now, and until about fifty years ago, they participated in military training, two weeks every year, marching long distances, sleeping outdoors, carrying supplies, and engaging in mock battles over unfamiliar terrain with disappearing targets. There was a strange inability in our world to realize that war was truly over for good.”

“And now,” I said, “haven't we got very nearly to the end of your prohibitions? You have forbidden alcohol, drugs, smoking, betting, and usury, games, trade, servants. But isn't there a vow of Chastity?”

“And now,” I said, “haven't we almost reached the end of your restrictions? You've banned alcohol, drugs, smoking, gambling, usury, games, trade, and servants. But isn't there a vow of chastity?”

“That is the Rule for your earthly orders?”

"Is that the rule for your earthly commands?"

“Yes—except, if I remember rightly, for Plato's Guardians.”

“Yes—except, if I remember correctly, for Plato's Guardians.”

“There is a Rule of Chastity here—but not of Celibacy. We know quite clearly that civilisation is an artificial arrangement, and that all the physical and emotional instincts of man are too strong, and his natural instinct of restraint too weak, for him to live easily in the civilised State. Civilisation has developed far more rapidly than man has modified. Under the unnatural perfection of security, liberty and abundance our civilisation has attained, the normal untrained human being is disposed to excess in almost every direction; he tends to eat too much and too elaborately, to drink too much, to become lazy faster than his work can be reduced, to waste his interest upon displays, and to make love too much and too elaborately. He gets out of training, and concentrates upon egoistic or erotic broodings. The past history of our race is very largely a history of social collapses due to demoralisation by indulgences following security and abundance. In the time of our Founders the signs of a world-wide epoch of prosperity and relaxation were plentiful. Both sexes drifted towards sexual excesses, the men towards sentimental extravagances, imbecile devotions, and the complication and refinement of physical indulgences; the women towards those expansions and differentiations of feeling that find expression in music and costly and distinguished dress. Both sexes became unstable and promiscuous. The whole world seemed disposed to do exactly the same thing with its sexual interest as it had done with its appetite for food and drink—make the most of it.”

“There’s a Rule of Chastity here—but not a Rule of Celibacy. We clearly understand that civilization is an artificial setup, and that all of our physical and emotional instincts are too strong, while our natural instinct for self-restraint is too weak, for us to live comfortably in a civilized society. Civilization has progressed much faster than humanity has evolved. In the unnatural safety, freedom, and abundance our civilization has reached, the average untrained person tends to go overboard in almost every aspect; they tend to eat too much and too lavishly, drink too much, become lazy faster than their workload can decrease, waste their focus on superficial displays, and indulge in love too frequently and extravagantly. They lose their discipline and fixate on selfish or erotic thoughts. The previous history of our species is largely a record of social breakdowns caused by the moral decay resulting from indulgence after achieving security and abundance. During the time of our Founders, the signs of a worldwide era of prosperity and relaxation were everywhere. Both men and women drifted toward sexual excess; men toward sentimental extremes, foolish devotion, and the complex and elaborate enjoyment of physical pleasures; women toward emotional expressions found in music and expensive, elegant clothing. Both genders became unstable and promiscuous. The whole world seemed inclined to handle its sexual interests just as it did its appetite for food and drink—by maximizing it.”

He paused.

He took a break.

“Satiety came to help you,” I said.

"Feeling full came to help you," I said.

“Destruction may come before satiety. Our Founders organised motives from all sorts of sources, but I think the chief force to give men self-control is Pride. Pride may not be the noblest thing in the soul, but it is the best King there, for all that. They looked to it to keep a man clean and sound and sane. In this matter, as in all matters of natural desire, they held no appetite must be glutted, no appetite must have artificial whets, and also and equally that no appetite should be starved. A man must come from the table satisfied, but not replete. And, in the matter of love, a straight and clean desire for a clean and straight fellow-creature was our Founders' ideal. They enjoined marriage between equals as the samurai's duty to the race, and they framed directions of the precisest sort to prevent that uxorious inseparableness, that connubiality which will reduce a couple of people to something jointly less than either. That Canon is too long to tell you now. A man under the Rule who loves a woman who does not follow it, must either leave the samurai to marry her, or induce her to accept what is called the Woman's Rule, which, while it excepts her from the severer qualifications and disciplines, brings her regimen of life into a working harmony with his.”

“Destruction can happen before fulfillment. Our Founders gathered insights from all kinds of sources, but I believe the strongest force for self-control in men is Pride. Pride may not be the most virtuous trait, but it's the best ruler there is. They relied on it to keep a man clean, sound, and sane. In this area, just like in all areas of natural desire, they believed no appetite should be overindulged, no appetite should be artificially provoked, and equally that no appetite should be starved. A man should leave the table satisfied, but not stuffed. And when it comes to love, a straight and pure desire for a clean and decent partner was the ideal of our Founders. They promoted marriage between equals as the samurai's duty to the community, and they created detailed guidelines to prevent that clingy inseparability, that relationship dynamic which reduces a couple to something less than the sum of their parts. That code is too lengthy to explain now. A man under the Rule who loves a woman who doesn't follow it must either leave the samurai to marry her or convince her to accept what's known as the Woman's Rule, which, while it exempts her from the stricter qualifications and disciplines, aligns her way of life to work in harmony with his.”

“Suppose she breaks the Rule afterwards?”

"Imagine she breaks the rule later on?"

“He must leave either her or the order.”

“He has to choose between her or the order.”

“There is matter for a novel or so in that.”

“There’s enough material for a novel or two in that.”

“There has been matter for hundreds.”

“There has been material for hundreds.”

“Is the Woman's Rule a sumptuary law as well as a regimen? I mean—may she dress as she pleases?”

“Is the Woman's Rule a law about spending and personal conduct as well as a set of guidelines? I mean—can she dress however she wants?”

“Not a bit of it,” said my double. “Every woman who could command money used it, we found, to make underbred aggressions on other women. As men emerged to civilisation, women seemed going back to savagery—to paint and feathers. But the samurai, both men and women, and the women under the Lesser Rule also, all have a particular dress. No difference is made between women under either the Great or the Lesser Rule. You have seen the men's dress—always like this I wear. The women may wear the same, either with the hair cut short or plaited behind them, or they may have a high-waisted dress of very fine, soft woollen material, with their hair coiled up behind.”

“Not at all,” replied my double. “We discovered that every woman who had money used it to aggressively go after other women. As men advanced in civilization, it seemed like women were regressing into savagery—back to paint and feathers. But the samurai, both men and women, as well as the women under the Lesser Rule, all have a specific style of dress. There’s no distinction between women under either the Great or the Lesser Rule. You’ve seen the men’s attire—I wear it just like this. Women can wear the same, either with their hair cut short or styled in braids, or they might choose a high-waisted dress made of very fine, soft wool, with their hair styled in a bun at the back.”

“I have seen it,” I said. Indeed, nearly all the women had seemed to be wearing variants of that simple formula. “It seems to me a very beautiful dress. The other—I'm not used to. But I like it on girls and slender women.”

“I’ve seen it,” I said. In fact, almost all the women seemed to be wearing different versions of that simple design. “I think it’s a really beautiful dress. The other one—I'm not used to. But I like it on girls and slim women.”

I had a thought, and added, “Don't they sometimes, well—take a good deal of care, dressing their hair?”

I had a thought and added, “Don’t they sometimes, you know—take a lot of time to style their hair?”

My double laughed in my eyes. “They do,” he said.

My double laughed in my face. “They do,” he said.

“And the Rule?”

"And the rule?"

“The Rule is never fussy,” said my double, still smiling.

"The Rule is never picky," said my double, still smiling.

“We don't want women to cease to be beautiful, and consciously beautiful, if you like,” he added. “The more real beauty of form and face we have, the finer our world. But costly sexualised trappings―”

“We don’t want women to stop being beautiful, and intentionally beautiful, if you prefer,” he added. “The more genuine beauty of form and face we have, the better our world. But expensive, sexualized decorations—”

“I should have thought,” I said, “a class of women who traded on their sex would have arisen, women, I mean, who found an interest and an advantage in emphasising their individual womanly beauty. There is no law to prevent it. Surely they would tend to counteract the severity of costume the Rule dictates.”

“I should have thought,” I said, “that a group of women who used their looks to their advantage would have emerged, women who found a benefit in highlighting their unique beauty. There’s nothing stopping them. They would definitely help balance out the strict dress code the Rule demands.”

“There are such women. But for all that the Rule sets the key of everyday dress. If a woman is possessed by the passion for gorgeous raiment she usually satisfies it in her own private circle, or with rare occasional onslaughts upon the public eye. Her everyday mood and the disposition of most people is against being conspicuous abroad. And I should say there are little liberties under the Lesser Rule; a discreet use of fine needlework and embroidery, a wider choice of materials.”

"There are definitely women like that. Still, the Rule dictates everyday dress. If a woman has a passion for beautiful clothing, she often indulges it within her private circle or through rare public appearances. Most people prefer not to stand out in daily life. I’d say there are a few small freedoms under the Lesser Rule; a subtle use of fine sewing and embroidery, along with a broader selection of fabrics."

“You have no changing fashions?”

"Don't you have any trends?"

“None. For all that, are not our dresses as beautiful as yours?”

“None. Still, aren't our dresses just as beautiful as yours?”

“Our women's dresses are not beautiful at all,” I said, forced for a time towards the mysterious philosophy of dress. “Beauty? That isn't their concern.”

“Our women's dresses aren't beautiful at all,” I said, drawn for a moment into the mysterious world of fashion. “Beauty? That’s not their focus.”

“Then what are they after?”

“Then what do they want?”

“My dear man! What is all my world after?”

"My dear man! What is my entire world after?"

§ 6

I should come to our third talk with a great curiosity to hear of the last portion of the Rule, of the things that the samurai are obliged to do.

I should come to our third conversation with a strong curiosity to hear about the final part of the Rule, about what the samurai are required to do.

There would be many precise directions regarding his health, and rules that would aim at once at health and that constant exercise of will that makes life good. Save in specified exceptional circumstances, the samurai must bathe in cold water, and the men must shave every day; they have the precisest directions in such matters; the body must be in health, the skin and muscles and nerves in perfect tone, or the samurai must go to the doctors of the order, and give implicit obedience to the regimen prescribed. They must sleep alone at least four nights in five; and they must eat with and talk to anyone in their fellowship who cares for their conversation for an hour, at least, at the nearest club-house of the samurai once on three chosen days in every week. Moreover, they must read aloud from the Book of the Samurai for at least ten minutes every day. Every month they must buy and read faithfully through at least one book that has been published during the past five years, and the only intervention with private choice in that matter is the prescription of a certain minimum of length for the monthly book or books. But the full Rule in these minor compulsory matters is voluminous and detailed, and it abounds with alternatives. Its aim is rather to keep before the samurai by a number of sample duties, as it were, the need of, and some of the chief methods towards health of body and mind, rather than to provide a comprehensive rule, and to ensure the maintenance of a community of feeling and interests among the samurai through habit, intercourse, and a living contemporary literature. These minor obligations do not earmark more than an hour in the day. Yet they serve to break down isolations of sympathy, all sorts of physical and intellectual sluggishness and the development of unsocial preoccupations of many sorts.

There would be many specific guidelines about his health, along with rules aimed at promoting both well-being and the strong will that makes life enjoyable. Except in specific exceptional situations, the samurai must take cold baths, and the men must shave every day; they have very detailed instructions in these matters. The body needs to be healthy, with the skin, muscles, and nerves in top condition, or the samurai must go to their order's doctors and strictly follow the prescribed regimen. They need to sleep alone at least four nights each week, and they must spend at least an hour with anyone in their group who enjoys their conversation at the nearest samurai clubhouse at least three times a week. Additionally, they must read aloud from the Book of the Samurai for at least ten minutes every day. Every month, they should buy and thoroughly read at least one book published in the last five years, with the only personal choice being a requirement for a minimum length for the monthly book or books. However, the full set of rules regarding these minor obligations is extensive and detailed, filled with options. Its purpose is to keep the samurai aware of the necessity of, and methods for, maintaining both physical and mental health through a variety of sample duties, rather than providing a comprehensive rule, and to foster a sense of community and shared interests among the samurai through habits, interactions, and contemporary literature. These minor obligations take up no more than an hour each day. Still, they help break down feelings of isolation, combat various forms of physical and mental laziness, and prevent the development of unsocial fixations.

Women samurai who are married, my double told me, must bear children—if they are to remain married as well as in the order—before the second period for terminating a childless marriage is exhausted. I failed to ask for the precise figures from my double at the time, but I think it is beyond doubt that it is from samurai mothers of the Greater or Lesser Rule that a very large proportion of the future population of Utopia will be derived. There is one liberty accorded to women samurai which is refused to men, and that is to marry outside the Rule, and women married to men not under the Rule are also free to become samurai. Here, too, it will be manifest there is scope for novels and the drama of life. In practice, it seems that it is only men of great poietic distinction outside the Rule, or great commercial leaders, who have wives under it. The tendency of such unions is either to bring the husband under the Rule, or take the wife out of it. There can be no doubt that these marriage limitations tend to make the samurai something of an hereditary class. Their children, as a rule, become samurai. But it is not an exclusive caste; subject to the most reasonable qualifications, anyone who sees fit can enter it at any time, and so, unlike all other privileged castes the world has seen, it increases relatively to the total population, and may indeed at last assimilate almost the whole population of the earth.

Women samurai who are married, my counterpart told me, must have children—if they want to stay married and remain in the order—before the second period for ending a childless marriage runs out. I didn’t ask for the exact numbers from my counterpart at the time, but I believe it’s clear that a significant portion of the future population of Utopia will come from samurai mothers of the Greater or Lesser Rule. One freedom granted to women samurai that is denied to men is the ability to marry outside the Rule, and women married to men not under the Rule are also allowed to become samurai. Here, too, it’s evident that there’s potential for stories and the drama of life. In practice, it seems that only men of significant creative distinction outside the Rule, or major business leaders, have wives within it. These unions often lead to either the husband being brought under the Rule or the wife being taken out of it. There’s no doubt that these marriage restrictions make the samurai a somewhat hereditary class. Generally, their children become samurai. However, it's not an exclusive caste; with reasonable qualifications, anyone who wants can join at any time, and so, unlike all other privileged classes the world has known, it grows relative to the total population and might eventually include almost the entire global population.

§ 7

So much my double told me readily.

So much my double told me easily.

But now he came to the heart of all his explanations, to the will and motives at the centre that made men and women ready to undergo discipline, to renounce the richness and elaboration of the sensuous life, to master emotions and control impulses, to keep in the key of effort while they had abundance about them to rouse and satisfy all desires, and his exposition was more difficult.

But now he reached the core of all his explanations, exploring the will and motives at the center that drove men and women to accept discipline, to give up the richness and extravagance of a sensual life, to control their emotions and manage their impulses, and to remain focused on effort even when they had plenty around them to stimulate and fulfill all their desires, making his explanation more challenging.

He tried to make his religion clear to me.

He tried to explain his religion to me.

The leading principle of the Utopian religion is the repudiation of the doctrine of original sin; the Utopians hold that man, on the whole, is good. That is their cardinal belief. Man has pride and conscience, they hold, that you may refine by training as you refine his eye and ear; he has remorse and sorrow in his being, coming on the heels of all inconsequent enjoyments. How can one think of him as bad? He is religious; religion is as natural to him as lust and anger, less intense, indeed, but coming with a wide-sweeping inevitableness as peace comes after all tumults and noises. And in Utopia they understand this, or, at least, the samurai do, clearly. They accept Religion as they accept Thirst, as something inseparably in the mysterious rhythms of life. And just as thirst and pride and all desires may be perverted in an age of abundant opportunities, and men may be degraded and wasted by intemperance in drinking, by display, or by ambition, so too the nobler complex of desires that constitutes religion may be turned to evil by the dull, the base, and the careless. Slovenly indulgence in religious inclinations, a failure to think hard and discriminate as fairly as possible in religious matters, is just as alien to the men under the Rule as it would be to drink deeply because they were thirsty, eat until glutted, evade a bath because the day was chilly, or make love to any bright-eyed girl who chanced to look pretty in the dusk. Utopia, which is to have every type of character that one finds on earth, will have its temples and its priests, just as it will have its actresses and wine, but the samurai will be forbidden the religion of dramatically lit altars, organ music, and incense, as distinctly as they are forbidden the love of painted women, or the consolations of brandy. And to all the things that are less than religion and that seek to comprehend it, to cosmogonies and philosophies, to creeds and formulæ, to catechisms and easy explanations, the attitude of the samurai, the note of the Book of Samurai, will be distrust. These things, the samurai will say, are part of the indulgences that should come before a man submits himself to the Rule; they are like the early gratifications of young men, experiences to establish renunciation. The samurai will have emerged above these things.

The main belief of the Utopian religion is the rejection of original sin; the Utopians believe that people, overall, are good. This is their core belief. They think that people have pride and conscience, which can be refined through training just like improving one’s eyesight and hearing; they also believe that people experience remorse and sadness, which follow from all fleeting pleasures. How can anyone see them as bad? People are religious; faith comes naturally to them, just like desire and anger—less intense, perhaps, but as inevitable as peace that arrives after chaos and noise. In Utopia, they understand this, or at least the samurai do. They accept religion as naturally as thirst, seeing it as an inseparable part of life’s mysterious rhythms. Just as thirst, pride, and all desires can be twisted in times of plenty, leading individuals to excess in drinking, showiness, or ambition, the deeper desires that form religion can also be corrupted by those who are dull, base, or careless. A careless approach to religious inclinations, a lack of deep thought and fair consideration of spiritual matters, is as foreign to the men under the Rule as drinking too much simply because they are thirsty, overeating, skipping a bath on a chilly day, or flirting with any attractive girl who happens to catch their eye in the evening. Utopia will feature all types of characters just like those on earth; it will have its temples and priests, just as it will have its actresses and wine. However, the samurai will distinctly be prohibited from participating in the religion marked by dramatic altars, organ music, and incense, just as they are banned from the love of painted women or the comforts of brandy. Regarding all things less than true religion that aim to explain it—cosmogonies and philosophies, creeds and formulas, catechisms and simple explanations—the samurai will approach with skepticism. They will argue that these are indulgences that must be faced before one submits to the Rule; they resemble the early pleasures of young men, experiences meant to lead to renunciation. The samurai will rise above these distractions.

The theology of the Utopian rulers will be saturated with that same philosophy of uniqueness, that repudiation of anything beyond similarities and practical parallelisms, that saturates all their institutions. They will have analysed exhaustively those fallacies and assumptions that arise between the One and the Many, that have troubled philosophy since philosophy began. Just as they will have escaped that delusive unification of every species under its specific definition that has dominated earthly reasoning, so they will have escaped the delusive simplification of God that vitiates all terrestrial theology. They will hold God to be complex and of an endless variety of aspects, to be expressed by no universal formula nor approved in any uniform manner. Just as the language of Utopia will be a synthesis, even so will its God be. The aspect of God is different in the measure of every man's individuality, and the intimate thing of religion must, therefore, exist in human solitude, between man and God alone. Religion in its quintessence is a relation between God and man; it is perversion to make it a relation between man and man, and a man may no more reach God through a priest than love his wife through a priest. But just as a man in love may refine the interpretation of his feelings and borrow expression from the poems and music of poietic men, so an individual man may at his discretion read books of devotion and hear music that is in harmony with his inchoate feelings. Many of the samurai, therefore, will set themselves private regimens that will help their secret religious life, will pray habitually, and read books of devotion, but with these things the Rule of the order will have nothing to do.

The theology of the Utopian rulers will be deeply rooted in that same philosophy of uniqueness, rejecting anything beyond similarities and practical parallels that fill all their institutions. They will have thoroughly analyzed the misconceptions and assumptions that arise between the One and the Many, which have troubled philosophy since its inception. Just as they will have moved beyond the misleading unification of every species under its specific definition that has dominated earthly reasoning, they will have also escaped the deceptive simplification of God that undermines all earthly theology. They will view God as complex and having an endless variety of aspects, not expressible by any universal formula or approved in a uniform way. Just as the language of Utopia will be a blend, so too will its God be. Everyone perceives God differently according to their individuality, and the essence of religion must, therefore, exist in human solitude, connecting man and God alone. At its core, religion is a relationship between God and man; it is a distortion to make it a relationship between people. A person cannot reach God through a priest any more than he can love his wife through a priest. However, just as a man in love may refine his feelings by borrowing expressions from poems and music created by artists, an individual may choose to read devotional books and listen to music that resonates with his emerging feelings. Many of the samurai will therefore establish personal practices to nurture their private spiritual lives, pray regularly, and read devotional literature, but the Rule of the order will not be involved in these activities.

Clearly the God of the samurai is a transcendental and mystical God. So far as the samurai have a purpose in common in maintaining the State, and the order and progress of the world, so far, by their discipline and denial, by their public work and effort, they worship God together. But the fount of motives lies in the individual life, it lies in silent and deliberate reflections, and at this, the most striking of all the rules of the samurai aims. For seven consecutive days in the year, at least, each man or woman under the Rule must go right out of all the life of man into some wild and solitary place, must speak to no man or woman, and have no sort of intercourse with mankind. They must go bookless and weaponless, without pen or paper, or money. Provisions must be taken for the period of the journey, a rug or sleeping sack—for they must sleep under the open sky—but no means of making a fire. They may study maps beforehand to guide them, showing any difficulties and dangers in the journey, but they may not carry such helps. They must not go by beaten ways or wherever there are inhabited houses, but into the bare, quiet places of the globe—the regions set apart for them.

Clearly, the God of the samurai is a transcendent and mystical God. As far as the samurai share a purpose in upholding the State and the order and progress of the world, they collectively worship God through their discipline and self-denial, as well as their public service and efforts. However, the source of motives lies in individual lives, stemming from quiet and intentional reflection, and this is one of the most significant principles of the samurai. At least once a year, for seven consecutive days, each man or woman under the Rule must leave behind all human life and travel to a wild and solitary place. They must not speak to anyone or interact with humanity. They should go without books or weapons, without pen, paper, or money. They must bring provisions for the journey, as well as a rug or sleeping bag since they are required to sleep under the open sky, but they cannot have any means to make a fire. They can study maps ahead of time to plan their route and identify any challenges or dangers, but they cannot carry these aids with them. They must avoid main roads or areas with people, instead venturing into the untouched, quiet places of the earth—the regions designated for them.

This discipline, my double said, was invented to secure a certain stoutness of heart and body in the members of the order, which otherwise might have lain open to too many timorous, merely abstemious, men and women. Many things had been suggested, swordplay and tests that verged on torture, climbing in giddy places and the like, before this was chosen. Partly, it is to ensure good training and sturdiness of body and mind, but partly, also, it is to draw their minds for a space from the insistent details of life, from the intricate arguments and the fretting effort to work, from personal quarrels and personal affections, and the things of the heated room. Out they must go, clean out of the world.

This discipline, my double said, was created to ensure a certain strength of heart and body in the members of the order, which might otherwise have attracted too many timid, merely self-denying men and women. Many options had been proposed, like sword fighting and challenges that bordered on torture, climbing in dizzying heights and such, before this one was chosen. Partly, it’s to guarantee good training and resilience of body and mind, but also to help take their minds away for a while from the constant demands of life, from the complicated arguments and the stressful struggle to work, from personal disputes and relationships, and the distractions of everyday life. They must go out, completely away from the world.

Certain great areas are set apart for these yearly pilgrimages beyond the securities of the State. There are thousands of square miles of sandy desert in Africa and Asia set apart; much of the Arctic and Antarctic circles; vast areas of mountain land and frozen marsh; secluded reserves of forest, and innumerable unfrequented lines upon the sea. Some are dangerous and laborious routes; some merely desolate; and there are even some sea journeys that one may take in the halcyon days as one drifts through a dream. Upon the seas one must go in a little undecked sailing boat, that may be rowed in a calm; all the other journeys one must do afoot, none aiding. There are, about all these desert regions and along most coasts, little offices at which the samurai says good-bye to the world of men, and at which they arrive after their minimum time of silence is overpast. For the intervening days they must be alone with Nature, necessity, and their own thoughts.

Certain great areas are designated for these annual pilgrimages outside the protections of the State. There are thousands of square miles of sandy desert in Africa and Asia set aside; much of the Arctic and Antarctic regions; vast expanses of mountain terrain and frozen marsh; secluded forest reserves, and countless unvisited routes on the sea. Some are risky and challenging paths; others are simply barren; and there are even some sea journeys that can be taken during peaceful days as one floats through a dream. On the seas, one must travel in a small, open sailing boat that can be rowed when it's calm; all the other journeys must be made on foot, with no help. Around all these desert areas and along most coastlines, there are little offices where the samurai bids farewell to the world of men, and where they arrive after their minimum period of silence has passed. For the days in between, they must be alone with Nature, necessity, and their own thoughts.

“It is good?” I said.

"Is it good?" I said.

“It is good,” my double answered. “We civilised men go back to the stark Mother that so many of us would have forgotten were it not for this Rule. And one thinks.... Only two weeks ago I did my journey for the year. I went with my gear by sea to Tromso, and then inland to a starting-place, and took my ice-axe and rücksack, and said good-bye to the world. I crossed over four glaciers; I climbed three high mountain passes, and slept on moss in desolate valleys. I saw no human being for seven days. Then I came down through pine woods to the head of a road that runs to the Baltic shore. Altogether it was thirteen days before I reported myself again, and had speech with fellow creatures.”

“It’s good,” my counterpart replied. “We civilized people return to the raw Mother that so many of us would have forgotten if it weren’t for this Rule. And one thinks... Just two weeks ago, I did my annual journey. I traveled by sea to Tromso, then went inland to a starting point, took my ice axe and backpack, and said goodbye to the world. I crossed four glaciers; I climbed three high mountain passes and slept on moss in empty valleys. I didn’t see another person for seven days. Then I descended through pine woods to the beginning of a road that leads to the Baltic shore. In total, it was thirteen days before I reported back and spoke with other people.”

“And the women do this?”

"And the women do that?"

“The women who are truly samurai—yes. Equally with the men. Unless the coming of children intervenes.”

“The women who are truly samurai—yes. Just like the men. Unless having children gets in the way.”

I asked him how it had seemed to him, and what he thought about during the journey.

I asked him how it felt to him and what he thought about during the trip.

“There is always a sense of effort for me,” he said, “when I leave the world at the outset of the journey. I turn back again and again, and look at the little office as I go up my mountain side. The first day and night I'm a little disposed to shirk the job—every year it's the same—a little disposed, for example, to sling my pack from my back, and sit down, and go through its contents, and make sure I've got all my equipment.”

“There's always this feeling of effort for me,” he said, “when I leave the world behind at the start of my journey. I look back repeatedly at the small office as I head up the mountain. On the first day and night, I'm a bit tempted to avoid the work—every year it’s the same—a bit tempted, for instance, to toss my pack off my back, sit down, and go through its contents to make sure I’ve got all my gear.”

“There's no chance of anyone overtaking you?”

“Is there any chance that someone could catch up to you?”

“Two men mustn't start from the same office on the same route within six hours of each other. If they come within sight of each other, they must shun an encounter, and make no sign—unless life is in danger. All that is arranged beforehand.”

“Two men can't start from the same office on the same route within six hours of each other. If they see each other, they need to avoid an encounter and not signal each other—unless it’s a life-or-death situation. All that is planned in advance.”

“It would be, of course. Go on telling me of your journey.”

“It would be, of course. Keep telling me about your journey.”

“I dread the night. I dread discomfort and bad weather. I only begin to brace up after the second day.”

“I hate the night. I hate being uncomfortable and dealing with bad weather. I only start to feel ready after the second day.”

“Don't you worry about losing your way?”

“Don’t you worry about getting lost?”

“No. There are cairns and skyline signs. If it wasn't for that, of course we should be worrying with maps the whole time. But I'm only sure of being a man after the second night, and sure of my power to go through.”

“No. There are stone piles and signs in the skyline. If it weren't for those, we would definitely have to be focused on maps all the time. But I only feel certain about being a man after the second night, and I'm confident in my strength to move forward.”

“And then?”

"What's next?"

“Then one begins to get into it. The first two days one is apt to have the events of one's journey, little incidents of travel, and thoughts of one's work and affairs, rising and fading and coming again; but then the perspectives begin. I don't sleep much at nights on these journeys; I lie awake and stare at the stars. About dawn, perhaps, and in the morning sunshine, I sleep! The nights this last time were very short, never more than twilight, and I saw the glow of the sun always, just over the edge of the world. But I had chosen the days of the new moon, so that I could have a glimpse of the stars.... Years ago, I went from the Nile across the Libyan Desert east, and then the stars—the stars in the later days of that journey—brought me near weeping.... You begin to feel alone on the third day, when you find yourself out on some shining snowfield, and nothing of mankind visible in the whole world save one landmark, one remote thin red triangle of iron, perhaps, in the saddle of the ridge against the sky. All this busy world that has done so much and so marvellously, and is still so little—you see it little as it is—and far off. All day long you go and the night comes, and it might be another planet. Then, in the quiet, waking hours, one thinks of one's self and the great external things, of space and eternity, and what one means by God.”

“Then you start to really immerse yourself. The first couple of days, your mind tends to wander through the events of your journey, little travel moments, and thoughts about your work and life, coming and going. But then, the perspectives shift. I don’t sleep much at night on these trips; I lie awake staring at the stars. Maybe around dawn, in the morning light, I finally sleep! The nights this time were very brief, barely more than twilight, and I could always see the sun glowing just over the edge of the world. But I chose the days of the new moon, so I could catch a glimpse of the stars.... Years ago, I traveled from the Nile across the Libyan Desert to the east, and by the end of that journey—the stars—those stars brought me close to tears.... You start to feel alone on the third day when you find yourself on a bright snowfield, with nothing human in sight except for one distant thin red triangle of iron, maybe, perched on the ridge against the sky. This busy world, which has created so much and can be so amazing, seems so small and far away—you perceive its smallness. You keep moving throughout the day, and night falls, and it feels like another planet. Then, in those quiet, waking moments, you begin to reflect on yourself and those vast external matters, on space and eternity, and what you understand as God.”

He mused.

He thought.

“You think of death?”

"Are you thinking about death?"

“Not of my own. But when I go among snows and desolations—and usually I take my pilgrimage in mountains or the north—I think very much of the Night of this World—the time when our sun will be red and dull, and air and water will lie frozen together in a common snowfield where now the forests of the tropics are steaming.... I think very much of that, and whether it is indeed God's purpose that our kind should end, and the cities we have built, the books we have written, all that we have given substance and a form, should lie dead beneath the snows.”

"Not because I want to. But when I'm out in the snow and desolation—and I usually take my journeys in the mountains or the north—I often think about the Night of this World—the time when our sun will be red and dull, and air and water will be frozen together in a vast snowfield where the tropical forests now steam.... I think a lot about that, and whether it's truly God's intention for our kind to end, and for the cities we've built, the books we've written, and everything we've given substance and form to, to lie buried under the snow."

“You don't believe that?”

"Do you really not believe that?"

“No. But if it is not so―. I went threading my way among gorges and precipices, with my poor brain dreaming of what the alternative should be, with my imagination straining and failing. Yet, in those high airs and in such solitude, a kind of exaltation comes to men.... I remember that one night I sat up and told the rascal stars very earnestly how they should not escape us in the end.”

“No. But if that’s not the case— I made my way through gorges and cliffs, with my mind wondering what the alternative could be, my imagination pushing hard but falling short. Still, in those elevated spaces and in such solitude, a sense of uplift comes to people.... I remember one night I stayed up and earnestly told the mischievous stars how they shouldn’t get away from us in the end.”

He glanced at me for a moment as though he doubted I should understand.

He looked at me for a moment, as if he wasn’t sure I would understand.

“One becomes a personification up there,” he said. “One becomes the ambassador of mankind to the outer world.

“One becomes a symbol up there,” he said. “One becomes the representative of humanity to the universe.”

“There is time to think over a lot of things. One puts one's self and one's ambition in a new pair of scales....

“There’s time to think about a lot of things. You put yourself and your ambitions on a new pair of scales....

“Then there are hours when one is just exploring the wilderness like a child. Sometimes perhaps one gets a glimpse from some precipice edge of the plains far away, and houses and roadways, and remembers there is still a busy world of men. And at last one turns one's feet down some slope, some gorge that leads back. You come down, perhaps, into a pine forest, and hear that queer clatter reindeer make—and then, it may be, see a herdsman very far away, watching you. You wear your pilgrim's badge, and he makes no sign of seeing you....

“Then there are moments when you’re just wandering through the wilderness like a child. Sometimes you might catch a glimpse from the edge of a cliff of the distant plains, with houses and roads, and remember that there’s still a busy world of people out there. Eventually, you turn your feet down some slope, some ravine that leads back. You make your way down, maybe into a pine forest, and you hear that strange sound reindeer make—and then, perhaps, you spot a herdsman way off in the distance, watching you. You’re wearing your pilgrim's badge, and he doesn’t seem to notice you....

“You know, after these solitudes, I feel just the same queer disinclination to go back to the world of men that I feel when I have to leave it. I think of dusty roads and hot valleys, and being looked at by many people. I think of the trouble of working with colleagues and opponents. This last journey I outstayed my time, camping in the pine woods for six days. Then my thoughts came round to my proper work again. I got keen to go on with it, and so I came back into the world. You come back physically clean—as though you had had your arteries and veins washed out. And your brain has been cleaned, too.... I shall stick to the mountains now until I am old, and then I shall sail a boat in Polynesia. That is what so many old men do. Only last year one of the great leaders of the samurai—a white-haired man, who followed the Rule in spite of his one hundred and eleven years—was found dead in his boat far away from any land, far to the south, lying like a child asleep....”

“You know, after these times alone, I feel the same strange reluctance to return to the world of people that I feel when I have to leave it. I think about dusty roads and hot valleys, and being watched by so many faces. I think about the hassle of working with colleagues and rivals. On this last trip, I stayed longer than I planned, camping in the pine woods for six days. Then my thoughts turned back to my real work. I got excited to continue with it, so I came back to the world. You return feeling physically refreshed—as if your arteries and veins have been cleaned out. And your mind has been cleared, too.... I’ll stick to the mountains now until I’m old, and then I’ll sail a boat in Polynesia. That’s what many old men do. Just last year, one of the great leaders of the samurai—a white-haired man who followed the Code despite being one hundred and eleven years old—was found dead in his boat far away from any land, far to the south, lying like a child asleep....”

“That's better than a tumbled bed,” said I, “and some boy of a doctor jabbing you with injections, and distressful people hovering about you.”

“That's better than a messed-up bed,” I said, “and some kid doctor poking you with needles, and annoying people hanging around you.”

“Yes,” said my double; “in Utopia we who are samurai die better than that.... Is that how your great men die?”

“Yes,” said my double; “in Utopia, we samurai die better than that... Is that how your great men die?”

It came to me suddenly as very strange that, even as we sat and talked, across deserted seas, on burning sands, through the still aisles of forests, and in all the high and lonely places of the world, beyond the margin where the ways and houses go, solitary men and women sailed alone or marched alone, or clambered—quiet, resolute exiles; they stood alone amidst wildernesses of ice, on the precipitous banks of roaring torrents, in monstrous caverns, or steering a tossing boat in the little circle of the horizon amidst the tumbled, incessant sea, all in their several ways communing with the emptiness, the enigmatic spaces and silences, the winds and torrents and soulless forces that lie about the lit and ordered life of men.

It hit me all of a sudden how strange it was that, even as we sat and talked, across empty seas, on hot sands, through the quiet aisles of forests, and in all the high and lonely places in the world, beyond where the roads and houses end, solitary men and women traveled alone, or marched alone, or climbed—quiet, determined exiles; they stood alone amidst icy wildernesses, on steep banks of roaring rivers, in huge caves, or steering a rocking boat in the small circle of the horizon amidst the churning, endless sea, all in their own ways connecting with the emptiness, the mysterious spaces and silences, the winds and torrents and lifeless forces surrounding the bright and ordered life of people.

I saw more clearly now something I had seen dimly already, in the bearing and the faces of this Utopian chivalry, a faint persistent tinge of detachment from the immediate heats and hurries, the little graces and delights, the tensions and stimulations of the daily world. It pleased me strangely to think of this steadfast yearly pilgrimage of solitude, and how near men might come then to the high distances of God.

I recognized more clearly now what I had previously noticed only vaguely in the demeanor and expressions of this idealistic chivalry—a subtle, constant hint of distance from the urgent pressures and fleeting pleasures, the small kindnesses and joys, the stresses and excitements of everyday life. It oddly delighted me to think about this annual journey of solitude, and how close people might get to the profound heights of God during that time.

§ 8

After that I remember we fell talking of the discipline of the Rule, of the Courts that try breaches of it, and interpret doubtful cases—for, though a man may resign with due notice and be free after a certain time to rejoin again, one deliberate breach may exclude a man for ever—of the system of law that has grown up about such trials, and of the triennial council that revises and alters the Rule. From that we passed to the discussion of the general constitution of this World State. Practically all political power vests in the samurai. Not only are they the only administrators, lawyers, practising doctors, and public officials of almost all kinds, but they are the only voters. Yet, by a curious exception, the supreme legislative assembly must have one-tenth, and may have one-half of its members outside the order, because, it is alleged, there is a sort of wisdom that comes of sin and laxness, which is necessary to the perfect ruling of life. My double quoted me a verse from the Canon on this matter that my unfortunate verbal memory did not retain, but it was in the nature of a prayer to save the world from “unfermented men.” It would seem that Aristotle's idea of a rotation of rulers, an idea that crops up again in Harrington's Oceana, that first Utopia of “the sovereign people” (a Utopia that, through Danton's readings in English, played a disastrous part in the French Revolution), gets a little respect in Utopia. The tendency is to give a practically permanent tenure to good men. Every ruler and official, it is true, is put on his trial every three years before a jury drawn by lot, according to the range of his activities, either from the samurai of his municipal area or from the general catalogue of the samurai, but the business of this jury is merely to decide whether to continue him in office or order a new election. In the majority of cases the verdict is continuation. Even if it is not so the official may still appear as a candidate before the second and separate jury which fills the vacant post....

After that, I remember we talked about the rules of the system, the courts that handle violations, and interpret unclear cases—because while a person can resign with proper notice and be free to rejoin later, one serious violation can exclude someone forever—about the legal system that has developed around such trials, and about the triennial council that reviews and updates the rules. From there, we moved on to discussing the overall structure of this World State. Almost all political power is held by the samurai. They are not only the sole administrators, lawyers, practicing doctors, and public officials in almost every area, but they're also the only voters. Yet, by a strange exception, the highest legislative assembly must include one-tenth and can have up to one-half of its members from outside the order because it's believed that a certain wisdom that comes from sin and looseness is essential for effective governance. My friend quoted a line from the Canon on this topic that I unfortunately didn't remember, but it was something like a prayer to save the world from “unfermented men.” It seems that Aristotle's idea of a rotation of rulers, which resurfaces in Harrington's Oceana, that early Utopia of “the sovereign people” (a Utopia that, due to Danton's readings in English, had a disastrous role in the French Revolution), gets a bit of respect in Utopia. The inclination is to grant a practically permanent position to capable individuals. Every ruler and official, it’s true, is put on trial every three years before a jury randomly selected based on their area of work, either from the samurai in their municipality or from the overall list of the samurai, but this jury’s job is only to decide whether to keep them in office or call for a new election. In most cases, the verdict is that they continue. Even if it's not, the official can still run as a candidate before the second and separate jury that fills the vacant position....

My double mentioned a few scattered details of the electoral methods, but as at that time I believed we were to have a number of further conversations, I did not exhaust my curiosities upon this subject. Indeed, I was more than a little preoccupied and inattentive. The religion of the samurai was after my heart, and it had taken hold of me very strongly.... But presently I fell questioning him upon the complications that arise in the Modern Utopia through the differences between the races of men, and found my attention returning. But the matter of that discussion I shall put apart into a separate chapter. In the end we came back to the particulars of this great Rule of Life that any man desiring of joining the samurai must follow.

My double mentioned a few scattered details about the voting methods, but since I thought we'd have several more conversations, I didn't dig too deeply into this topic. Honestly, I was pretty distracted and not fully focused. The religion of the samurai really resonated with me, and it had a strong hold on my mind.... Eventually, I started asking him about the complexities that arise in the Modern Utopia due to the differences among races of people, and found my interest piqued again. However, I will set that discussion aside for a separate chapter. Ultimately, we returned to the specifics of this great Rule of Life that anyone wanting to join the samurai must follow.

I remember how, after our third bout of talking, I walked back through the streets of Utopian London to rejoin the botanist at our hotel.

I remember how, after our third conversation, I walked back through the streets of Utopian London to meet up with the botanist at our hotel.

My double lived in an apartment in a great building—I should judge about where, in our London, the Tate Gallery squats, and, as the day was fine, and I had no reason for hurry, I went not by the covered mechanical way, but on foot along the broad, tree-set terraces that follow the river on either side.

My twin lived in an apartment in a nice building—I would guess it's around where the Tate Gallery is in London, and since it was a beautiful day and I had no reason to rush, I chose to walk instead of taking the underground route, strolling along the wide, tree-lined terraces that run alongside the river.

It was afternoon, and the mellow Thames Valley sunlight, warm and gentle, lit a clean and gracious world. There were many people abroad, going to and fro, unhurrying, but not aimless, and I watched them so attentively that were you to ask me for the most elementary details of the buildings and terraces that lay back on either bank, or of the pinnacles and towers and parapets that laced the sky, I could not tell you them. But of the people I could tell a great deal.

It was afternoon, and the soft, warm sunlight of the Thames Valley filled the world with a cozy glow. There were many people out and about, moving leisurely but with purpose, and I watched them so closely that if you asked me for the most basic details about the buildings and terraces lining the banks, or the peaks, towers, and walls reaching into the sky, I wouldn't be able to tell you. But I could share a lot about the people.

No Utopians wear black, and for all the frequency of the samurai uniform along the London ways the general effect is of a gaily-coloured population. You never see anyone noticeably ragged or dirty; the police, who answer questions and keep order (and are quite distinct from the organisation for the pursuit of criminals) see to that; and shabby people are very infrequent. People who want to save money for other purposes, or who do not want much bother with their clothing, seem to wear costumes of rough woven cloth, dyed an unobtrusive brown or green, over fine woollen underclothing, and so achieve a decent comfort in its simplest form. Others outside the Rule of the samurai range the spectrum for colour, and have every variety of texture; the colours attained by the Utopian dyers seem to me to be fuller and purer than the common range of stuffs on earth; and the subtle folding of the woollen materials witness that Utopian Bradford is no whit behind her earthly sister. White is extraordinarily frequent; white woollen tunics and robes into which are woven bands of brilliant colour, abound. Often these ape the cut and purple edge that distinguishes the samurai. In Utopian London the air is as clear and less dusty than it is among high mountains; the roads are made of unbroken surfaces, and not of friable earth; all heating is done by electricity, and no coal ever enters the town; there are no horses or dogs, and so there is not a suspicion of smoke and scarcely a particle of any sort of dirt to render white impossible.

No Utopians wear black, and despite the frequent sight of the samurai uniform on the streets of London, the overall appearance is that of a vibrant, colorful community. You never see anyone who looks particularly ragged or dirty; the police, who answer questions and maintain order (and are separate from those chasing criminals), ensure that. Shabby individuals are quite rare. People aiming to save money for other things, or those who prefer not to deal much with their clothing, tend to wear outfits made of rough-woven cloth dyed in subtle shades of brown or green, layered over fine wool undergarments, achieving a decent comfort in its simplest form. Others outside the samurai framework explore a spectrum of colors, showcasing every variety of texture; the hues produced by Utopian dyers seem richer and purer than the typical fabrics found on Earth. The delicate draping of the woolen materials shows that Utopian Bradford is on par with its earthly counterpart. White is exceptionally common; white wool tunics and robes interwoven with bands of bright color are everywhere. Often, these mimic the style and purple trim that define the samurai. In Utopian London, the air is clearer and less dusty than in high mountain areas; the roads have smooth surfaces rather than loose soil; all heating is done with electricity, and no coal enters the city; there are no horses or dogs, so there’s no sign of smoke and hardly any dirt to spoil the whiteness.

The radiated influence of the uniform of the samurai has been to keep costume simple, and this, perhaps, emphasises the general effect of vigorous health, of shapely bodies. Everyone is well grown and well nourished; everyone seems in good condition; everyone walks well, and has that clearness of eye that comes with cleanness of blood. In London I am apt to consider myself of a passable size and carriage; here I feel small and mean-looking. The faint suspicions of spinal curvatures, skew feet, unequal legs, and ill-grown bones, that haunt one in a London crowd, the plain intimations—in yellow faces, puffy faces, spotted and irregular complexions, in nervous movements and coughs and colds—of bad habits and an incompetent or disregarded medical profession, do not appear here. I notice few old people, but there seems to be a greater proportion of men and women at or near the prime of life.

The influence of the samurai uniform has kept the clothing simple, which likely highlights the overall impression of strong health and well-shaped bodies. Everyone is well-built and well-nourished; everyone looks fit; everyone walks confidently and has the brightness in their eyes that comes from good health. In London, I tend to think I'm of average size and stature; here, I feel small and unimpressive. The slight worries about hunches, crooked feet, uneven legs, and poorly developed bones that you notice in a London crowd, along with the obvious signs—like sallow faces, puffy faces, blotchy and uneven complexions, nervous fidgeting, and frequent coughs and colds—indicating bad habits and a failing or ignored healthcare system, aren't noticeable here. I see few elderly people, but there seems to be a larger proportion of men and women at or near their prime.

I hang upon that. I have seen one or two fat people here—they are all the more noticeable because they are rare. But wrinkled age? Have I yet in Utopia set eyes on a bald head?

I dwell on that. I've noticed a few overweight people here—they stand out even more because they are so uncommon. But as for wrinkles that come with age? Have I even spotted a bald head in Utopia yet?

The Utopians have brought a sounder physiological science than ours to bear upon regimen. People know better what to do and what to avoid, how to foresee and forestall coming trouble, and how to evade and suppress the subtle poisons that blunt the edge of sensation. They have put off the years of decay. They keep their teeth, they keep their digestions, they ward off gout and rheumatism, neuralgia and influenza and all those cognate decays that bend and wrinkle men and women in the middle years of existence. They have extended the level years far into the seventies, and age, when it comes, comes swiftly and easily. The feverish hurry of our earth, the decay that begins before growth has ceased, is replaced by a ripe prolonged maturity. This modern Utopia is an adult world. The flushed romance, the predominant eroticisms, the adventurous uncertainty of a world in which youth prevails, gives place here to a grave deliberation, to a fuller and more powerful emotion, to a broader handling of life.

The Utopians have developed a more advanced understanding of physical health than we have for managing well-being. People know more about what to do and what to avoid, how to predict and prevent potential issues, and how to dodge the hidden toxins that dull their senses. They've managed to delay the aging process. They maintain their teeth and digestive health, and they avoid gout, arthritis, neuralgia, flu, and all those related issues that cause men and women to bend and wrinkle in their middle years. They have extended their healthy years well into their seventies, and when age finally comes, it does so gently and easily. The frantic rush of our world, the decline that starts before growth has fully finished, is swapped for a rich, extended maturity. This modern Utopia is a grown-up environment. The fleeting romance, the overwhelming sensuality, and the adventurous uncertainty of a youth-dominated world give way here to serious thoughtfulness, deeper and more intense emotions, and a broader approach to life.

Yet youth is here.

Yet youth is present.

Amidst the men whose faces have been made fine by thought and steadfast living, among the serene-eyed women, comes youth, gaily-coloured, buoyantly healthy, with challenging eyes, with fresh and eager face....

Amidst the men whose faces have been shaped by deep thinking and determined living, among the calm-eyed women, comes youth, vibrant and lively, full of health, with bold eyes and a fresh, eager face...

For everyone in Utopia who is sane enough to benefit, study and training last until twenty; then comes the travel year, and many are still students until twenty-four or twenty-five. Most are still, in a sense, students throughout life, but it is thought that, unless responsible action is begun in some form in the early twenties, will undergoes a partial atrophy. But the full swing of adult life is hardly attained until thirty is reached. Men marry before the middle thirties, and the women rather earlier, few are mothers before five-and-twenty. The majority of those who become samurai do so between twenty-seven and thirty-five. And, between seventeen and thirty, the Utopians have their dealings with love, and the play and excitement of love is a chief interest in life. Much freedom of act is allowed them so that their wills may grow freely. For the most part they end mated, and love gives place to some special and more enduring interest, though, indeed, there is love between older men and fresh girls, and between youths and maturer women. It is in these most graceful and beautiful years of life that such freedoms of dress as the atmosphere of Utopia permits are to be seen, and the crude bright will and imagination of youth peeps out in ornament and colour.

For everyone in Utopia who is sane enough to benefit, study and training last until twenty; then comes the travel year, and many are still students until twenty-four or twenty-five. Most remain, in a sense, students throughout their lives, but it’s believed that unless responsible actions are taken in some form during the early twenties, their willpower may start to fade. However, full adult life really doesn’t kick in until they reach thirty. Men typically marry before their mid-thirties, while women tend to marry a bit earlier, and few women become mothers before twenty-five. The majority of those who become samurai do so between twenty-seven and thirty-five. Between seventeen and thirty, Utopians engage in love, with the playfulness and excitement of romance being a central interest in life. They are given a lot of freedom to act so that their wills can develop freely. For the most part, they end up pairing off, and love eventually gives way to more lasting interests. However, there is still love between older men and younger women, as well as between younger men and older women. It is during these most graceful and beautiful years of life that the unconventional clothing allowed by the atmosphere of Utopia can be seen, and the vibrant will and imagination of youth express themselves in embellishments and colors.

Figures come into my sight and possess me for a moment and pass, and give place to others; there comes a dusky little Jewess, red-lipped and amber-clad, with a deep crimson flower—I know not whether real or sham—in the dull black of her hair. She passes me with an unconscious disdain; and then I am looking at a brightly-smiling, blue-eyed girl, tall, ruddy, and freckled warmly, clad like a stage Rosalind, and talking gaily to a fair young man, a novice under the Rule. A red-haired mother under the Lesser Rule goes by, green-gowned, with dark green straps crossing between her breasts, and her two shock-headed children, bare-legged and lightly shod, tug at her hands on either side. Then a grave man in a long, fur-trimmed robe, a merchant, maybe, debates some serious matter with a white-tunicked clerk. And the clerk's face―? I turn to mark the straight, blue-black hair. The man must be Chinese....

Figures come into view, grab my attention for a moment, then fade away, making room for others. A short, dark-skinned Jewish woman walks by, her lips red and dressed in amber, with a deep crimson flower—I can't tell if it's real or fake—in her dark hair. She glances at me with a hint of disdain, then I see a tall, freckled girl with bright blue eyes, dressed like a stage Rosalind, chatting happily with a young man, a beginner under the Rule. A red-haired mother, dressed in green under the Lesser Rule, strolls past with her two wild-haired kids, barefoot and lightly shod, pulling at her hands on either side. Then, a serious-looking man in a long, fur-trimmed robe, possibly a merchant, discusses something important with a clerk in a white tunic. And the clerk's face—? I turn to notice the straight, blue-black hair. He must be Chinese...

Then come two short-bearded men in careless indigo blue raiment, both of them convulsed with laughter—men outside the Rule, who practise, perhaps, some art—and then one of the samurai, in cheerful altercation with a blue-robed girl of eight. “But you could have come back yesterday, Dadda,” she persists. He is deeply sunburnt, and suddenly there passes before my mind the picture of a snowy mountain waste at night-fall and a solitary small figure under the stars....

Then two short-bearded guys in casual indigo blue outfits show up, both of them bursting with laughter—men who live outside the norms, maybe practicing some kind of art—and then one of the samurai is happily arguing with a blue-robed girl who’s about eight. “But you could have come back yesterday, Dadda,” she insists. He’s really sunburned, and suddenly a vivid image flashes in my mind of a snowy mountain wilderness at dusk and a lone small figure under the stars....

When I come back to the present thing again, my eye is caught at once by a young negro, carrying books in his hand, a prosperous-looking, self-respecting young negro, in a trimly-cut coat of purple-blue and silver.

When I return to the present moment, my attention is immediately drawn to a young Black man carrying books in his hand. He looks well-off and self-respecting, dressed in a sharply tailored coat of purple-blue and silver.

I am reminded of what my double said to me of race.

I remember what my other self told me about race.

CHAPTER THE TENTH
Race in Utopia

§ 1

Above the sphere of the elemental cravings and necessities, the soul of man is in a perpetual vacillation between two conflicting impulses: the desire to assert his individual differences, the desire for distinction, and his terror of isolation. He wants to stand out, but not too far out, and, on the contrary, he wants to merge himself with a group, with some larger body, but not altogether. Through all the things of life runs this tortuous compromise, men follow the fashions but resent ready-made uniforms on every plane of their being. The disposition to form aggregations and to imagine aggregations is part of the incurable nature of man; it is one of the great natural forces the statesman must utilise, and against which he must construct effectual defences. The study of the aggregations and of the ideals of aggregations about which men's sympathies will twine, and upon which they will base a large proportion of their conduct and personal policy, is the legitimate definition of sociology.

Above the sphere of basic cravings and needs, the human soul constantly swings between two opposing urges: the desire to express individual differences and stand out, and the fear of being alone. People want to be unique, but not too much, and at the same time, they want to connect with a group or a larger community, but not completely lose themselves in it. Throughout life, this complicated balance is evident; people follow trends yet resist feeling like they’re in a one-size-fits-all mold in every aspect of their lives. The tendency to form groups and envision collective identities is inherent to human nature; it’s one of the major forces that leaders must harness and also protect against. Understanding these groups and the ideals that resonate with people's emotions, which significantly influence their behavior and personal choices, is the true definition of sociology.

Now the sort of aggregation to which men and women will refer themselves is determined partly by the strength and idiosyncrasy of the individual imagination, and partly by the reek of ideas that chances to be in the air at the time. Men and women may vary greatly both in their innate and their acquired disposition towards this sort of larger body or that, to which their social reference can be made. The “natural” social reference of a man is probably to some rather vaguely conceived tribe, as the “natural” social reference of a dog is to a pack. But just as the social reference of a dog may be educated until the reference to a pack is completely replaced by a reference to an owner, so on his higher plane of educability the social reference of the civilised man undergoes the most remarkable transformations. But the power and scope of his imagination and the need he has of response sets limits to this process. A highly intellectualised mature mind may refer for its data very consistently to ideas of a higher being so remote and indefinable as God, so comprehensive as humanity, so far-reaching as the purpose in things. I write “may,” but I doubt if this exaltation of reference is ever permanently sustained. Comte, in his Positive Polity, exposes his soul with great freedom, and the curious may trace how, while he professes and quite honestly intends to refer himself always to his “Greater Being” Humanity, he narrows constantly to his projected “Western Republic” of civilised men, and quite frequently to the minute indefinite body of Positivist subscribers. And the history of the Christian Church, with its development of orders and cults, sects and dissents, the history of fashionable society with its cliques and sets and every political history with its cabals and inner cabinets, witness to the struggle that goes on in the minds of men to adjust themselves to a body larger indeed than themselves, but which still does not strain and escape their imaginative grasp.

Now, the kind of groups that men and women identify with is shaped partly by their individual imagination and partly by the ideas that are prevalent at the time. People can differ widely in both their natural and learned tendencies toward this type of larger group or that, to which they can relate socially. The “natural” social reference for a man is likely some vaguely defined tribe, just as a dog’s “natural” social reference is to a pack. However, just as a dog's social reference can be trained to completely shift from a pack to an owner, so too can the social reference of a civilized person transform remarkably on a higher level of understanding. Yet the extent and power of their imagination and their need for connection put limits on this process. A highly intellectual, mature mind might consistently relate its ideas to something as abstract and ungraspable as God, something as broad as humanity, or something as expansive as the purpose of existence. I say “might,” but I question whether this elevated reference is ever truly maintained for long. Comte, in his Positive Polity, honestly lays bare his thoughts, and the curious can see how, while he sincerely claims to refer to his “Greater Being” Humanity, he consistently narrows his focus to his envisioned “Western Republic” of civilized individuals, and often to the small, indistinct group of Positivist followers. The history of the Christian Church, with its various orders and sects, the evolution of fashionable society with its cliques and groups, and every political history with its factions and inner circles, all illustrate the struggle within people to adjust to a group that is indeed larger than themselves but still within their imaginative reach.

The statesman, both for himself and others, must recognise this inadequacy of grasp, and the necessity for real and imaginary aggregations to sustain men in their practical service of the order of the world. He must be a sociologist; he must study the whole science of aggregations in relation to that World State to which his reason and his maturest thought direct him. He must lend himself to the development of aggregatory ideas that favour the civilising process, and he must do his best to promote the disintegration of aggregations and the effacement of aggregatory ideas, that keep men narrow and unreasonably prejudiced one against another.

The statesman, for himself and for others, must recognize this limitation in understanding and the need for both real and imagined groups to support people in their practical role in the world. He needs to be a sociologist; he must study the entire field of group dynamics in relation to the World State that his reason and deepest thoughts guide him toward. He should contribute to the development of unifying ideas that promote civilization and do his best to encourage the breakdown of groups and the erasure of divisive ideas that keep people narrow-minded and unfairly biased against one another.

He will, of course, know that few men are even rudely consistent in such matters, that the same man in different moods and on different occasions, is capable of referring himself in perfect good faith, not only to different, but to contradictory larger beings, and that the more important thing about an aggregatory idea from the State maker's point of view is not so much what it explicitly involves as what it implicitly repudiates. The natural man does not feel he is aggregating at all, unless he aggregates against something. He refers himself to the tribe; he is loyal to the tribe, and quite inseparably he fears or dislikes those others outside the tribe. The tribe is always at least defensively hostile and usually actively hostile to humanity beyond the aggregation. The Anti-idea, it would seem, is inseparable from the aggregatory idea; it is a necessity of the human mind. When we think of the class A as desirable, we think of Not-A as undesirable. The two things are as inevitably connected as the tendons of our hands, so that when we flatten down our little fingers on our palms, the fourth digit, whether we want it or not, comes down halfway. All real working gods, one may remark, all gods that are worshipped emotionally, are tribal gods, and every attempt to universalise the idea of God trails dualism and the devil after it as a moral necessity.

He knows, of course, that few people are consistently straightforward in these matters. The same person, depending on their mood and the situation, can genuinely align themselves with not just different, but even opposing larger groups. From the perspective of someone creating a state, what's crucial about a collective idea isn't just what it directly includes, but also what it implicitly rejects. The average person doesn’t feel like they’re part of a group unless they’re banding together *against* something. They identify with their tribe; they are loyal to it, and at the same time, they fear or dislike those outside it. The tribe is always at least defensively hostile and often actively hostile to those beyond its bounds. The idea of opposition seems to be inseparable from the collective idea; it's a fundamental aspect of human thought. When we view class A as desirable, we naturally see Not-A as undesirable. The two concepts are inherently linked, just like the tendons in our hands, so that when we press our little fingers down into our palms, the fourth finger, whether we want it to or not, also moves down halfway. It’s worth noting that all genuinely worshipped gods—those that evoke strong emotions—are tribal gods. Any attempt to make the idea of God universal tends to bring dualism and the concept of the devil along as a necessary moral consequence.

When we inquire, as well as the unformed condition of terrestrial sociology permits, into the aggregatory ideas that seem to satisfy men, we find a remarkable complex, a disorderly complex, in the minds of nearly all our civilised contemporaries. For example, all sorts of aggregatory ideas come and go across the chameleon surfaces of my botanist's mind. He has a strong feeling for systematic botanists as against plant physiologists, whom he regards as lewd and evil scoundrels in this relation, but he has a strong feeling for all botanists, and, indeed, all biologists, as against physicists, and those who profess the exact sciences, all of whom he regards as dull, mechanical, ugly-minded scoundrels in this relation; but he has a strong feeling for all who profess what is called Science as against psychologists, sociologists, philosophers, and literary men, whom he regards as wild, foolish, immoral scoundrels in this relation; but he has a strong feeling for all educated men as against the working man, whom he regards as a cheating, lying, loafing, drunken, thievish, dirty scoundrel in this relation; but so soon as the working man is comprehended together with those others, as Englishmen—which includes, in this case, I may remark, the Scottish and Welsh—he holds them superior to all other sorts of European, whom he regards, &c....

When we ask, as much as the undeveloped state of social studies allows, about the collective ideas that seem to fulfill people, we discover a strikingly complicated and chaotic mix in the minds of nearly all our modern civilized peers. For instance, all sorts of collective ideas flit across the ever-changing thoughts of my botanist. He strongly prefers systematic botanists over plant physiologists, whom he sees as sleazy and dishonest in this regard, but he also has a strong preference for all botanists and, indeed, all biologists compared to physicists and those in the exact sciences, whom he considers dull, mechanical, and narrow-minded in this context; however, he holds all those who claim to practice what is called Science in higher regard than psychologists, sociologists, philosophers, and writers, whom he sees as wild, foolish, and morally questionable in this context; yet he favors all educated individuals over the working class, whom he thinks of as deceitful, lazy, drunken, thieving, and unkempt scoundrels in this regard; but as soon as the working class is viewed alongside those others as Englishmen—which, in this case, includes the Scottish and Welsh—he considers them superior to all other types of Europeans, whom he regards, etc....

Now one perceives in all these aggregatory ideas and rearrangements of the sympathies one of the chief vices of human thought, due to its obsession by classificatory suggestions. [Footnote: See Chapter the First, § 5, and the Appendix.] The necessity for marking our classes has brought with it a bias for false and excessive contrast, and we never invent a term but we are at once cramming it with implications beyond its legitimate content. There is no feat of irrelevance that people will not perform quite easily in this way; there is no class, however accidental, to which they will not at once ascribe deeply distinctive qualities. The seventh sons of seventh sons have remarkable powers of insight; people with a certain sort of ear commit crimes of violence; people with red hair have souls of fire; all democratic socialists are trustworthy persons; all people born in Ireland have vivid imaginations and all Englishmen are clods; all Hindoos are cowardly liars; all curly-haired people are good-natured; all hunch-backs are energetic and wicked, and all Frenchmen eat frogs. Such stupid generalisations have been believed with the utmost readiness, and acted upon by great numbers of sane, respectable people. And when the class is one's own class, when it expresses one of the aggregations to which one refers one's own activities, then the disposition to divide all qualities between this class and its converse, and to cram one's own class with every desirable distinction, becomes overwhelming.

Now, it's clear in all these collective ideas and rearrangements of feelings that there's a major flaw in human thinking, caused by an obsession with categorizing things. [Footnote: See Chapter the First, § 5, and the Appendix.] The need to label our categories has led to a tendency for false and exaggerated contrasts, and whenever we create a term, we immediately overload it with meanings beyond what it actually represents. People can easily commit all kinds of irrelevant reasoning this way; there’s no group, no matter how random, to which they won’t readily assign sharply defined traits. The seventh sons of seventh sons have amazing powers of insight; people with a certain kind of ear are likely to commit violent acts; red-haired people have fiery souls; all democratic socialists are trustworthy; everyone born in Ireland has a vivid imagination, and all Englishmen are dull; all Hindoos are cowardly liars; all curly-haired people are friendly; all hunchbacks are energetic and wicked, and all Frenchmen eat frogs. Such ridiculous generalizations have been accepted readily and acted upon by many rational, respectable individuals. And when the class in question is your own, when it reflects a group through which you view your own actions, the urge to divide all qualities between this group and the opposite one, and to fill your own with every admirable trait, becomes incredibly powerful.

It is part of the training of the philosopher to regard all such generalisations with suspicion; it is part of the training of the Utopist and statesman, and all good statesmen are Utopists, to mingle something very like animosity with that suspicion. For crude classifications and false generalisations are the curse of all organised human life.

It's part of a philosopher's training to view all such generalizations with skepticism; it's also part of the training for Utopians and politicians—since all good politicians are Utopians—to mix a bit of hostility with that skepticism. Crude classifications and misleading generalizations are the downfall of all organized human life.

§ 2

Disregarding classes, cliques, sets, castes, and the like minor aggregations, concerned for the most part with details and minor aspects of life, one finds among the civilised peoples of the world certain broad types of aggregatory idea. There are, firstly, the national ideas, ideas which, in their perfection, require a uniformity of physical and mental type, a common idiom, a common religion, a distinctive style of costume, decoration, and thought, and a compact organisation acting with complete external unity. Like the Gothic cathedral, the national idea is never found complete with all its parts; but one has in Russia, with her insistence on political and religious orthodoxy, something approaching it pretty closely, and again in the inland and typical provinces of China, where even a strange pattern of hat arouses hostility. We had it in vigorous struggle to exist in England under the earlier Georges in the minds of those who supported the Established Church. The idea of the fundamental nature of nationality is so ingrained in thought, with all the usual exaggeration of implication, that no one laughs at talk about Swedish painting or American literature. And I will confess and point out that my own detachment from these delusions is so imperfect and discontinuous that in another passage I have committed myself to a short assertion of the exceptionally noble quality of the English imagination. [Footnote: Chapter the Seventh, § 6.] I am constantly gratified by flattering untruths about English superiority which I should reject indignantly were the application bluntly personal, and I am ever ready to believe the scenery of England, the poetry of England, even the decoration and music of England, in some mystic and impregnable way, the best. This habit of intensifying all class definitions, and particularly those in which one has a personal interest, is in the very constitution of man's mind. It is part of the defect of that instrument. We may watch against it and prevent it doing any great injustices, or leading us into follies, but to eradicate it is an altogether different matter. There it is, to be reckoned with, like the coccyx, the pineal eye, and the vermiform appendix. And a too consistent attack on it may lead simply to its inversion, to a vindictively pro-foreigner attitude that is equally unwise.

Disregarding social classes, cliques, groups, castes, and other minor gatherings that mainly focus on the details and small aspects of life, among the civilized peoples of the world, there are certain broad types of collective ideas. First, there are national ideas—ideas that, in their ideal form, require a uniformity of physical and mental characteristics, a common language, a shared religion, a distinct style of clothing, decoration, and thought, and a cohesive organization acting with complete external unity. Like a Gothic cathedral, the national idea is never found fully realized with all its components; however, in Russia, with its emphasis on political and religious orthodoxy, there's something that comes quite close, and likewise in the interior provinces of China, where even an unusual hat design can provoke hostility. We had it in a vigorous fight for existence in England under the earlier Georges in the minds of those who supported the Established Church. The concept of the fundamental nature of nationality is so deeply ingrained in our thinking, with all the typical exaggeration of implications, that no one laughs at discussions about Swedish painting or American literature. And I will admit and point out that my own detachment from these illusions is so imperfect and inconsistent that in another section I have made a brief statement about the exceptionally noble quality of the English imagination. [Footnote: Chapter the Seventh, § 6.] I often feel pleased by flattering untruths about English superiority that I would vehemently deny if they were bluntly personal, and I’m always ready to believe that the scenery of England, the poetry of England, even the decoration and music of England, is in some mystical and undeniable way the best. This tendency to amplify all class definitions, especially those in which one has a personal stake, is part of human nature. It's a flaw in that part of our psyche. We can monitor it and prevent it from causing major injustices or leading us into foolishness, but completely eradicating it is a different story. It is there to be dealt with, like the coccyx, the pineal eye, and the vermiform appendix. A relentless attack on it may simply result in its opposite—a vindictive pro-foreigner stance that is equally unwise.

The second sort of aggregatory ideas, running very often across the boundaries of national ideas and in conflict with them, are religious ideas. In Western Europe true national ideas only emerged to their present hectic vigour after the shock of the Reformation had liberated men from the great tradition of a Latin-speaking Christendom, a tradition the Roman Catholic Church has sustained as its modification of the old Latin-speaking Imperialism in the rule of the pontifex maximus. There was, and there remains to this day, a profound disregard of local dialect and race in the Roman Catholic tradition, which has made that Church a persistently disintegrating influence in national life. Equally spacious and equally regardless of tongues and peoples is the great Arabic-speaking religion of Mahomet. Both Christendom and Islam are indeed on their secular sides imperfect realisations of a Utopian World State. But the secular side was the weaker side of these cults; they produced no sufficiently great statesmen to realise their spiritual forces, and it is not in Rome under pontifical rule, nor in Munster under the Anabaptists, but rather in Thomas à Kempis and Saint Augustin's City of God that we must seek for the Utopias of Christianity.

The second type of unifying ideas, often transcending national boundaries and sometimes conflicting with them, are religious ideas. In Western Europe, genuine national ideas only developed their current intense energy after the Reformation freed people from the longstanding tradition of a Latin-speaking Christianity, a tradition that the Roman Catholic Church has maintained as its adaptation of ancient Latin-speaking Imperialism under the authority of the pontifex maximus. There was, and still is today, a deep disregard for local dialects and ethnicities in the Roman Catholic tradition, which has made that Church a continually disruptive force in national life. Similarly broad and equally indifferent to languages and peoples is the major Arabic-speaking religion of Muhammad. Both Christianity and Islam are indeed, in their secular aspects, flawed attempts at a Utopian World State. However, the secular aspect has been the weaker side of these religions; they have not produced sufficiently great leaders to harness their spiritual energy, and we should look to Thomas à Kempis and Saint Augustine's City of God for the Utopias of Christianity, not to Rome under papal authority or to Munster under the Anabaptists.

In the last hundred years a novel development of material forces, and especially of means of communication, has done very much to break up the isolations in which nationality perfected its prejudices and so to render possible the extension and consolidation of such a world-wide culture as mediæval Christendom and Islam foreshadowed. The first onset of these expansive developments has been marked in the world of mind by an expansion of political ideals—Comte's “Western Republic” (1848) was the first Utopia that involved the synthesis of numerous States—by the development of “Imperialisms” in the place of national policies, and by the search for a basis for wider political unions in racial traditions and linguistic affinities. Anglo-Saxonism, Pan-Germanism, and the like are such synthetic ideas. Until the eighties, the general tendency of progressive thought was at one with the older Christian tradition which ignored “race,” and the aim of the expansive liberalism movement, so far as it had a clear aim, was to Europeanise the world, to extend the franchise to negroes, put Polynesians into trousers, and train the teeming myriads of India to appreciate the exquisite lilt of The Lady of the Lake. There is always some absurdity mixed with human greatness, and we must not let the fact that the middle Victorians counted Scott, the suffrage and pantaloons among the supreme blessings of life, conceal from us the very real nobility of their dream of England's mission to the world....

In the last hundred years, a major development in material forces, especially in communication methods, has significantly reduced the isolation in which nationalities used to cultivate their biases. This has made it possible to expand and strengthen a global culture similar to what medieval Christendom and Islam hinted at. The initial wave of these expansive developments has resulted in a growth of political ideals—Comte's “Western Republic” (1848) was the first Utopia that combined multiple States—replaced national policies with “Imperialisms,” and sought a foundation for broader political unions based on racial traditions and language connections. Ideas like Anglo-Saxonism and Pan-Germanism represent these synthetic concepts. Until the 1880s, the general trend of progressive thought aligned with the older Christian tradition, which overlooked “race,” and the goal of expansive liberalism, as far as it had a clear objective, was to Europeanize the world; this included extending voting rights to Black people, dressing Polynesians in trousers, and educating the vast populations of India to appreciate the delicate rhythm of The Lady of the Lake. There’s often a mix of absurdity and human greatness, and we shouldn’t let the fact that middle Victorians considered Scott, suffrage, and trousers among life’s greatest blessings distract us from acknowledging the genuine nobility in their vision of England’s mission to the world....

We of this generation have seen a flood of reaction against such universalism. The great intellectual developments that centre upon the work of Darwin have exacerbated the realisation that life is a conflict between superior and inferior types, it has underlined the idea that specific survival rates are of primary significance in the world's development, and a swarm of inferior intelligences has applied to human problems elaborated and exaggerated versions of these generalisations. These social and political followers of Darwin have fallen into an obvious confusion between race and nationality, and into the natural trap of patriotic conceit. The dissent of the Indian and Colonial governing class to the first crude applications of liberal propositions in India has found a voice of unparalleled penetration in Mr. Kipling, whose want of intellectual deliberation is only equalled by his poietic power. The search for a basis for a new political synthesis in adaptable sympathies based on linguistic affinities, was greatly influenced by Max Müller's unaccountable assumption that language indicated kindred, and led straight to wildly speculative ethnology, to the discovery that there was a Keltic race, a Teutonic race, an Indo-European race, and so forth. A book that has had enormous influence in this matter, because of its use in teaching, is J. R. Green's Short History of the English People, with its grotesque insistence upon Anglo-Saxonism. And just now, the world is in a sort of delirium about race and the racial struggle. The Briton forgetting his Defoe, [Footnote: The True-born Englishman.] the Jew forgetting the very word proselyte, the German forgetting his anthropometric variations, and the Italian forgetting everything, are obsessed by the singular purity of their blood, and the danger of contamination the mere continuance of other races involves. True to the law that all human aggregation involves the development of a spirit of opposition to whatever is external to the aggregation, extraordinary intensifications of racial definition are going on; the vileness, the inhumanity, the incompatibility of alien races is being steadily exaggerated. The natural tendency of every human being towards a stupid conceit in himself and his kind, a stupid depreciation of all unlikeness, is traded upon by this bastard science. With the weakening of national references, and with the pause before reconstruction in religious belief, these new arbitrary and unsubstantial race prejudices become daily more formidable. They are shaping policies and modifying laws, and they will certainly be responsible for a large proportion of the wars, hardships, and cruelties the immediate future holds in store for our earth.

We, in this generation, have witnessed a surge of reactions against universalism. The significant intellectual advancements stemming from Darwin's work have heightened the understanding that life is a struggle between superior and inferior types. This has emphasized that survival rates are crucial in the world's development, leading many with lesser intelligence to apply elaborate and exaggerated versions of these ideas to human issues. Darwin’s social and political followers have confused race with nationality, falling into the easy trap of patriotic pride. The disapproval from Indian and Colonial leaders towards the early, crude applications of liberal ideas in India has found a remarkably insightful voice in Mr. Kipling, whose lack of intellectual reflection is matched only by his creative power. The search for a foundation for a new political synthesis based on adaptable sympathies tied to linguistic connections was strongly influenced by Max Müller's strange belief that language indicated kinship. This led to wildly speculative ethnology and the discovery of distinct groups like a Celtic race, a Teutonic race, an Indo-European race, and so on. A book that has greatly impacted this discussion, due to its use in education, is J. R. Green's Short History of the English People, with its ridiculous emphasis on Anglo-Saxonism. Right now, the world is in a kind of frenzy over race and racial conflict. The Briton forgets Defoe, [Footnote: The True-born Englishman.] the Jew overlooks the very word proselyte, the German forgets his anthropometric variations, and the Italian ignores everything, all consumed by the supposed purity of their blood and the peril of contamination that other races pose. Following the principle that human groups generate a spirit of opposition to anything outside their group, there's a marked intensification of racial definitions happening. The villainy, inhumanity, and incompatibility of foreign races are being exaggerated. This twisted science preys on the innate human tendency towards foolish pride in oneself and one’s kind and a foolish devaluation of all that is different. As national references weaken and we hesitate before reconstructing religious beliefs, these new arbitrary and unfounded racial prejudices are becoming increasingly powerful. They are shaping policies and altering laws, and they will undeniably be responsible for many of the wars, hardships, and cruelties that our immediate future holds in store for our planet.

No generalisations about race are too extravagant for the inflamed credulity of the present time. No attempt is ever made to distinguish differences in inherent quality—the true racial differences—from artificial differences due to culture. No lesson seems ever to be drawn from history of the fluctuating incidence of the civilising process first upon this race and then upon that. The politically ascendant peoples of the present phase are understood to be the superior races, including such types as the Sussex farm labourer, the Bowery tough, the London hooligan, and the Paris apache; the races not at present prospering politically, such as the Egyptians, the Greeks, the Spanish, the Moors, the Chinese, the Hindoos, the Peruvians, and all uncivilised people are represented as the inferior races, unfit to associate with the former on terms of equality, unfit to intermarry with them on any terms, unfit for any decisive voice in human affairs. In the popular imagination of Western Europe, the Chinese are becoming bright gamboge in colour, and unspeakably abominable in every respect; the people who are black—the people who have fuzzy hair and flattish noses, and no calves to speak of—are no longer held to be within the pale of humanity. These superstitions work out along the obvious lines of the popular logic. The depopulation of the Congo Free State by the Belgians, the horrible massacres of Chinese by European soldiery during the Pekin expedition, are condoned as a painful but necessary part of the civilising process of the world. The world-wide repudiation of slavery in the nineteenth century was done against a vast sullen force of ignorant pride, which, reinvigorated by the new delusions, swings back again to power.

No generalizations about race are too extreme for the heightened gullibility of today. There's never any effort to separate genuine differences in quality—the real racial differences—from the artificial ones created by culture. No lessons seem to be learned from history about how the process of civilization has shifted from one race to another over time. The currently powerful groups are viewed as the superior races, which includes individuals like the Sussex farmworker, the Bowery tough, the London thug, and the Parisian apache; while those races that are currently struggling politically, like the Egyptians, Greeks, Spaniards, Moors, Chinese, Hindus, Peruvians, and all uncivilized people are seen as inferior, unworthy of equality, unworthy of intermarriage, and unworthy of having any significant say in global matters. In the common perception in Western Europe, the Chinese are viewed as a vivid yellow and are considered horrifically undesirable in every sense; those who are black—who have curly hair, flattened noses, and little to no calves—are increasingly seen as outside the realm of humanity. These beliefs evolve along the familiar lines of popular reasoning. The depopulation of the Congo Free State by the Belgians and the brutal killings of Chinese by European soldiers during the Peking expedition are excused as painful but necessary steps in the world's civilizing process. The global rejection of slavery in the nineteenth century faced a massive, discontented force of ignorant pride that, fueled by these new delusions, is swinging back into power.

“Science” is supposed to lend its sanction to race mania, but it is only “science” as it is understood by very illiterate people that does anything of the sort—“scientists'” science, in fact. What science has to tell about “The Races of Man” will be found compactly set forth by Doctor J. Deinker, in the book published under that title. [Footnote: See also an excellent paper in the American Journal of Sociology for March, 1904, The Psychology of Race Prejudice, by W. I. Thomas.] From that book one may learn the beginnings of race charity. Save for a few isolated pools of savage humanity, there is probably no pure race in the whole world. The great continental populations are all complex mixtures of numerous and fluctuating types. Even the Jews present every kind of skull that is supposed to be racially distinctive, a vast range of complexion—from blackness in Goa, to extreme fairness in Holland—and a vast mental and physical diversity. Were the Jews to discontinue all intermarriage with “other races” henceforth for ever, it would depend upon quite unknown laws of fecundity, prepotency, and variability, what their final type would be, or, indeed, whether any particular type would ever prevail over diversity. And, without going beyond the natives of the British Isles, one can discover an enormous range of types, tall and short, straight-haired and curly, fair and dark, supremely intelligent and unteachably stupid, straightforward, disingenuous, and what not. The natural tendency is to forget all this range directly “race” comes under discussion, to take either an average or some quite arbitrary ideal as the type, and think only of that. The more difficult thing to do, but the thing that must be done if we are to get just results in this discussion, is to do one's best to bear the range in mind.

“Science” is said to support race obsession, but it’s only “science” as understood by very uneducated people that does anything like that—“scientists'” science, actually. What science really says about “The Races of Man” is clearly outlined by Doctor J. Deinker in the book published under that title. [Footnote: See also an excellent paper in the American Journal of Sociology for March 1904, The Psychology of Race Prejudice, by W. I. Thomas.] From that book, you can learn the origins of race compassion. Aside from a few isolated pockets of primitive humanity, there’s probably no pure race in the entire world. The major populations on each continent are all complex mixtures of various and changing types. Even the Jews display every kind of skull that’s thought to be racially distinctive, a wide range of skin tones—from blackness in Goa to extreme fairness in Holland—and a great mental and physical diversity. If Jews were to stop all intermarriage with “other races” forever, what their final type would be, or if any specific type would even dominate over diversity, would depend on unknown laws of fertility, dominance, and variability. And just looking at the natives of the British Isles, one can find an enormous variety of types: tall and short, straight-haired and curly, fair and dark, highly intelligent and utterly ignorant, straightforward, deceitful, and so on. The natural tendency is to forget all this variety as soon as “race” comes up, to assume either an average or some completely arbitrary ideal as the type, and focus only on that. The more challenging thing to do, but necessary if we want fair outcomes in this discussion, is to do our best to remember the range of differences.

Let us admit that the average Chinaman is probably different in complexion, and, indeed, in all his physical and psychical proportions, from the average Englishman. Does that render their association upon terms of equality in a World State impossible? What the average Chinaman or Englishman may be, is of no importance whatever to our plan of a World State. It is not averages that exist, but individuals. The average Chinaman will never meet the average Englishman anywhere; only individual Chinamen will meet individual Englishmen. Now among Chinamen will be found a range of variety as extensive as among Englishmen, and there is no single trait presented by all Chinamen and no Englishman, or vice versa. Even the oblique eye is not universal in China, and there are probably many Chinamen who might have been “changed at birth,” taken away and educated into quite passable Englishmen. Even after we have separated out and allowed for the differences in carriage, physique, moral prepossessions, and so forth, due to their entirely divergent cultures, there remains, no doubt, a very great difference between the average Chinaman and the average Englishman; but would that amount to a wider difference than is to be found between extreme types of Englishmen?

Let’s acknowledge that the average Chinese person likely differs in complexion and, indeed, in all their physical and psychological traits from the average English person. Does that make it impossible for them to interact as equals in a World State? What the average Chinese person or English person is does not matter at all to our vision of a World State. It’s not averages that exist; it’s individuals. The average Chinese person will never encounter the average English person anywhere; only individual Chinese people will meet individual English people. Among Chinese people, there is a variety as broad as among English people, and there’s no single characteristic shared by all Chinese people that isn’t also found in English people, and vice versa. Even the characteristic of having slanted eyes isn’t universal in China, and there are likely many Chinese people who could have been “switched at birth,” taken away, and raised to be quite acceptable English people. Even after accounting for the differences in posture, physique, moral attitudes, and so on, due to their completely different cultures, there is undoubtedly still a significant difference between the average Chinese person and the average English person; but would that difference be greater than the variation found among the most extreme types of English people?

For my own part I do not think that it would. But it is evident that any precise answer can be made only when anthropology has adopted much more exact and exhaustive methods of inquiry, and a far more precise analysis than its present resources permit.

For my part, I don't think it would. However, it's clear that any definitive answer can only be given once anthropology has adopted much more accurate and thorough methods of inquiry, and has a much more detailed analysis than its current resources allow.

Be it remembered how doubtful and tainted is the bulk of our evidence in these matters. These are extraordinarily subtle inquiries, from which few men succeed in disentangling the threads of their personal associations—the curiously interwoven strands of self-love and self-interest that affect their inquiries. One might almost say that instinct fights against such investigations, as it does undoubtedly against many necessary medical researches. But while a long special training, a high tradition and the possibility of reward and distinction, enable the medical student to face many tasks that are at once undignified and physically repulsive, the people from whom we get our anthropological information are rarely men of more than average intelligence, and of no mental training at all. And the problems are far more elusive. It surely needs at least the gifts and training of a first-class novelist, combined with a sedulous patience that probably cannot be hoped for in combination with these, to gauge the all-round differences between man and man. Even where there are no barriers of language and colour, understanding may be nearly impossible. How few educated people seem to understand the servant class in England, or the working men! Except for Mr. Bart Kennedy's A Man Adrift, I know of scarcely any book that shows a really sympathetic and living understanding of the navvy, the longshore sailor man, the rough chap of our own race. Caricatures, luridly tragic or gaily comic, in which the misconceptions of the author blend with the preconceptions of the reader and achieve success, are, of course, common enough. And then consider the sort of people who pronounce judgments on the moral and intellectual capacity of the negro, the Malay, or the Chinaman. You have missionaries, native schoolmasters, employers of coolies, traders, simple downright men, who scarcely suspect the existence of any sources of error in their verdicts, who are incapable of understanding the difference between what is innate and what is acquired, much less of distinguishing them in their interplay. Now and then one seems to have a glimpse of something really living—in Mary Kingsley's buoyant work, for instance—and even that may be no more than my illusion.

Remember how uncertain and questionable most of our evidence is in these matters. These inquiries are extremely subtle, and few people manage to untangle their personal biases—the intricately woven threads of self-love and self-interest that influence their investigations. One might almost say that instinct resists such inquiries, just as it undoubtedly does against many necessary medical studies. However, while extensive training, a strong tradition, and the chance for recognition and reward allow medical students to tackle many tasks that are both undignified and physically unpleasant, the individuals from whom we gather our anthropological insights are rarely more than average in intelligence and have no mental training at all. Moreover, the issues at hand are much more elusive. It truly requires the talents and training of a top-notch novelist, along with a level of patience that likely cannot be expected alongside those talents, to understand the broad differences among people. Even when there are no barriers of language or race, understanding can be nearly impossible. How few educated people seem to truly grasp the servant class in England or the working class! Aside from Mr. Bart Kennedy's A Man Adrift, I know of hardly any book that captures a genuinely sympathetic and dynamic understanding of the laborer, the dock worker, or the rough man of our own culture. Caricatures, whether tragically exaggerated or humorously light, in which the author's misconceptions mix with the reader's assumptions to achieve success, are, of course, quite common. And think about the kinds of people who make judgments on the moral and intellectual capacities of Black individuals, Malays, or Chinese. These are missionaries, local teachers, employers of laborers, traders, and straightforward men who hardly suspect any sources of error in their conclusions. They are unable to differentiate between what is innate and what is learned, much less distinguish them in their interaction. Occasionally, one seems to glimpse something truly alive—in Mary Kingsley's vibrant work, for instance—and even that might just be my illusion.

For my own part I am disposed to discount all adverse judgments and all statements of insurmountable differences between race and race. I talk upon racial qualities to all men who have had opportunities of close observation, and I find that their insistence upon these differences is usually in inverse proportion to their intelligence. It may be the chance of my encounters, but that is my clear impression. Common sailors will generalise in the profoundest way about Irishmen, and Scotchmen, and Yankees, and Nova Scotians, and “Dutchies,” until one might think one talked of different species of animal, but the educated explorer flings clear of all these delusions. To him men present themselves individualised, and if they classify it is by some skin-deep accident of tint, some trick of the tongue, or habit of gesture, or such-like superficiality. And after all there exists to-day available one kind at least of unbiassed anthropological evidence. There are photographs. Let the reader turn over the pages of some such copiously illustrated work as The Living Races of Mankind, [Footnote: The Living Races of Mankind, by H. N. Hutchinson, J. W. Gregory, and R. Lydekker. (Hutchinson.)] and look into the eyes of one alien face after another. Are they not very like the people one knows? For the most part, one finds it hard to believe that, with a common language and common social traditions, one would not get on very well with these people. Here or there is a brutish or evil face, but you can find as brutish and evil in the Strand on any afternoon. There are differences no doubt, but fundamental incompatibilities—no! And very many of them send out a ray of special resemblance and remind one more strongly of this friend or that, than they do of their own kind. One notes with surprise that one's good friend and neighbour X and an anonymous naked Gold Coast negro belong to one type, as distinguished from one's dear friend Y and a beaming individual from Somaliland, who as certainly belong to another.

For my part, I tend to ignore all negative opinions and claims about unbridgeable differences between races. I discuss racial traits with anyone who has had the chance to observe closely, and I've noticed that the stronger their focus on these differences, the lower their intelligence tends to be. It could just be my experiences, but that's how I see it. Regular sailors will make sweeping generalizations about Irish, Scottish, American, and Nova Scotian people, and even "Dutchies," as if they were talking about different species, while educated travelers move past these misconceptions. To them, people appear as individuals, and if they do categorize, it’s based on superficial differences like skin color, accents, or gestures. And today, there’s at least one source of unbiased anthropological evidence: photographs. Let the reader flip through a well-illustrated book like The Living Races of Mankind, [Footnote: The Living Races of Mankind, by H. N. Hutchinson, J. W. Gregory, and R. Lydekker. (Hutchinson.)] and observe the faces in the pictures. Don’t they look a lot like the people you know? Generally, it’s hard to believe that, with a shared language and similar social customs, we wouldn’t get along well with these individuals. Sure, there are some brutish or unkind faces, but you can find just as many on the Strand on any given afternoon. There are certainly differences, but fundamental incompatibilities—no! Many of them even seem to resemble certain friends more closely than they do their own groups. It’s surprising to realize that your good friend and neighbor X and an anonymous naked man from the Gold Coast share one type, while your dear friend Y and a cheerful person from Somaliland belong to a completely different type.

In one matter the careless and prejudiced nature of accepted racial generalisations is particularly marked. A great and increasing number of people are persuaded that “half-breeds” are peculiarly evil creatures—as hunchbacks and bastards were supposed to be in the middle ages. The full legend of the wickedness of the half-breed is best to be learnt from a drunken mean white from Virginia or the Cape. The half-breed, one hears, combines all the vices of either parent, he is wretchedly poor in health and spirit, but vindictive, powerful, and dangerous to an extreme degree, his morals—the mean white has high and exacting standards—are indescribable even in whispers in a saloon, and so on, and so on. There is really not an atom of evidence an unprejudiced mind would accept to sustain any belief of the sort. There is nothing to show that the children of racial admixture are, as a class, inherently either better or worse in any respect than either parent. There is an equally baseless theory that they are better, a theory displayed to a fine degree of foolishness in the article on Shakespeare in the Encyclopædia Britannica. Both theories belong to the vast edifice of sham science that smothers the realities of modern knowledge. It may be that most “half-breeds” are failures in life, but that proves nothing. They are, in an enormous number of cases, illegitimate and outcast from the normal education of either race; they are brought up in homes that are the battle-grounds of conflicting cultures; they labour under a heavy premium of disadvantage. There is, of course, a passing suggestion of Darwin's to account for atavism that might go to support the theory of the vileness of half-breeds, if it had ever been proved. But, then, it never has been proved. There is no proof in the matter at all.

In one area, the careless and biased nature of common racial stereotypes is especially clear. A significant and growing number of people believe that “mixed-race individuals” are particularly evil, much like how hunchbacks and illegitimate children were viewed in the Middle Ages. You can learn the full story of the wickedness attributed to mixed-race individuals from a drunken, bitter white person from Virginia or the Cape. They say the mixed-race person embodies all the negative traits of both parents, is woefully poor in health and spirit, yet is also vindictive, powerful, and extremely dangerous. Their morals—according to the critical white person—are unspeakable, even when whispered in a bar, and so on. In reality, there's not a shred of evidence that an unbiased mind would accept to support this belief. There's nothing to indicate that children of mixed race are, as a group, inherently better or worse in any way compared to either parent. There's an equally unfounded theory that they are better, which is shown to be quite foolish in the article about Shakespeare in the Encyclopædia Britannica. Both theories are part of the vast structure of false science that obscures the truths of modern knowledge. It may be that most “mixed-race individuals” face difficulties in life, but that doesn’t prove anything. Many are illegitimate and excluded from the normal education of either race; they grow up in homes that are battlegrounds of conflicting cultures and carry a heavy burden of disadvantage. There’s a fleeting mention of Darwin’s ideas about atavism that could support the theory of mixed-race individuals being vile, but that has never been proven. In fact, there is no proof at all on the subject.

§ 3

Suppose, now, there is such a thing as an all-round inferior race. Is that any reason why we should propose to preserve it for ever in a condition of tutelage? Whether there is a race so inferior I do not know, but certainly there is no race so superior as to be trusted with human charges. The true answer to Aristotle's plea for slavery, that there are “natural slaves,” lies in the fact that there are no “natural” masters. Power is no more to be committed to men without discipline and restriction than alcohol. The true objection to slavery is not that it is unjust to the inferior but that it corrupts the superior. There is only one sane and logical thing to be done with a really inferior race, and that is to exterminate it.

Suppose there is indeed an all-around inferior race. Does that mean we should keep it permanently in a state of dependency? I don't know if such a race exists, but for sure, there isn't a race so superior that it can be trusted with the responsibility of others. The real response to Aristotle's argument for slavery, that there are "natural slaves," lies in the fact that there are no "natural" masters. Power shouldn't be handed over to people without discipline and limits any more than alcohol should. The main issue with slavery isn't just that it's unfair to the inferior but that it corrupts the superior. The only reasonable and logical thing to do with a truly inferior race would be to eliminate it.

Now there are various ways of exterminating a race, and most of them are cruel. You may end it with fire and sword after the old Hebrew fashion; you may enslave it and work it to death, as the Spaniards did the Caribs; you may set it boundaries and then poison it slowly with deleterious commodities, as the Americans do with most of their Indians; you may incite it to wear clothing to which it is not accustomed and to live under new and strange conditions that will expose it to infectious diseases to which you yourselves are immune, as the missionaries do the Polynesians; you may resort to honest simple murder, as we English did with the Tasmanians; or you can maintain such conditions as conduce to “race suicide,” as the British administration does in Fiji. Suppose, then, for a moment, that there is an all-round inferior race; a Modern Utopia is under the hard logic of life, and it would have to exterminate such a race as quickly as it could. On the whole, the Fijian device seems the least cruel. But Utopia would do that without any clumsiness of race distinction, in exactly the same manner, and by the same machinery, as it exterminates all its own defective and inferior strains; that is to say, as we have already discussed in Chapter the Fifth, § 1, by its marriage laws, and by the laws of the minimum wage. That extinction need never be discriminatory. If any of the race did, after all, prove to be fit to survive, they would survive—they would be picked out with a sure and automatic justice from the over-ready condemnation of all their kind.

Now there are various ways to wipe out a race, and most of them are brutal. You could do it with violence like the old Hebrews; you might enslave them and work them to death, as the Spaniards did with the Caribs; you could set boundaries and then slowly poison them with harmful goods, like how Americans have treated many of their Native Americans; you might force them to wear unfamiliar clothing and live under new and strange conditions, exposing them to diseases that you yourself are immune to, like missionaries have done with the Polynesians; you could simply murder them outright, like the English did with the Tasmanians; or you can create circumstances that lead to "race suicide," as the British administration does in Fiji. Now, let’s imagine for a moment that there is a universally inferior race; a Modern Utopia, shaped by the harsh realities of life, would have to eliminate such a race as quickly as possible. Overall, the approach used in Fiji seems the least cruel. But Utopia would do this without any awkward racial distinctions, in exactly the same way it eliminates all its own defective and inferior members; that is to say, as we discussed in Chapter the Fifth, § 1, through its marriage laws and minimum wage laws. That extinction wouldn’t need to be selective. If any individuals from that race were actually fit to survive, they would survive—selected with an automatic fairness from the blanket condemnation of their kind.

Is there, however, an all-round inferior race in the world? Even the Australian black-fellow is, perhaps, not quite so entirely eligible for extinction as a good, wholesome, horse-racing, sheep-farming Australian white may think. These queer little races, the black-fellows, the Pigmies, the Bushmen, may have their little gifts, a greater keenness, a greater fineness of this sense or that, a quaintness of the imagination or what not, that may serve as their little unique addition to the totality of our Utopian civilisation. We are supposing that every individual alive on earth is alive in Utopia, and so all the surviving “black-fellows” are there. Every one of them in Utopia has had what none have had on earth, a fair education and fair treatment, justice, and opportunity. Suppose that the common idea is right about the general inferiority of these people, then it would follow that in Utopia most of them are childless, and working at or about the minimum wage, and some will have passed out of all possibility of offspring under the hand of the offended law; but still—cannot we imagine some few of these little people—whom you must suppose neither naked nor clothed in the European style, but robed in the Utopian fashion—may have found some delicate art to practise, some peculiar sort of carving, for example, that justifies God in creating them? Utopia has sound sanitary laws, sound social laws, sound economic laws; what harm are these people going to do?

Is there really an entirely inferior race in the world? Even the Australian Aboriginal might not be as completely destined for extinction as a typical, wholesome, horse-racing, sheep-farming Australian might believe. These unique little groups, the Aboriginals, the Pigmies, the Bushmen, could have their distinct talents, a sharper insight, a finer sensitivity in one area or another, a whimsical imagination or something else, that adds their unique contributions to the overall fabric of our ideal civilization. We're assuming that every individual living on earth exists in a utopia, and so all the surviving “Aboriginals” are there. Each of them in utopia has experienced what nobody on earth has: a fair education, fair treatment, justice, and opportunity. If we accept the common belief about the general inferiority of these people, it would follow that in utopia, most of them are childless, working at or near minimum wage, and some may be unable to have children due to the constraints of the law; but still—can we not envision a few of these small individuals—who you must imagine are neither naked nor dressed in European styles, but clothed in a Utopian way—might have discovered some delicate art to practice, perhaps a specific kind of carving, that justifies their creation? Utopia has strong sanitary, social, and economic laws; what harm could these people possibly cause?

Some may be even prosperous and admired, may have married women of their own or some other race, and so may be transmitting that distinctive thin thread of excellence, to take its due place in the great synthesis of the future.

Some might even be successful and respected, may have married women from their own or different backgrounds, and thus might be passing on that unique thread of excellence, to find its rightful place in the greater synthesis of the future.

And, indeed, coming along that terrace in Utopia, I see a little figure, a little bright-eyed, bearded man, inky black, frizzy haired, and clad in a white tunic and black hose, and with a mantle of lemon yellow wrapped about his shoulders. He walks, as most Utopians walk, as though he had reason to be proud of something, as though he had no reason to be afraid of anything in the world. He carries a portfolio in his hand. It is that, I suppose, as much as his hair, that recalls the Quartier Latin to my mind.

And as I walk along that terrace in Utopia, I see a small figure, a bright-eyed little man with a beard, jet black, frizzy hair, dressed in a white tunic and black leggings, and wrapped in a lemon yellow cloak. He moves, like most Utopians, as if he has every reason to be proud of something and no reason to fear anything in the world. He holds a portfolio in his hand. I suppose it’s that, along with his hair, that reminds me of the Quartier Latin.

§ 4

I had already discussed the question of race with the botanist at Lucerne.

I had already talked about the issue of race with the botanist in Lucerne.

“But you would not like,” he cried in horror, “your daughter to marry a Chinaman or a negro?”

“But you wouldn’t want,” he exclaimed in shock, “your daughter to marry a Chinese man or a Black man?”

“Of course,” said I, “when you say Chinaman, you think of a creature with a pigtail, long nails, and insanitary habits, and when you say negro you think of a filthy-headed, black creature in an old hat. You do this because your imagination is too feeble to disentangle the inherent qualities of a thing from its habitual associations.”

“Of course,” I said, “when you say Chinese person, you picture someone with a pigtail, long nails, and poor hygiene, and when you say Black person, you imagine a dirty-headed, Black individual in an old hat. You do this because your imagination is too weak to separate the true characteristics of a person from the stereotypes attached to them.”

“Insult isn't argument,” said the botanist.

“Insult isn’t an argument,” said the botanist.

“Neither is unsound implication. You make a question of race into a question of unequal cultures. You would not like your daughter to marry the sort of negro who steals hens, but then you would also not like your daughter to marry a pure English hunchback with a squint, or a drunken cab tout of Norman blood. As a matter of fact, very few well-bred English girls do commit that sort of indiscretion. But you don't think it necessary to generalise against men of your own race because there are drunken cab touts, and why should you generalise against negroes? Because the proportion of undesirables is higher among negroes, that does not justify a sweeping condemnation. You may have to condemn most, but why all? There may be—neither of us knows enough to deny—negroes who are handsome, capable, courageous.”

“Neither is it a sound assumption. You turn a question of race into a question of different cultures. You wouldn't want your daughter to marry the type of Black man who steals chickens, but you also wouldn't want her to marry a pure English hunchback with a squint, or a drunken cab driver of Norman descent. In reality, very few well-bred English girls make that kind of mistake. But you don’t feel the need to generalize about men of your own race just because there are drunken cab drivers, so why should you generalize about Black men? Just because there are more undesirable individuals among Black people, that doesn’t justify condemning all of them. You may have to criticize most, but why all? There may be—neither of us knows enough to say otherwise—Black people who are attractive, skilled, and brave.”

“Ugh!” said the botanist.

“Ugh!” said the plant expert.

“How detestable you must find Othello!”

“How terrible you must find Othello!”

It is my Utopia, and for a moment I could almost find it in my heart to spite the botanist by creating a modern Desdemona and her lover sooty black to the lips, there before our eyes. But I am not so sure of my case as that, and for the moment there shall come nothing more than a swart-faced, dusky Burmese woman in the dress of the Greater Rule, with her tall Englishman (as he might be on earth) at her side. That, however, is a digression from my conversation with the botanist.

It is my perfect world, and for a moment, I could almost bring myself to annoy the botanist by creating a modern Desdemona and her lover, dark-skinned to the lips, right before us. But I’m not as certain of my argument as that, and for now, all I’ll create is a dark-skinned Burmese woman in the attire of the Greater Rule, with her tall Englishman (as he might appear on earth) next to her. That, however, is a sidetrack from my discussion with the botanist.

“And the Chinaman?” said the botanist.

“And the Chinese guy?” said the botanist.

“I think we shall have all the buff and yellow peoples intermingling pretty freely.”

“I think we will see all the buff and yellow people mixing together quite freely.”

“Chinamen and white women, for example.”

“Chinese men and white women, for example.”

“Yes,” I said, “you've got to swallow that, anyhow; you shall swallow that.”

“Yes,” I said, “you have to accept that, anyway; you will accept that.”

He finds the idea too revolting for comment.

He thinks the idea is too disgusting to even comment on.

I try and make the thing seem easier for him. “Do try,” I said, “to grasp a Modern Utopian's conditions. The Chinaman will speak the same language as his wife—whatever her race may be—he will wear costume of the common civilised fashion, he will have much the same education as his European rival, read the same literature, bow to the same traditions. And you must remember a wife in Utopia is singularly not subject to her husband....”

I try to make it easier for him. “Please try,” I said, “to understand the conditions of a Modern Utopian. The Chinese man will speak the same language as his wife—regardless of her race—he will wear clothing that’s considered normal in civilized society, he will have a similar education to his European counterpart, read the same books, and follow the same traditions. And you need to remember that in Utopia, a wife is notably not under her husband’s authority…”

The botanist proclaims his invincible conclusion: “Everyone would cut her!”

The botanist declares his unshakeable conclusion: “Everyone would cut her!”

“This is Utopia,” I said, and then sought once more to tranquillise his mind. “No doubt among the vulgar, coarse-minded people outside the Rule there may be something of the sort. Every earthly moral blockhead, a little educated, perhaps, is to be found in Utopia. You will, no doubt, find the ‘cut’ and the ‘boycott,’ and all those nice little devices by which dull people get a keen edge on life, in their place here, and their place here is somewhere―”

“This is Utopia,” I said, and then tried again to calm his mind. “Surely among the ignorant, narrow-minded folks outside the Rule, there might be something like that. You can find every earthly moral fool, maybe a bit educated, in Utopia. You will likely encounter the ‘cut’ and the ‘boycott,’ and all those clever little tricks that dull people use to get an advantage in life, and their place here is somewhere—”

I turned a thumb earthward. “There!”

I pointed my thumb down. “There!”

The botanist did not answer for a little while. Then he said, with some temper and great emphasis: “Well, I'm jolly glad anyhow that I'm not to be a permanent resident in this Utopia, if our daughters are to be married to Hottentots by regulation. I'm jolly glad.”

The botanist took a moment before responding. Then he said, with some irritation and strong emphasis: “Well, I’m really glad, anyway, that I’m not going to be a permanent resident in this Utopia, if our daughters are supposed to marry Hottentots by rule. I’m really glad.”

He turned his back on me.

He turned away from me.

Now did I say anything of the sort?...

Now did I say anything like that?...

I had to bring him, I suppose; there's no getting away from him in this life. But, as I have already observed, the happy ancients went to their Utopias without this sort of company.

I guess I had to bring him along; there's no escaping him in this life. But, as I've already pointed out, the happy people of the past went to their perfect worlds without this kind of company.

§ 5

What gives the botanist so great an advantage in all his Anti-Utopian utterances is his unconsciousness of his own limitations. He thinks in little pieces that lie about loose, and nothing has any necessary link with anything else in his mind. So that I cannot retort upon him by asking him, if he objects to this synthesis of all nations, tongues and peoples in a World State, what alternative ideal he proposes.

What gives the botanist such an advantage in all his Anti-Utopian comments is that he is unaware of his own limitations. He thinks in random bits that are scattered everywhere, and nothing in his mind is necessarily connected to anything else. This means I can't push back by asking him, if he opposes this combination of all nations, languages, and peoples in a World State, what alternative ideal he suggests.

People of this sort do not even feel the need of alternatives. Beyond the scope of a few personal projects, meeting Her again, and things like that, they do not feel that there is a future. They are unencumbered by any baggage of convictions whatever, in relation to that. That, at least, is the only way in which I can explain our friend's high intellectual mobility. Attempts to correlate statesmanship, which they regard with interest as a dramatic interplay of personalities, with any secular movement of humanity, they class with the differential calculus and Darwinism, as things far too difficult to be anything but finally and subtly wrong.

People like this don’t even see the need for alternatives. Aside from a couple of personal projects, meeting her again, and similar things, they don’t think there’s a future. They’re not weighed down by any beliefs about that. At least, that’s the only way I can make sense of our friend’s strong intellectual flexibility. They view statesmanship, which they find interesting as a dramatic exchange of personalities, and try to link it to any social movement of humanity, but they just group it with differential calculus and Darwinism—as things too complex to be anything but ultimately and subtly incorrect.

So the argument must pass into a direct address to the reader.

So the argument has to shift to a direct address to the reader.

If you are not prepared to regard a world-wide synthesis of all cultures and polities and races into one World State as the desirable end upon which all civilising efforts converge, what do you regard as the desirable end? Synthesis, one may remark in passing, does not necessarily mean fusion, nor does it mean uniformity.

If you don't see a global integration of all cultures, governments, and races into one World State as the ideal goal that all civilizing efforts aim for, what do you consider the ideal goal? It's worth noting that integration doesn't have to mean merging or sameness.

The alternatives fall roughly under three headings. The first is to assume there is a best race, to define as well as one can that best race, and to regard all other races as material for extermination. This has a fine, modern, biological air (“Survival of the Fittest”). If you are one of those queer German professors who write insanity about Welt-Politik, you assume the best race is the “Teutonic”; Cecil Rhodes affected that triumph of creative imagination, the “Anglo-Saxon race”; my friend, Moses Cohen, thinks there is much to be said for the Jew. On its premises, this is a perfectly sound and reasonable policy, and it opens out a brilliant prospect for the scientific inventor for what one might call Welt-Apparat in the future, for national harrowing and reaping machines, and race-destroying fumigations. The great plain of China (“Yellow Peril”) lends itself particularly to some striking wholesale undertaking; it might, for example, be flooded for a few days, and then disinfected with volcanic chlorine. Whether, when all the inferior races have been stamped out, the superior race would not proceed at once, or after a brief millennial period of social harmony, to divide itself into sub-classes, and begin the business over again at a higher level, is an interesting residual question into which we need not now penetrate.

The alternatives can be grouped into three main categories. The first is to assume that there is a superior race, to define that superior race as accurately as possible, and to view all other races as targets for extermination. This concept has a modern, scientific vibe (“Survival of the Fittest”). If you’re one of those strange German professors who write nonsense about world politics, you might assume that the superior race is the “Teutonic”; Cecil Rhodes imagined the triumph of the “Anglo-Saxon race”; my friend, Moses Cohen, believes there’s a strong case for the Jewish race. Based on its premises, this is a perfectly logical and rational policy, and it opens up an exciting future for scientific inventors who might create what could be called world apparatus for national farming and harvesting machines, and race-eradicating fumigations. The vast expanse of China (“Yellow Peril”) seems particularly suited for some bold large-scale initiatives; for instance, it could be flooded for several days and then sanitized with volcanic chlorine. Whether, once all the inferior races have been eliminated, the superior race would eventually start to divide into subclasses and begin the process anew at a higher level is an intriguing leftover question we won’t delve into right now.

That complete development of a scientific Welt-Politik is not, however, very widely advocated at present, no doubt from a want of confidence in the public imagination. We have, however, a very audible and influential school, the Modern Imperialist school, which distinguishes its own race—there is a German, a British, and an Anglo-Saxon section in the school, and a wider teaching which embraces the whole “white race” in one remarkable tolerance—as the superior race, as one, indeed, superior enough to own slaves, collectively, if not individually; and the exponents of this doctrine look with a resolute, truculent, but slightly indistinct eye to a future in which all the rest of the world will be in subjection to these elect. The ideals of this type are set forth pretty clearly in Mr. Kidd's Control of the Tropics. The whole world is to be administered by the “white” Powers—Mr. Kidd did not anticipate Japan—who will see to it that their subjects do not “prevent the utilisation of the immense natural resources which they have in charge.” Those other races are to be regarded as children, recalcitrant children at times, and without any of the tender emotions of paternity. It is a little doubtful whether the races lacking “in the elementary qualities of social efficiency” are expected to acquire them under the chastening hands of those races which, through “strength and energy of character, humanity, probity, and integrity, and a single-minded devotion to conceptions of duty,” are developing “the resources of the richest regions of the earth” over their heads, or whether this is the ultimate ideal.

The complete development of a scientific world politics isn’t widely supported right now, likely due to a lack of trust in the public’s imagination. However, there is a prominent and influential group, the Modern Imperialist school, which promotes its own race—there’s a German section, a British section, and an Anglo-Saxon section, along with a broader perspective that includes the entire “white race” in a surprising show of tolerance—as the superior race, one indeed superior enough to collectively own slaves, if not individually; and the advocates of this idea look with a resolute, aggressive, but somewhat unclear vision toward a future where the rest of the world will be under the control of these chosen ones. The ideals of this group are laid out quite clearly in Mr. Kidd's Control of the Tropics. The whole world is meant to be governed by the “white” powers—Mr. Kidd didn’t foresee Japan—who will ensure that their subjects do not “prevent the utilization of the immense natural resources they manage.” Those other races are viewed as children, sometimes rebellious, without any of the caring feelings of parenthood. It’s somewhat unclear whether the races lacking “the basic qualities of social efficiency” are expected to develop those qualities under the strict guidance of those races which, through “strength and energy of character, humanity, integrity, and a focused commitment to duty,” are exploiting “the resources of the richest regions of the earth” above them, or if this is the ultimate goal.

Next comes the rather incoherent alternative that one associates in England with official Liberalism.

Next comes the rather unclear alternative that one connects in England with official Liberalism.

Liberalism in England is not quite the same thing as Liberalism in the rest of the world; it is woven of two strands. There is Whiggism, the powerful tradition of seventeenth-century Protestant and republican England, with its great debt to republican Rome, its strong constructive and disciplinary bias, its broad and originally very living and intelligent outlook; and interwoven with this there is the sentimental and logical Liberalism that sprang from the stresses of the eighteenth century, that finds its early scarce differentiated expression in Harrington's Oceana, and after fresh draughts of the tradition of Brutus and Cato and some elegant trifling with noble savages, budded in La Cité Morellyste, flowered in the emotional democratic naturalism of Rousseau, and bore abundant fruit in the French Revolution. These are two very distinct strands. Directly they were freed in America from the grip of conflict with British Toryism, they came apart as the Republican and Democratic parties respectively. Their continued union in Great Britain is a political accident. Because of this mixture, the whole career of English-speaking Liberalism, though it has gone to one unbroken strain of eloquence, has never produced a clear statement of policy in relation to other peoples politically less fortunate. It has developed no definite ideas at all about the future of mankind. The Whig disposition, which once had some play in India, was certainly to attempt to anglicise the “native,” to assimilate his culture, and then to assimilate his political status with that of his temporary ruler. But interwoven with this anglicising tendency, which was also, by the bye, a Christianising tendency, was a strong disposition, derived from the Rousseau strand, to leave other peoples alone, to facilitate even the separation and autonomy of detached portions of our own peoples, to disintegrate finally into perfect, because lawless, individuals. The official exposition of British “Liberalism” to-day still wriggles unstably because of these conflicting constituents, but on the whole the Whig strand now seems the weaker. The contemporary Liberal politician offers cogent criticism upon the brutality and conceit of modern imperialisms, but that seems to be the limit of his service. Taking what they do not say and do not propose as an indication of Liberal intentions, it would seem that the ideal of the British Liberals and of the American Democrats is to favour the existence of just as many petty, loosely allied, or quite independent nationalities as possible, just as many languages as possible, to deprecate armies and all controls, and to trust to the innate goodness of disorder and the powers of an ardent sentimentality to keep the world clean and sweet. The Liberals will not face the plain consequence that such a state of affairs is hopelessly unstable, that it involves the maximum risk of war with the minimum of permanent benefit and public order. They will not reflect that the stars in their courses rule inexorably against it. It is a vague, impossible ideal, with a rude sort of unworldly moral beauty, like the gospel of the Doukhobors. Besides that charm it has this most seductive quality to an official British Liberal, that it does not exact intellectual activity nor indeed activity of any sort whatever. It is, by virtue of that alone, a far less mischievous doctrine than the crude and violent Imperialism of the popular Press.

Liberalism in England isn't exactly the same as Liberalism elsewhere; it's made up of two distinct elements. One is Whiggism, the strong tradition from seventeenth-century Protestant and republican England, which owes a lot to republican Rome, emphasizing constructive and disciplinary values, along with a broad and originally vibrant and intelligent perspective. The other element is the sentimental and logical Liberalism that emerged from the tensions of the eighteenth century, first expressed in Harrington's Oceana, evolving with influences from the likes of Brutus and Cato, leading to La Cité Morellyste, blooming in the emotional democratic naturalism of Rousseau, and bearing fruit in the French Revolution. These are two very distinct elements. Once freed in America from the conflicts with British Toryism, they split into the Republican and Democratic parties. Their ongoing connection in Great Britain is merely a political coincidence. Because of this combination, the entire trajectory of English-speaking Liberalism, despite being a continuous flow of eloquence, has struggled to produce a clear policy statement about less politically fortunate nations. It hasn't developed any solid ideas about the future of humanity. The Whig inclination, which once had some influence in India, was clearly to attempt to anglicize the “natives,” to assimilate their cultures, and then to align their political status with that of their temporary rulers. However, intertwined with this anglicizing, which also had a Christian aspect, was a strong tendency from the Rousseau element to leave other people alone, to encourage even the separation and autonomy of different parts of our own populations, ultimately leading to a breakdown into completely, albeit lawlessly, independent individuals. The current articulation of British “Liberalism” today still struggles to find stability because of these conflicting elements, but overall the Whig aspect now appears weaker. Today's Liberal politicians provide sharp critiques of the brutality and arrogance of modern imperialism, but that seems to be the extent of their contribution. By considering what they don’t say or propose as a clue to Liberal intentions, it seems that the goal of British Liberals and American Democrats is to promote the existence of as many small, loosely connected, or entirely independent nations as possible, as many languages as possible, to discourage militaries and all forms of control, and to rely on the innate goodness of chaos and a strong sense of sentimentality to keep the world clean and pleasant. Liberals refuse to acknowledge that such a situation is hopelessly unstable, that it carries the highest risk of war with the least amount of lasting benefit and public order. They won’t reflect on the fact that the stars in their courses inevitably work against it. It’s a vague and unrealistic ideal, possessing a rough sort of unearthly moral beauty, like the teachings of the Doukhobors. Besides that charm, it has the alluring quality for an official British Liberal that it doesn’t require any intellectual engagement or indeed any form of action at all. Because of that, it's much less harmful than the crude and aggressive Imperialism of popular media.

Neither of these two schools of policy, neither the international laisser faire of the Liberals, nor “hustle to the top” Imperialism, promise any reality of permanent progress for the world of men. They are the resort, the moral reference, of those who will not think frankly and exhaustively over the whole field of this question. Do that, insist upon solutions of more than accidental applicability, and you emerge with one or other of two contrasted solutions, as the consciousness of kind or the consciousness of individuality prevails in your mind. In the former case you will adopt aggressive Imperialism, but you will carry it out to its “thorough” degree of extermination. You will seek to develop the culture and power of your kind of men and women to the utmost in order to shoulder all other kinds from the earth. If on the other hand you appreciate the unique, you will aim at such a synthesis as this Utopia displays, a synthesis far more credible and possible than any other Welt-Politik. In spite of all the pageant of modern war, synthesis is in the trend of the world. To aid and develop it, could be made the open and secure policy of any great modern empire now. Modern war, modern international hostility is, I believe, possible only through the stupid illiteracy of the mass of men and the conceit and intellectual indolence of rulers and those who feed the public mind. Were the will of the mass of men lit and conscious, I am firmly convinced it would now burn steadily for synthesis and peace.

Neither of these two approaches to policy—the international laissez-faire of the Liberals or the "hustle to the top" Imperialism—promises any real chance for lasting progress for humanity. They serve as a fallback, a moral reference, for those who won't think deeply and thoroughly about the whole issue. If you engage with the question seriously and demand solutions that are more than just superficial, you will find yourself leaning towards one of two contrasting solutions, depending on whether the idea of collective identity or individual identity is stronger in your mind. If you lean towards collective identity, you'll embrace aggressive Imperialism and take it to its extreme of total domination. You'll aim to elevate and empower your own group to the fullest extent, seeking to eliminate all other groups. Conversely, if you recognize the value of uniqueness, you'll strive for a synthesis like the one envisioned in this Utopia, which is far more believable and achievable than any other global policy. Despite the spectacle of modern warfare, synthesis is where the world is headed. Supporting and advancing it could be the clear and secure policy of any major modern empire today. I believe modern war and international conflict are only possible due to the widespread ignorance of the masses and the arrogance and intellectual laziness of leaders and those who influence public opinion. If the will of the people was enlightened and aware, I am convinced it would consistently strive for synthesis and peace.

It would be so easy to bring about a world peace within a few decades, was there but the will for it among men! The great empires that exist need but a little speech and frankness one with another. Within, the riddles of social order are already half solved in books and thought, there are the common people and the subject peoples to be educated and drilled, to be led to a common speech and a common literature, to be assimilated and made citizens; without, there is the possibility of treaties. Why, for example, should Britain and France, or either and the United States, or Sweden and Norway, or Holland, or Denmark, or Italy, fight any more for ever? And if there is no reason, how foolish and dangerous it is still to sustain linguistic differences and custom houses, and all sorts of foolish and irritating distinctions between their various citizens! Why should not all these peoples agree to teach some common language, French, for example, in their common schools, or to teach each other's languages reciprocally? Why should they not aim at a common literature, and bring their various common laws, their marriage laws, and so on, into uniformity? Why should they not work for a uniform minimum of labour conditions through all their communities? Why, then, should they not—except in the interests of a few rascal plutocrats—trade freely and exchange their citizenship freely throughout their common boundaries? No doubt there are difficulties to be found, but they are quite finite difficulties. What is there to prevent a parallel movement of all the civilised Powers in the world towards a common ideal and assimilation?

It would be so easy to create world peace within a few decades if only people had the will! The major empires that exist only need a little honest communication with each other. The challenges of social order are already halfway solved in books and ideas; we just need to educate and train the common people and subject nations, guide them toward a shared language and a common literature, and integrate them as citizens. Externally, there is the potential for treaties. Why, for instance, should Britain and France, or either of them with the United States, or Sweden and Norway, or Holland, or Denmark, or Italy, continue to fight? If there’s no reason, how foolish and dangerous it is to maintain language barriers, customs checks, and all sorts of annoying distinctions among their citizens! Why shouldn’t all these nations agree to teach a common language, like French, in their public schools or teach each other’s languages in return? Why shouldn’t they aim for a shared literature and align their various laws, including marriage laws, to be consistent? Why shouldn’t they work towards a uniform minimum standard for labor conditions across all their communities? So why shouldn’t they—other than for the interests of a few greedy billionaires—trade freely and allow their citizens to move freely across their borders? Of course, there are challenges, but they are manageable. What’s stopping all the civilized countries in the world from moving toward a common ideal and integration?

Stupidity—nothing but stupidity, a stupid brute jealousy, aimless and unjustifiable.

Stupidity—just pure stupidity, a mindless, unjustified jealousy.

The coarser conceptions of aggregation are at hand, the hostile, jealous patriotisms, the blare of trumpets and the pride of fools; they serve the daily need though they lead towards disaster. The real and the immediate has us in its grip, the accidental personal thing. The little effort of thought, the brief sustained effort of will, is too much for the contemporary mind. Such treaties, such sympathetic international movements, are but dream stuff yet on earth, though Utopia has realised them long since and already passed them by.

The rough ideas of coming together are present, the aggressive, jealous nationalisms, the loud trumpets, and the foolish pride; they meet our daily needs, even though they lead to disaster. The real and the immediate have a tight hold on us, the random personal matters. The slight effort of thought, the short burst of willpower, is too much for today's mind. These agreements, these caring international movements, are just dreams here on earth, even though Utopia has achieved them long ago and has already moved beyond them.

CHAPTER THE ELEVENTH
The Bubble Bursts

§ 1

As I walk back along the river terrace to the hotel where the botanist awaits me, and observe the Utopians I encounter, I have no thought that my tenure of Utopia becomes every moment more precarious. There float in my mind vague anticipations of more talks with my double and still more, of a steady elaboration of detail, of interesting journeys of exploration. I forget that a Utopia is a thing of the imagination that becomes more fragile with every added circumstance, that, like a soap-bubble, it is most brilliantly and variously coloured at the very instant of its dissolution. This Utopia is nearly done. All the broad lines of its social organisation are completed now, the discussion of all its general difficulties and problems. Utopian individuals pass me by, fine buildings tower on either hand; it does not occur to me that I may look too closely. To find the people assuming the concrete and individual, is not, as I fondly imagine, the last triumph of realisation, but the swimming moment of opacity before the film gives way. To come to individual emotional cases, is to return to the earth.

As I walk back along the river path to the hotel where the botanist is waiting for me, and see the Utopians I meet, I have no idea that my time in Utopia is becoming more unstable by the second. I’m lost in vague thoughts of more conversations with my counterpart and even more about steadily diving into details and exciting exploratory journeys. I forget that a Utopia is just a figment of the imagination that becomes more delicate with each new detail, that, like a soap bubble, it is most vibrant and varied right before it bursts. This Utopia is almost finished. All the main structures of its social organization are complete now, and the discussions around its general challenges have been wrapped up. Utopian individuals pass me by, stunning buildings rise on either side; I don’t think to look too closely. Discovering people in their concrete individuality is not, as I naively believe, the final achievement of realization, but rather the murky moment before it all falls apart. To delve into individual emotional stories is to come back down to earth.

I find the botanist sitting at a table in the hotel courtyard.

I see the botanist sitting at a table in the hotel courtyard.

“Well?” I say, standing before him.

“Well?” I say, standing in front of him.

“I've been in the gardens on the river terrace,” he answers, “hoping I might see her again.”

“I’ve been in the gardens on the river terrace,” he replies, “hoping I might see her again.”

“Nothing better to do?”

“Got nothing better to do?”

“Nothing in the world.”

“Nothing in the world.”

“You'll have your double back from India to-morrow. Then you'll have conversation.”

"You'll get your double back from India tomorrow. Then you'll have a chance to talk."

“I don't want it,” he replies, compactly.

“I don’t want it,” he replies, tersely.

I shrug my shoulders, and he adds, “At least with him.”

I shrug my shoulders, and he adds, "At least with him."

I let myself down into a seat beside him.

I lowered myself into a seat next to him.

For a time I sit restfully enjoying his companionable silence, and thinking fragmentarily of those samurai and their Rules. I entertain something of the satisfaction of a man who has finished building a bridge; I feel that I have joined together things that I had never joined before. My Utopia seems real to me, very real, I can believe in it, until the metal chair-back gives to my shoulder blades, and Utopian sparrows twitter and hop before my feet. I have a pleasant moment of unhesitating self-satisfaction; I feel a shameless exultation to be there. For a moment I forget the consideration the botanist demands; the mere pleasure of completeness, of holding and controlling all the threads possesses me.

For a while, I sit comfortably, enjoying his quiet company and thinking in bits about those samurai and their rules. I feel a bit like someone who's just finished building a bridge; I sense that I’ve connected things I’d never connected before. My ideal world feels so real to me, very real, I can truly believe in it, until the metal chair back presses into my shoulder blades, and Utopian sparrows chirp and hop at my feet. I have a nice moment of pure self-satisfaction; I feel a bold thrill just being there. For a moment, I forget the expectations of the botanist; the simple joy of feeling complete, of having and managing all the threads overwhelms me.

“You will persist in believing,” I say, with an aggressive expository note, “that if you meet this lady she will be a person with the memories and sentiments of her double on earth. You think she will understand and pity, and perhaps love you. Nothing of the sort is the case.” I repeat with confident rudeness, “Nothing of the sort is the case. Things are different altogether here; you can hardly tell even now how different are―”

“You will keep believing,” I say, with a forceful tone, “that if you meet this woman, she will have the memories and feelings of her counterpart on earth. You think she will understand, feel sorry for you, and maybe even love you. That’s not how it is at all.” I assert with bold rudeness, “That’s not how it is at all. Things are completely different here; you can hardly tell even now how different they are—”

I discover he is not listening to me.

I realize he isn't listening to me.

“What is the matter?” I ask abruptly.

"What's up?" I ask suddenly.

He makes no answer, but his expression startles me.

He doesn't say anything, but his expression surprises me.

“What is the matter?” and then I follow his eyes.

"What’s wrong?" and then I follow his gaze.

A woman and a man are coming through the great archway—and instantly I guess what has happened. She it is arrests my attention first—long ago I knew she was a sweetly beautiful woman. She is fair, with frank blue eyes, that look with a sort of tender receptivity into her companion's face. For a moment or so they remain, greyish figures in the cool shadow, against the sunlit greenery of the gardens beyond.

A woman and a man walk through the large archway—and immediately I realize what’s going on. She catches my attention first—I’ve known for a long time that she is a beautifully sweet woman. She has light hair and open blue eyes that look at her companion’s face with a kind of gentle openness. For a moment, they stay there, gray figures in the cool shadow, contrasting with the sunlit greenery of the gardens beyond.

“It is Mary,” the botanist whispers with white lips, but he stares at the form of the man. His face whitens, it becomes so transfigured with emotion that for a moment it does not look weak. Then I see that his thin hand is clenched.

“It’s Mary,” the botanist whispers, his lips pale, but he keeps his eyes on the man. His face turns pale, and he looks so overcome with emotion that for a moment he doesn’t seem weak. Then I notice that his thin hand is clenched.

I realise how little I understand his emotions.

I realize how little I understand his feelings.

A sudden fear of what he will do takes hold of me. He sits white and tense as the two come into the clearer light of the courtyard. The man, I see, is one of the samurai, a dark, strong-faced man, a man I have never seen before, and she is wearing the robe that shows her a follower of the Lesser Rule.

A sudden fear of what he might do grips me. He sits there, pale and tense, as the two step into the brighter light of the courtyard. The man, I realize, is one of the samurai, a dark, strong-faced guy I've never seen before, and she is wearing the robe that marks her as a follower of the Lesser Rule.

Some glimmering of the botanist's feelings strikes through to my slow sympathies. Of course—a strange man! I put out a restraining hand towards his arm. “I told you,” I say, “that very probably, most probably, she would have met some other. I tried to prepare you.”

Some of the botanist's feelings break through to my slow understanding. Of course—he's a strange guy! I reach out to gently touch his arm. “I told you,” I say, “that very likely, most likely, she would have met someone else. I tried to get you ready for that.”

“Nonsense,” he whispers, without looking at me. “It isn't that. It's—that scoundrel―”

“Nonsense,” he whispers, not looking at me. “It’s not that. It’s—that jerk—”

He has an impulse to rise. “That scoundrel,” he repeats.

He has a sudden urge to get up. “That jerk,” he keeps saying.

“He isn't a scoundrel,” I say. “How do you know? Keep still! Why are you standing up?”

“He's not a jerk,” I say. “How do you know? Be quiet! Why are you standing up?”

He and I stand up quickly, I as soon as he. But now the full meaning of the group has reached me. I grip his arm. “Be sensible,” I say, speaking very quickly, and with my back to the approaching couple. “He's not a scoundrel here. This world is different from that. It's caught his pride somehow and made a man of him. Whatever troubled them there―”

He and I get up quickly, me right after him. But now I completely understand what the group is all about. I grab his arm. “Be sensible,” I say, talking really fast and turning my back to the couple that's coming over. “He’s not a bad guy here. This place is different from that one. It’s somehow boosted his pride and turned him into a man. Whatever was bothering them back there―”

He turns a face of white wrath on me, of accusation, and for the moment of unexpected force. “This is your doing,” he says. “You have done this to mock me. He—of all men!” For a moment speech fails him, then; “You—you have done this to mock me.”

He turns a face of white anger towards me, filled with accusation and unexpected intensity. “This is your fault,” he says. “You did this to make fun of me. He—of all people!” For a moment, he's at a loss for words, then he says, “You—you did this to make fun of me.”

I try to explain very quickly. My tone is almost propitiatory.

I try to explain really quickly. My tone is almost apologetic.

“I never thought of it until now. But he's― How did I know he was the sort of man a disciplined world has a use for?”

“I never thought about it until now. But he's— How did I know he was the kind of person a disciplined world needs?”

He makes no answer, but he looks at me with eyes that are positively baleful, and in the instant I read his mute but mulish resolve that Utopia must end.

He doesn't say anything, but he looks at me with eyes that are completely menacing, and in that moment, I understand his silent but stubborn determination that Utopia has to come to an end.

“Don't let that old quarrel poison all this,” I say almost entreatingly. “It happened all differently here—everything is different here. Your double will be back to-morrow. Wait for him. Perhaps then you will understand―”

“Don’t let that old argument ruin everything,” I say almost pleadingly. “It all happened differently here—everything is different here. Your double will be back tomorrow. Wait for him. Maybe then you will understand—”

He shakes his head, and then bursts out with, “What do I want with a double? Double! What do I care if things have been different here? This―”

He shakes his head, then exclaims, “What do I want with a double? Double! Why should I care if things have been different here? This—”

He thrusts me weakly back with his long, white hand. “My God!” he says almost forcibly, “what nonsense all this is! All these dreams! All Utopias! There she is―! Oh, but I have dreamt of her! And now―”

He weakly pushes me away with his long, white hand. “My God!” he says almost angrily, “what nonsense all this is! All these dreams! All these Utopias! There she is―! Oh, but I’ve dreamed of her! And now―”

A sob catches him. I am really frightened by this time. I still try to keep between him and these Utopians, and to hide his gestures from them.

A sob chokes him. I'm genuinely scared this time. I still try to position myself between him and these Utopians, and to conceal his gestures from them.

“It's different here,” I persist. “It's different here. The emotion you feel has no place in it. It's a scar from the earth—the sore scar of your past―”

“It's different here,” I insist. “It's different here. The feelings you have don’t fit in. It's a mark left by the earth—the painful mark of your past—”

“And what are we all but scars? What is life but a scarring? It's you—you who don't understand! Of course we are covered with scars, we live to be scarred, we are scars! We are the scars of the past! These dreams, these childish dreams―!”

“And what are we if not scars? What is life if not a series of scars? It's you—you who don’t get it! Of course we are covered in scars; we exist to be scarred, we are scars! We are the scars of our past! These dreams, these childish dreams―!”

He does not need to finish his sentence, he waves an unteachable destructive arm.

He doesn’t need to finish his sentence; he gestures with a wild, uncontrollable arm.

My Utopia rocks about me.

My Utopia is amazing.

For a moment the vision of that great courtyard hangs real. There the Utopians live real about me, going to and fro, and the great archway blazes with sunlight from the green gardens by the riverside. The man who is one of the samurai, and his lady, whom the botanist loved on earth, pass out of sight behind the marble flower-set Triton that spouts coolness in the middle of the place. For a moment I see two working men in green tunics sitting on a marble seat in the shadow of the colonnade, and a sweet little silver-haired old lady, clad all in violet, and carrying a book, comes towards us, and lifts a curious eye at the botanist's gestures. And then―

For a moment, the image of that grand courtyard feels real. The Utopians are all around me, bustling to and fro, and the massive archway shines with sunlight from the lush gardens by the riverside. The man, one of the samurai, and his lady, whom the botanist loved on earth, disappear from view behind the marble flower-embellished Triton that sprays refreshing water in the center of the space. For a moment, I notice two workers in green tunics sitting on a marble bench in the shade of the colonnade, and a charming little silver-haired lady, dressed entirely in violet and carrying a book, approaches us, looking curiously at the botanist's gestures. And then―

“Scars of the past! Scars of the past! These fanciful, useless dreams!”

“Scars of the past! Scars of the past! These unrealistic, pointless dreams!”

§ 2

There is no jerk, no sound, no hint of material shock. We are in London, and clothed in the fashion of the town. The sullen roar of London fills our ears....

There’s no jerk, no noise, no sign of a physical impact. We’re in London, dressed in the style of the city. The dull roar of London fills our ears...

I see that I am standing beside an iron seat of poor design in that grey and gawky waste of asphalte—Trafalgar Square, and the botanist, with perplexity in his face, stares from me to a poor, shrivelled, dirt-lined old woman—my God! what a neglected thing she is!—who proffers a box of matches....

I see that I’m standing next to a poorly designed iron bench in that dull and awkward patch of asphalt—Trafalgar Square, and the botanist, looking confused, shifts his gaze between me and a frail, dirty old woman—my God! what a neglected sight she is!—who offers a box of matches....

He buys almost mechanically, and turns back to me.

He buys almost automatically and turns back to me.

“I was saying,” he says, “the past rules us absolutely. These dreams―”

“I was saying,” he says, “the past completely controls us. These dreams―”

His sentence does not complete itself. He looks nervous and irritated.

His sentence doesn't finish. He looks anxious and annoyed.

“You have a trick at times,” he says instead, “of making your suggestions so vivid―”

“You have a way at times,” he says instead, “of making your suggestions so clear―”

He takes a plunge. “If you don't mind,” he says in a sort of quavering ultimatum, “we won't discuss that aspect of the question—the lady, I mean—further.”

He takes a risk. “If you don't mind,” he says in a shaky ultimatum, “let's not discuss that part of the question—the woman, I mean—any further.”

He pauses, and there still hangs a faint perplexity between us.

He pauses, and there's still a slight confusion hanging between us.

“But―” I begin.

“But―” I start.

For a moment we stand there, and my dream of Utopia runs off me like water from an oiled slab. Of course—we lunched at our club. We came back from Switzerland by no dream train but by the ordinary Bâle express. We have been talking of that Lucerne woman he harps upon, and I have made some novel comment on his story. I have touched certain possibilities.

For a moment, we stand there, and my dream of Utopia slips away from me like water off an oiled surface. Of course—we had lunch at our club. We didn't return from Switzerland on some magical train, but on the regular Bâle express. We've been discussing that woman from Lucerne he keeps going on about, and I've added some fresh thoughts to his tale. I've explored certain possibilities.

“You can't conceivably understand,” he says.

"You can't possibly understand," he says.

“The fact remains,” he goes on, taking up the thread of his argument again with an air of having defined our field, “we are the scars of the past. That's a thing one can discuss—without personalities.”

“The fact is,” he continues, picking up where he left off with a sense of having clarified our focus, “we are the marks of our history. That’s something we can talk about—without getting personal.”

“No,” I say rather stupidly, “no.”

“No,” I say pretty foolishly, “no.”

“You are always talking as though you could kick the past to pieces; as though one could get right out from oneself and begin afresh. It is your weakness—if you don't mind my being frank—it makes you seem harsh and dogmatic. Life has gone easily for you; you have never been badly tried. You have been lucky—you do not understand the other way about. You are—hard.”

“You always talk like you could tear the past apart; like you could completely separate yourself from it and start over. It’s a weakness of yours—if you don’t mind me being honest—it makes you come off as harsh and opinionated. Life has been easy for you; you’ve never faced serious challenges. You’ve been lucky—you don’t understand the opposite experience. You are—cold.”

I answer nothing.

I don’t answer anything.

He pants for breath. I perceive that in our discussion of his case I must have gone too far, and that he has rebelled. Clearly I must have said something wounding about that ineffectual love story of his.

He’s breathing hard. I realize that during our discussion of his situation, I must have overstepped, and now he’s pushed back. I must have said something hurtful about that unsuccessful love story of his.

“You don't allow for my position,” he says, and it occurs to me to say, “I'm obliged to look at the thing from my own point of view....”

“You're not considering my position,” he says, and it occurs to me to reply, “I have to see things from my own perspective....”

One or other of us makes a move. What a lot of filthy, torn paper is scattered about the world! We walk slowly side by side towards the dirt-littered basin of the fountain, and stand regarding two grimy tramps who sit and argue on a further seat. One holds a horrible old boot in his hand, and gesticulates with it, while his other hand caresses his rag-wrapped foot. “Wot does Cham'lain si?” his words drift to us. “W'y, 'e says, wot's the good of 'nvesting your kepital where these 'ere Americans may dump it flat any time they like....”

One of us makes a move. There’s so much filthy, torn paper scattered around! We walk slowly side by side toward the dirt-covered basin of the fountain and stop to watch two grimy homeless men sitting and arguing on another bench. One man holds a disgusting old boot in his hand, waving it around while he rubs his foot wrapped in rags. “What does Cham'lain say?” we overhear him say. “Well, he says, what’s the point of investing your capital where these Americans can just throw it away anytime they want..."

(Were there not two men in green sitting on a marble seat?)

(Were there not two men in green sitting on a marble seat?)

§ 3

We walk on, our talk suspended, past a ruthlessly clumsy hoarding, towards where men and women and children are struggling about a string of omnibuses. A newsvendor at the corner spreads a newspaper placard upon the wood pavement, pins the corners down with stones, and we glimpse something about:—

We keep walking, our conversation paused, past a really awkward billboard, towards where people of all ages are gathered around a line of buses. A newsstand at the corner lays out a newspaper poster on the wooden sidewalk, anchors the corners with stones, and we catch a glimpse of something that says:—

MASSACRE IN ODESSA.
DISCOVERY OF HUMAN REMAINS AT CHERTSEY.
SHOCKING LYNCHING OUTRAGE IN NEW YORK STATE.
SHOCKING LYNCHING OUTRAGE IN NEW YORK STATE.

GERMAN INTRIGUES GET A SET-BACK.
THE BIRTHDAY HONOURS.—FULL LIST.

Dear old familiar world!

Dear familiar world!

An angry parent in conversation with a sympathetic friend jostles against us. “I'll knock his blooming young 'ed orf if 'e cheeks me again. It's these 'ere brasted Board Schools―”

An angry parent talking to a sympathetic friend bumps into us. “I’ll knock his stupid head off if he disrespects me again. It’s these damn Board Schools―”

An omnibus passes, bearing on a board beneath an incorrectly drawn Union Jack an exhortation to the true patriot to “Buy Bumper's British-Boiled Jam.”...

An omnibus goes by, displaying an incorrectly drawn Union Jack on a sign that urges true patriots to “Buy Bumper's British-Boiled Jam.”...

I am stunned beyond the possibility of discussion for a space. In this very place it must have been that the high terrace ran with the gardens below it, along which I came from my double to our hotel. I am going back, but now through reality, along the path I passed so happily in my dream. And the people I saw then are the people I am looking at now—with a difference.

I am completely speechless for a moment. This must be the spot where the elevated terrace met the gardens below, the same path I took with my partner to our hotel. I'm heading back, but this time in reality, along the route I enjoyed so much in my dream. And the people I saw then are the ones I'm seeing now—though there’s a difference.

The botanist walks beside me, white and nervously jerky in his movements, his ultimatum delivered.

The botanist walks next to me, looking pale and fidgety in his movements, having just delivered his ultimatum.

We start to cross the road. An open carriage drives by, and we see a jaded, red-haired woman, smeared with paint, dressed in furs, and petulantly discontented. Her face is familiar to me, her face, with a difference.

We begin to cross the street. An open carriage passes by, and we see a tired, red-haired woman, covered in paint, wearing furs, and looking sulky. Her face looks familiar to me, but with a twist.

Why do I think of her as dressed in green?

Why do I picture her wearing green?

Of course!—she it was I saw leading her children by the hand!

Of course!—she was the one I saw leading her kids by the hand!

Comes a crash to our left, and a running of people to see a cab-horse down on the slippery, slanting pavement outside St. Martin's Church.

A crash sounds to our left, and people start running to see a cab horse down on the slippery, slanted pavement outside St. Martin's Church.

We go on up the street.

We're walking up the street.

A heavy-eyed young Jewess, a draggled prostitute—no crimson flower for her hair, poor girl!—regards us with a momentary speculation, and we get a whiff of foul language from two newsboys on the kerb.

A young Jewish woman with heavy eyes, a worn-out prostitute—poor girl, no red flower in her hair!—looks at us with a brief curiosity, and we catch a whiff of foul language from two newsboys on the curb.

“We can't go on talking,” the botanist begins, and ducks aside just in time to save his eye from the ferule of a stupidly held umbrella. He is going to treat our little tiff about that lady as closed. He has the air of picking up our conversation again at some earlier point.

“We can't keep talking,” the botanist starts, quickly moving aside just in time to avoid getting poked in the eye by a poorly held umbrella. He’s decided to consider our little argument about that lady over. He seems ready to pick up our conversation again from somewhere earlier.

He steps into the gutter, walks round outside a negro hawker, just escapes the wheel of a hansom, and comes to my side again.

He steps into the gutter, walks around a Black street vendor, barely avoids the wheel of a cab, and comes back to my side.

“We can't go on talking of your Utopia,” he says, “in a noise and crowd like this.”

"We can't keep talking about your Utopia," he says, "with all this noise and crowd."

We are separated by a portly man going in the opposite direction, and join again. “We can't go on talking of Utopia,” he repeats, “in London.... Up in the mountains—and holiday-time—it was all right. We let ourselves go!”

We’re blocked by a chubby guy heading the other way, and then we reconnect. “We can’t keep talking about Utopia,” he says again, “in London... When we were up in the mountains during vacation, it was fine. We really let ourselves enjoy it!”

“I've been living in Utopia,” I answer, tacitly adopting his tacit proposal to drop the lady out of the question.

“I've been living in Utopia,” I reply, implicitly agreeing with his unspoken suggestion to leave the lady out of the conversation.

“At times,” he says, with a queer laugh, “you've almost made me live there too.”

“At times,” he says with a strange laugh, “you've almost made me live there too.”

He reflects. “It doesn't do, you know. No! And I don't know whether, after all, I want―”

He thinks. “It doesn't work, you know. No! And I don't know if, after all, I want―”

We are separated again by half-a-dozen lifted flagstones, a burning brazier, and two engineers concerned with some underground business or other—in the busiest hour of the day's traffic.

We’re separated again by six raised flagstones, a blazing brazier, and two engineers focused on some underground project or another—in the busiest hour of the day’s traffic.

“Why shouldn't it do?” I ask.

"Why not?" I ask.

“It spoils the world of everyday to let your mind run on impossible perfections.”

“It ruins the everyday world to let your mind dwell on unachievable ideals.”

“I wish,” I shout against the traffic, “I could smash the world of everyday.”

“I wish,” I shout over the noise of the traffic, “I could smash the world of the ordinary.”

My note becomes quarrelsome. “You may accept this as the world of reality, you may consent to be one scar in an ill-dressed compound wound, but so—not I! This is a dream too—this world. Your dream, and you bring me back to it—out of Utopia―”

My note turns confrontational. "You might accept this as the reality, you might agree to be just one scar in a poorly healed wound, but not me! This world is also a dream—your dream, and you drag me back to it—from Utopia—"

The crossing of Bow Street gives me pause again.

The crossing of Bow Street makes me hesitate once more.

The face of a girl who is passing westward, a student girl, rather carelessly dressed, her books in a carrying-strap, comes across my field of vision. The westward sun of London glows upon her face. She has eyes that dream, surely no sensuous nor personal dream.

The face of a girl walking west, a student, dressed a bit carelessly, with her books slung over her shoulder, comes into view. The setting sun over London shines on her face. She has eyes that seem to dream, certainly not of anything sensual or personal.

After all, after all, dispersed, hidden, disorganised, undiscovered, unsuspected even by themselves, the samurai of Utopia are in this world, the motives that are developed and organised there stir dumbly here and stifle in ten thousand futile hearts....

After all, after all, scattered, concealed, chaotic, undiscovered, and even unrecognized by themselves, the samurai of Utopia exist in this world; the motives that emerge and take shape there quietly influence here and suffocate in countless pointless hearts....

I overtake the botanist, who got ahead at the crossing by the advantage of a dust-cart.

I pass the botanist, who got ahead at the intersection because of a dust cart.

“You think this is real because you can't wake out of it,” I say. “It's all a dream, and there are people—I'm just one of the first of a multitude—between sleeping and waking—who will presently be rubbing it out of their eyes.”

“You think this is real because you can't wake up from it,” I say. “It's all a dream, and there are people—I'm just one of the first of many—between sleeping and waking—who will soon be rubbing the sleep out of their eyes.”

A pinched and dirty little girl, with sores upon her face, stretches out a bunch of wilting violets, in a pitifully thin little fist, and interrupts my speech. “Bunch o' vi'lets—on'y a penny.”

A shabby, dirty little girl with sores on her face reaches out with a tiny, frail hand holding some wilting violets and interrupts my conversation. “Bunch of violets—only a penny.”

“No!” I say curtly, hardening my heart.

“No!” I say sharply, steeling myself.

A ragged and filthy nursing mother, with her last addition to our Imperial People on her arm, comes out of a drinkshop, and stands a little unsteadily, and wipes mouth and nose comprehensively with the back of a red chapped hand....

A tattered and dirty nursing mother, with her newest addition to our Imperial People in her arms, stumbles out of a bar, stands a bit unsteadily, and wipes her mouth and nose thoroughly with the back of her red, chapped hand....

§ 4

“Isn't that reality?” says the botanist, almost triumphantly, and leaves me aghast at his triumph.

“Isn't that reality?” says the botanist, almost triumphantly, and leaves me shocked by his victory.

That!” I say belatedly. “It's a thing in a nightmare!”

That!” I say a moment later. “It's something from a nightmare!”

He shakes his head and smiles—exasperatingly.

He shakes his head and smiles—frustratingly.

I perceive quite abruptly that the botanist and I have reached the limits of our intercourse.

I suddenly realize that the botanist and I have reached the end of our conversation.

“The world dreams things like that,” I say, “because it suffers from an indigestion of such people as you.”

“The world dreams things like that,” I say, “because it’s struggling with a surplus of people like you.”

His low-toned self-complacency, like the faded banner of an obstinate fort, still flies unconquered. And you know, he's not even a happy man with it all!

His quiet self-satisfaction, like the worn-out flag of a stubborn fortress, still waves undefeated. And you know, he's not even a happy man despite all of this!

For ten seconds or more I am furiously seeking in my mind for a word, for a term of abuse, for one compendious verbal missile that shall smash this man for ever. It has to express total inadequacy of imagination and will, spiritual anæmia, dull respectability, gross sentimentality, a cultivated pettiness of heart....

For ten seconds or more, I'm frantically searching in my mind for a word, for an insult, for one powerful phrase that will completely destroy this guy. It needs to capture total lack of imagination and will, spiritual emptiness, boring respectability, excessive sentimentality, and a nurtured small-mindedness....

That word will not come. But no other word will do. Indeed the word does not exist. There is nothing with sufficient vituperative concentration for this moral and intellectual stupidity of educated people....

That word won’t come. But no other word will work. In fact, the word doesn’t even exist. There’s nothing with enough harshness to capture the moral and intellectual foolishness of educated people...

“Er―” he begins.

"Uh―" he begins.

No! I can't endure him.

No way! I can't stand him.

With a passionate rapidity of movement, I leave his side, dart between a carriage and a van, duck under the head of a cab-horse, and board a 'bus going westward somewhere—but anyhow, going in exactly the reverse direction to the botanist. I clamber up the steps and thread my swaying way to the seat immediately behind the driver.

With a quick burst of energy, I leave his side, slip between a taxi and a delivery van, duck under the head of a horse, and hop onto a bus heading west—anywhere really, just not where the botanist is going. I climb up the steps and make my way carefully to the seat right behind the driver.

“There!” I say, as I whack myself down on the seat and pant.

“There!” I say, as I flop down on the seat and catch my breath.

When I look round the botanist is out of sight.

When I look around, the botanist is nowhere to be found.

§ 5

But I am back in the world for all that, and my Utopia is done.

But I'm back in the world for all that, and my Utopia is over.

It is good discipline for the Utopist to visit this world occasionally.

It’s beneficial for the Utopist to visit this world from time to time.

But from the front seat on the top of an omnibus on a sunny September afternoon, the Strand, and Charing Cross corner, and Whitehall, and the great multitude of people, the great uproar of vehicles, streaming in all directions, is apt to look a world altogether too formidable. It has a glare, it has a tumult and vigour that shouts one down. It shouts one down, if shouting is to carry it. What good was it to trot along the pavement through this noise and tumult of life, pleading Utopia to that botanist? What good would it be to recommend Utopia in this driver's preoccupied ear?

But from the front seat on top of a bus on a sunny September afternoon, the Strand, Charing Cross corner, Whitehall, and the huge crowd of people, the loud noise of vehicles rushing in all directions, tends to look like a world that's way too overwhelming. It has a brightness, it has a chaos and energy that drown you out. It drowns you out if drowning out is all that counts. What good does it do to stroll along the sidewalk through this noise and chaos of life, trying to convince that botanist about Utopia? What good would it do to suggest Utopia in this driver’s distracted ear?

There are moments in the life of every philosopher and dreamer when he feels himself the flimsiest of absurdities, when the Thing in Being has its way with him, its triumphant way, when it asks in a roar, unanswerably, with a fine solid use of the current vernacular, “What Good is all this—Rot about Utopias?”

There are moments in the life of every philosopher and dreamer when they feel like the flimsiest of absurdities, when the essence of existence has its way with them, its triumphant way, when it asks in a loud voice, without needing an answer, using the current language, “What’s the point of all this—nonsense about Utopias?”

One inspects the Thing in Being with something of the diffident speculation of primitive man, peering from behind a tree at an angry elephant.

One examines the Thing in Being with a bit of the hesitant curiosity of early humans, watching from behind a tree at an angry elephant.

(There is an omen in that image. On how many occasions must that ancestor of ours have had just the Utopist's feeling of ambitious unreality, have decided that on the whole it was wiser to go very quietly home again, and leave the big beast alone? But, in the end, men rode upon the elephant's head, and guided him this way or that.... The Thing in Being that roars so tremendously about Charing Cross corner seems a bigger antagonist than an elephant, but then we have better weapons than chipped flint blades....)

(There is a warning in that image. How many times must our ancestor have experienced that Utopist feeling of unrealistic ambition, deciding it was smarter to quietly go home and leave the big beast alone? But in the end, people climbed onto the elephant's head and directed it this way or that.... The thing that rumbles so powerfully around Charing Cross corner seems like a bigger opponent than an elephant, but we have better tools than primitive flint blades....)

After all, in a very little time everything that impresses me so mightily this September afternoon will have changed or passed away for ever, everything. These omnibuses, these great, stalwart, crowded, many-coloured things that jostle one another, and make so handsome a clatter-clamour, will all have gone; they and their horses and drivers and organisation; you will come here and you will not find them. Something else will be here, some different sort of vehicle, that is now perhaps the mere germ of an idea in some engineer student's brain. And this road and pavement will have changed, and these impressive great buildings; other buildings will be here, buildings that are as yet more impalpable than this page you read, more formless and flimsy by far than anything that is reasoned here. Little plans sketched on paper, strokes of a pen or of a brush, will be the first materialisations of what will at last obliterate every detail and atom of these re-echoing actualities that overwhelm us now. And the clothing and gestures of these innumerable people, the character of their faces and bearing, these too will be recast in the spirit of what are now obscure and impalpable beginnings.

After all, in no time at all, everything that impresses me so much this September afternoon will have changed or disappeared forever, everything. These buses, these big, sturdy, crowded, colorful vehicles that jostle each other and make such a beautiful noise, will all be gone; along with their horses, drivers, and organization; you'll come here and you won't find them. Something else will be here, some different kind of vehicle that is maybe just a tiny idea in some engineering student's mind right now. And this road and pavement will have changed, and these impressive buildings; other buildings will be here, buildings that are currently more intangible than this page you’re reading, much more abstract and flimsy than anything being discussed here. Little plans sketched on paper, lines from a pen or brush, will be the first realizations of what will eventually erase every detail and aspect of these resonating realities that surround us now. And the clothing and actions of these countless people, the expressions on their faces and their attitudes, these too will be transformed in the spirit of what are now obscure and vague beginnings.

The new things will be indeed of the substance of the thing that is, but differing just in the measure of the will and imagination that goes to make them. They will be strong and fair as the will is sturdy and organised and the imagination comprehensive and bold; they will be ugly and smeared with wretchedness as the will is fluctuating and the imagination timid and mean.

The new things will certainly be based on the essence of what exists, but they will vary in how much will and imagination are involved in creating them. They will be strong and beautiful when the will is firm and organized, and the imagination is expansive and daring; they will be unattractive and tainted with misery when the will is inconsistent and the imagination is shy and limited.

Indeed Will is stronger than Fact, it can mould and overcome Fact. But this world has still to discover its will, it is a world that slumbers inertly, and all this roar and pulsation of life is no more than its heavy breathing.... My mind runs on to the thought of an awakening.

Indeed, will is stronger than fact; it can shape and surpass fact. But this world has yet to discover its will; it is a world that lies in a deep sleep, and all this noise and activity of life is nothing more than its heavy breathing.... My mind is filled with thoughts of awakening.

As my omnibus goes lumbering up Cockspur Street through the clatter rattle of the cabs and carriages, there comes another fancy in my mind.... Could one but realise an apocalyptic image and suppose an angel, such as was given to each of the seven churches of Asia, given for a space to the service of the Greater Rule. I see him as a towering figure of flame and colour, standing between earth and sky, with a trumpet in his hands, over there above the Haymarket, against the October glow; and when he sounds, all the samurai, all who are samurai in Utopia, will know themselves and one another....

As my bus slowly makes its way up Cockspur Street amidst the noise of cabs and carriages, another thought crosses my mind.... What if we could envision an apocalyptic scene and imagine an angel, like the ones given to each of the seven churches of Asia, temporarily serving the Greater Rule? I picture him as a towering figure of fire and color, standing between earth and sky, holding a trumpet in his hands, over there above the Haymarket, illuminated by the October glow; and when he sounds the trumpet, all the samurai, everyone who is samurai in Utopia, will recognize themselves and each other....

(Whup! says a motor brougham, and a policeman stays the traffic with his hand.)

(Whup! says a motor carriage, and a police officer stops the traffic with his hand.)

All of us who partake of the samurai would know ourselves and one another!

All of us who share the samurai experience should understand ourselves and each other!

For a moment I have a vision of this resurrection of the living, of a vague, magnificent answer, of countless myriads at attention, of all that is fine in humanity at attention, round the compass of the earth.

For a moment, I imagine this resurrection of the living, a vague yet magnificent answer, countless people focused and attentive, all that is good in humanity gathered around the earth.

Then that philosophy of individual uniqueness resumes its sway over my thoughts, and my dream of a world's awakening fades.

Then that idea of individual uniqueness takes over my thoughts again, and my dream of the world awakening fades away.

I had forgotten....

I forgot....

Things do not happen like that. God is not simple, God is not theatrical, the summons comes to each man in its due time for him, with an infinite subtlety of variety....

Things don't happen that way. God isn't simple, God isn't dramatic; the call comes to each person in their own time, with an endless variety of subtleties.

If that is so, what of my Utopia?

If that's the case, what about my Utopia?

This infinite world must needs be flattened to get it on one retina. The picture of a solid thing, although it is flattened and simplified, is not necessarily a lie. Surely, surely, in the end, by degrees, and steps, something of this sort, some such understanding, as this Utopia must come. First here, then there, single men and then groups of men will fall into line—not indeed with my poor faulty hesitating suggestions—but with a great and comprehensive plan wrought out by many minds and in many tongues. It is just because my plan is faulty, because it mis-states so much, and omits so much, that they do not now fall in. It will not be like my dream, the world that is coming. My dream is just my own poor dream, the thing sufficient for me. We fail in comprehension, we fail so variously and abundantly. We see as much as it is serviceable for us to see, and we see no further. But the fresh undaunted generations come to take on our work beyond our utmost effort, beyond the range of our ideas. They will learn with certainty things that to us are guesses and riddles....

This endless world has to be flattened to fit it onto one screen. The image of a solid object, even though it's flattened and simplified, isn't necessarily a lie. Surely, in the end, step by step, something like this, some sort of understanding like this Utopia will emerge. First here, then there, individuals and then groups will align—not with my imperfect, uncertain suggestions—but with a larger, comprehensive plan developed by many minds and in many languages. It's precisely because my plan is flawed, because it misrepresents so much and leaves so much out, that they don't come together now. The world that's coming won’t look like my dream. My dream is just my personal, inadequate vision, the thing that's enough for me. We struggle with understanding, and we fail in so many different ways. We see only as much as we need to see, and we don't look beyond that. But the brave new generations will build on our work, going beyond our greatest efforts and the limits of our ideas. They will discover with certainty things that are just guesses and puzzles to us....

There will be many Utopias. Each generation will have its new version of Utopia, a little more certain and complete and real, with its problems lying closer and closer to the problems of the Thing in Being. Until at last from dreams Utopias will have come to be working drawings, and the whole world will be shaping the final World State, the fair and great and fruitful World State, that will only not be a Utopia because it will be this world. So surely it must be―

There will be many Utopias. Each generation will create its own version of Utopia, a little more certain, complete, and real, with its issues increasingly connected to the realities of existence. Eventually, what started as dreams will turn into practical plans, and the entire world will be working towards the final World State—the fair, great, and prosperous World State—that will only not be a Utopia because it will be this world. It must surely be that way.

The policeman drops his hand. “Come up,” says the 'bus driver, and the horses strain; “Clitter, clatter, cluck, clak,” the line of hurrying hansoms overtakes the omnibus going west. A dexterous lad on a bicycle with a bale of newspapers on his back dodges nimbly across the head of the column and vanishes up a side street.

The cop lowers his hand. “Step up,” says the bus driver, and the horses pull forward; “Clitter, clatter, cluck, clak,” the row of rushing horse-drawn carriages catches up to the bus heading west. A skilled kid on a bicycle with a bundle of newspapers on his back skillfully weaves through the front of the line and disappears down a side street.

The omnibus sways forward. Rapt and prophetic, his plump hands clasped round the handle of his umbrella, his billycock hat a trifle askew, this irascible little man of the Voice, this impatient dreamer, this scolding Optimist, who has argued so rudely and dogmatically about economics and philosophy and decoration, and indeed about everything under the sun, who has been so hard on the botanist and fashionable women, and so reluctant in the matter of beer, is carried onward, dreaming dreams, dreams that with all the inevitable ironies of difference, may be realities when you and I are dreams.

The bus sways forward. With eager anticipation, his chubby hands gripping the handle of his umbrella, his bowler hat slightly askew, this fiery little man of the Voice, this restless dreamer, this critical Optimist, who has debated so harshly and dogmatically about economics, philosophy, and fashion, and really about everything under the sun, who has been tough on the botanist and trendy women, and so hesitant when it comes to beer, is carried along, lost in thoughts, thoughts that, despite all the inevitable ironies of difference, could become real when you and I are just memories.

He passes, and for a little space we are left with his egoisms and idiosyncrasies more or less in suspense.

He walks by, and for a moment we're left with his selfishness and quirks hanging in the air.

But why was he intruded? you ask. Why could not a modern Utopia be discussed without this impersonation—impersonally? It has confused the book, you say, made the argument hard to follow, and thrown a quality of insincerity over the whole. Are we but mocking at Utopias, you demand, using all these noble and generalised hopes as the backcloth against which two bickering personalities jar and squabble? Do I mean we are never to view the promised land again except through a foreground of fellow-travellers? There is a common notion that the reading of a Utopia should end with a swelling heart and clear resolves, with lists of names, formation of committees, and even the commencement of subscriptions. But this Utopia began upon a philosophy of fragmentation, and ends, confusedly, amidst a gross tumult of immediate realities, in dust and doubt, with, at the best, one individual's aspiration. Utopias were once in good faith, projects for a fresh creation of the world and of a most unworldly completeness; this so-called Modern Utopia is a mere story of personal adventures among Utopian philosophies.

But why was he involved? you ask. Why couldn’t we talk about a modern Utopia without this impersonation—objectively? It has muddled the book, you say, made the argument difficult to follow, and cast a sense of insincerity over the entire thing. Are we just mocking Utopias, you wonder, using all these noble and generalized hopes as the backdrop against which two arguing personalities clash and squabble? Am I suggesting we can never see the promised land again except through a lens of fellow travelers? There’s a common belief that reading a Utopia should leave you with an uplifted heart and clear intentions, leading to lists of names, forming committees, and even starting subscriptions. But this Utopia starts with a philosophy of fragmentation and ends, confusingly, in a chaotic mix of immediate realities, in dust and doubt, with, at best, one person's aspiration. Utopias once represented genuine efforts to create a new world and achieve an extraordinary completeness; this so-called Modern Utopia is just a tale of personal adventures within Utopian philosophies.

Indeed, that came about without the writer's intention. So it was the summoned vision came. For I see about me a great multitude of little souls and groups of souls as darkened, as derivative as my own; with the passage of years I understand more and more clearly the quality of the motives that urge me and urge them to do whatever we do.... Yet that is not all I see, and I am not altogether bounded by my littleness. Ever and again, contrasting with this immediate vision, come glimpses of a comprehensive scheme, in which these personalities float, the scheme of a synthetic wider being, the great State, mankind, in which we all move and go, like blood corpuscles, like nerve cells, it may be at times like brain cells, in the body of a man. But the two visions are not seen consistently together, at least by me, and I do not surely know that they exist consistently together. The motives needed for those wider issues come not into the interplay of my vanities and wishes. That greater scheme lies about the men and women I know, as I have tried to make the vistas and spaces, the mountains, cities, laws, and order of Utopia lie about my talking couple, too great for their sustained comprehension. When one focuses upon these two that wide landscape becomes indistinct and distant, and when one regards that then the real persons one knows grow vague and unreal. Nevertheless, I cannot separate these two aspects of human life, each commenting on the other. In that incongruity between great and individual inheres the incompatibility I could not resolve, and which, therefore, I have had to present in this conflicting form. At times that great scheme does seem to me to enter certain men's lives as a passion, as a real and living motive; there are those who know it almost as if it was a thing of desire; even for me, upon occasion, the little lures of the immediate life are seen small and vain, and the soul goes out to that mighty Being, to apprehend it and serve it and possess. But this is an illumination that passes as it comes, a rare transitory lucidity, leaving the soul's desire suddenly turned to presumption and hypocrisy upon the lips. One grasps at the Universe and attains—Bathos. The hungers, the jealousies, the prejudices and habits have us again, and we are forced back to think that it is so, and not otherwise, that we are meant to serve the mysteries; that in these blinkers it is we are driven to an end we cannot understand. And then, for measured moments in the night watches or as one walks alone or while one sits in thought and speech with a friend, the wider aspirations glow again with a sincere emotion, with the colours of attainable desire....

Actually, that happened without the writer's intention. That’s how the vision appeared. I see a large number of little souls and groups of souls around me, just as shadowy and derivative as my own; over the years, I understand more clearly the motives that push me and them to do what we do.... But that’s not all I see, and I’m not completely limited by my smallness. Now and then, contrasting with this immediate vision, I get glimpses of a larger plan, in which these personalities exist, the plan of a broader, unified being, the great State, humanity, where we all move like blood cells, nerve cells, or sometimes even brain cells, in the body of a person. However, these two visions are not consistently seen together, at least not by me, and I can’t be sure they coexist together. The motives needed for those wider issues don’t mix with my vanities and wishes. That larger plan surrounds the men and women I know, just as I’ve tried to shape the vistas and spaces, mountains, cities, laws, and order of Utopia around my talking couple, which is too grand for their lasting understanding. When you focus on these two, that vast landscape becomes blurry and distant, and when you regard that, the real people you know feel vague and unreal. Still, I can’t separate these two aspects of human life; each reflects on the other. In that inconsistency between the grand and the individual lies the incompatibility I couldn’t resolve, which is why I’ve had to present it in this conflicting form. Sometimes, that grand scheme seems to ignite certain men’s lives as a passion, as a genuine and living motive; there are those who almost see it as something to desire; even for me, at times, the small temptations of everyday life seem trivial and empty, and the soul reaches out to that mighty Being, to grasp and serve and possess it. But this clarity is fleeting, a rare moment of lucidity, leaving the soul’s desire suddenly shifting to presumption and hypocrisy on the lips. One reaches for the Universe and finds—Bathos. The hungers, jealousies, prejudices, and habits pull us back again, and we are forced to believe that it must be this way, that we are meant to serve the mysteries; that in these blinkers, we are driven toward an end we cannot comprehend. And then, for brief moments in the late hours or when walking alone or while sitting in thought and conversation with a friend, the broader aspirations shine again with sincere emotion, with the colors of attainable desire....

That is my all about Utopia, and about the desire and need for Utopia, and how that planet lies to this planet that bears the daily lives of men.

That's everything I have to say about Utopia, and about the desire and need for Utopia, and how that world connects to this one where people live their everyday lives.


APPENDIX
SCEPTICISM OF THE INSTRUMENT

A Portion of a Paper read to the Oxford Philosophical Society, November 8, 1903, and reprinted, with some Revision, from the Version given in Mind, vol. xiii. (N.S.), No. 51.

A portion of a paper presented to the Oxford Philosophical Society, November 8, 1903, and reprinted, with some revisions, from the version published in Mind, vol. xiii. (N.S.), No. 51.

(See also Chapter I., § 6, and Chapter X., §§ 1 and 2.)

(See also Chapter I., § 6, and Chapter X., §§ 1 and 2.)

It seems to me that I may most propitiously attempt to interest you this evening by describing very briefly the particular metaphysical and philosophical system in which I do my thinking, and more particularly by setting out for your consideration one or two points in which I seem to myself to differ most widely from current accepted philosophy.

It seems to me that tonight is a great opportunity to engage your interest by briefly outlining the specific metaphysical and philosophical system that I use for my thinking, and especially by highlighting one or two areas where I feel I differ significantly from the currently accepted philosophy.

You must be prepared for things that will strike you as crude, for a certain difference of accent and dialect that you may not like, and you must be prepared too to hear what may strike you as the clumsy statement of my ignorant rediscovery of things already beautifully thought out and said. But in the end you may incline to forgive me some of this first offence.... It is quite unavoidable that, in setting out these intellectual foundations of mine, I should lapse for a moment or so towards autobiography.

You need to be ready for things that might seem rough or unrefined, and for some differences in accent and dialect that you may not appreciate. You should also be prepared to hear what might come off as a clumsy restatement of ideas that have already been beautifully expressed. But in the end, you might be inclined to forgive me for some of this initial offense... It's completely unavoidable that while laying out my intellectual foundations, I might drift into a bit of autobiography.

A convergence of circumstances led to my having my knowledge of concrete things quite extensively developed before I came to philosophical examination at all. I have heard someone say that a savage or an animal is mentally a purely objective being, and in that respect I was like a savage or an animal until I was well over twenty. I was extremely unaware of the subjective or introverted element in my being. I was a Positivist without knowing it. My early education was a feeble one; it was one in which my private observation, inquiry and experiment were far more important factors than any instruction, or rather perhaps the instruction I received was less even than what I learnt for myself, and it terminated at thirteen. I had come into pretty intimate contact with the harder realities of life, with hunger in various forms, and many base and disagreeable necessities, before I was fifteen. About that age, following the indication of certain theological and speculative curiosities, I began to learn something of what I will call deliberately and justly, Elementary Science—stuff I got out of Cassell's Popular Educator and cheap text-books—and then, through accidents and ambitions that do not matter in the least to us now, I came to three years of illuminating and good scientific work. The central fact of those three years was Huxley's course in Comparative Anatomy at the school in Exhibition Road. About that as a nucleus I arranged a spacious digest of facts. At the end of that time I had acquired what I still think to be a fairly clear, and complete and ordered view of the ostensibly real universe. Let me try to give you the chief things I had. I had man definitely placed in the great scheme of space and time. I knew him incurably for what he was, finite and not final, a being of compromises and adaptations. I had traced his lungs, for example, from a swimming bladder, step by step, with scalpel and probe, through a dozen types or more, I had seen the ancestral cæcum shrink to that disease nest, the appendix of to-day, I had watched the gill slit patched slowly to the purposes of the ear and the reptile jaw suspension utilised to eke out the needs of a sense organ taken from its native and natural water. I had worked out the development of those extraordinarily unsatisfactory and untrustworthy instruments, man's teeth, from the skin scutes of the shark to their present function as a basis for gold stoppings, and followed the slow unfolding of the complex and painful process of gestation through which man comes into the world. I had followed all these things and many kindred things by dissection and in embryology—I had checked the whole theory of development again in a year's course of palæontology, and I had taken the dimensions of the whole process, by the scale of the stars, in a course of astronomical physics. And all that amount of objective elucidation came before I had reached the beginnings of any philosophical or metaphysical inquiry, any inquiry as to why I believed, how I believed, what I believed, or what the fundamental stuff of things was.

A mix of circumstances led to my gaining a pretty extensive understanding of concrete things before I even started to examine philosophy. I’ve heard someone say that a savage or an animal is purely objective in their thinking, and until I was well over twenty, I was like that—a savage or an animal in that respect. I was completely unaware of the subjective or introspective aspect of my existence. I was a Positivist without realizing it. My early education was weak; it relied much more on my own observation, questioning, and experimentation than any formal instruction, which was actually minimal and ended by the age of thirteen. By the time I was fifteen, I had already faced the harsher realities of life, dealing with various forms of hunger and many unpleasant necessities. Around that age, prompted by some theological and speculative interests, I started to learn what I would call Elementary Science—information I got from Cassell's Popular Educator and inexpensive textbooks. Then, through a series of events and ambitions that don’t really matter to us now, I experienced three years of enlightening and solid scientific work. The core of those three years was Huxley's course in Comparative Anatomy at the school on Exhibition Road. Based around that, I compiled a comprehensive summary of facts. By the end of that time, I had what I still believe to be a fairly clear, complete, and organized perspective of the apparently real universe. Let me share the main things I learned. I had positioned humans within the grand scheme of space and time. I understood them as inherently finite and not conclusive, beings built on compromises and adaptations. For example, I traced the evolution of lungs from a swimming bladder, step-by-step, using a scalpel and probe, across more than a dozen types. I observed the ancestral cæcum shrink into what we now know as the appendix, a site of disease. I watched how the gill slit slowly adapted to serve the ear, and how the reptilian jaw suspension was repurposed to support a sense organ that had moved from its original aquatic habitat. I analyzed the development of those exceedingly disappointing and unreliable tools we call teeth, tracing them from the skin scales of sharks to their current role as bases for gold fillings, and I followed the complex and arduous process of gestation through which humans enter the world. I explored all these various aspects and more through dissection and embryology—I reviewed the entire developmental theory in a year-long course in paleontology, and I measured the whole process against the scale of the stars in a course on astronomical physics. All this objective insight came before I even began any philosophical or metaphysical questioning about why I believed what I believed, how I believed, or what the essential nature of things was.

Now following hard upon this interlude with knowledge, came a time when I had to give myself to teaching, and it became advisable to acquire one of those Teaching Diplomas that are so widely and so foolishly despised, and that enterprise set me to a superficial, but suggestive study of educational method, of educational theory, of logic, of psychology, and so at last, when the little affair with the diploma was settled, to philosophy. Now to come to logic over the bracing uplands of comparative anatomy is to come to logic with a lot of very natural preconceptions blown clean out of one's mind. It is, I submit, a way of taking logic in the flank. When you have realised to the marrow, that all the physical organs of man and all his physical structure are what they are through a series of adaptations and approximations, and that they are kept up to a level of practical efficiency only by the elimination of death, and that this is true also of his brain and of his instincts and of many of his mental predispositions, you are not going to take his thinking apparatus unquestioningly as being in any way mysteriously different and better. And I had read only a little logic before I became aware of implications that I could not agree with, and assumptions that seemed to me to be altogether at variance with the general scheme of objective fact established in my mind.

Now, right after this break with knowledge, I reached a point where I had to focus on teaching, and it made sense to get one of those teaching diplomas that are widely and foolishly looked down upon. This project led me to a surface-level yet thought-provoking study of educational methods, educational theory, logic, and psychology, and eventually, once I sorted out that little diploma issue, I turned to philosophy. Approaching logic after thoroughly studying comparative anatomy means coming into it with many natural assumptions cleared from my mind. It's a unique way to tackle logic. When you truly understand that all of the physical organs and structures in humans exist because of a series of adaptations and approximations, and that they maintain a level of practical efficiency only by avoiding death, and that the same applies to the brain, instincts, and various mental predispositions, you're not going to treat the thinking processes as being mysteriously different or superior. I had read only a little logic before I began to notice implications I couldn't agree with and assumptions that seemed completely at odds with the overall objective reality I had built in my mind.

I came to an examination of logical processes and of language with the expectation that they would share the profoundly provisional character, the character of irregular limitation and adaptation that pervades the whole physical and animal being of man. And I found the thing I had expected. And as a consequence I found a sort of intellectual hardihood about the assumptions of logic, that at first confused me and then roused all the latent scepticism in my mind.

I approached an analysis of logical processes and language expecting them to have the same temporary nature, the irregular limitations and adaptability that are a part of human existence. And that’s exactly what I found. As a result, I encountered a kind of intellectual boldness in the assumptions of logic that initially confused me but eventually stirred up all the lingering skepticism in my mind.

My first quarrel with the accepted logic I developed long ago in a little paper that was printed in the Fortnightly Review in July 1891. It was called the “Rediscovery of the Unique,” and re-reading it I perceive not only how bad and even annoying it was in manner—a thing I have long known—but also how remarkably bad it was in expression. I have good reason for doubting whether my powers of expression in these uses have very perceptibly improved, but at any rate I am doing my best now with that previous failure before me.

My first disagreement with the accepted logic came long ago in a short paper published in the Fortnightly Review in July 1891. It was titled “Rediscovery of the Unique,” and as I read it again, I realize not only how poorly and even annoyingly it was written—a fact I’ve known for a while—but also how incredibly bad the expression was. I have good reason to doubt whether my writing skills have noticeably improved since then, but at least I’m trying my best now with that earlier failure in mind.

That unfortunate paper, among other oversights I can no longer regard as trivial, disregarded quite completely the fact that a whole literature upon the antagonism of the one and the many, of the specific ideal and the individual reality, was already in existence. It defined no relations to other thought or thinkers. I understand now, what I did not understand then, why it was totally ignored. But the idea underlying that paper I cling to to-day. I consider it an idea that will ultimately be regarded as one of primary importance to human thought, and I will try and present the substance of that early paper again now very briefly, as the best opening of my general case. My opening scepticism is essentially a doubt of the objective reality of classification. I have no hesitation in saying that is the first and primary proposition of my philosophy.

That unfortunate paper, along with other oversights I can no longer view as unimportant, completely ignored the fact that a whole body of literature about the conflict between the one and the many, between the specific ideal and individual reality, already existed. It made no connections to other ideas or thinkers. I now understand, more than I did back then, why it was completely overlooked. However, I still hold on to the idea behind that paper today. I believe it’s an idea that will eventually be seen as fundamentally important to human thought, and I'll try to summarize the main points of that early paper again now very briefly, as the best way to introduce my overall argument. My initial skepticism is essentially a doubt about the objective reality of classification. I have no doubt in saying that this is the first and foundational proposition of my philosophy.

I have it in my mind that classification is a necessary condition of the working of the mental implement, but that it is a departure from the objective truth of things, that classification is very serviceable for the practical purposes of life but a very doubtful preliminary to those fine penetrations the philosophical purpose, in its more arrogant moods, demands. All the peculiarities of my way of thinking derive from that.

I believe that classification is essential for how our minds work, but it strays from the objective truth of reality. While classification is quite useful for everyday life, it is a questionable starting point for the deeper insights that philosophy, especially in its more ambitious states, seeks. All the unique aspects of my thinking come from this perspective.

A mind nourished upon anatomical study is of course permeated with the suggestion of the vagueness and instability of biological species. A biological species is quite obviously a great number of unique individuals which is separable from other biological species only by the fact that an enormous number of other linking individuals are inaccessible in time—are in other words dead and gone—and each new individual in that species does, in the distinction of its own individuality, break away in however infinitesimal degree from the previous average properties of the species. There is no property of any species, even the properties that constitute the specific definition, that is not a matter of more or less. If, for example, a species be distinguished by a single large red spot on the back, you will find if you go over a great number of specimens that red spot shrinking here to nothing, expanding there to a more general redness, weakening to pink, deepening to russet and brown, shading into crimson, and so on, and so on. And this is true not only of biological species. It is true of the mineral specimens constituting a mineral species, and I remember as a constant refrain in the lectures of Prof. Judd upon rock classification, the words “they pass into one another by insensible gradations.” That is true, I hold, of all things.

A mind engaged in studying anatomy is naturally filled with the idea that biological species are vague and unstable. A biological species is clearly made up of many unique individuals, and it's only set apart from other species by the fact that numerous connecting individuals are unavailable in time—they're essentially dead and gone. Each new individual within that species slightly diverges from the average characteristics of the species. There’s no characteristic of any species, even those that define it, that isn’t a matter of degree. For instance, if a species is defined by a single large red spot on its back, you'll find that among many specimens, that red spot can shrink to nothing, enlarge into a broader redness, fade to pink, deepen to russet and brown, and shift into crimson, and so on. This is true not just for biological species; it's also applicable to the mineral specimens that make up a mineral species. I remember a phrase that Prof. Judd often repeated in his lectures on rock classification: “they pass into one another by insensible gradations.” I believe this applies to everything.

You will think perhaps of atoms of the elements as instances of identically similar things, but these are things not of experience but of theory, and there is not a phenomenon in chemistry that is not equally well explained on the supposition that it is merely the immense quantities of atoms necessarily taken in any experiment that mask by the operation of the law of averages the fact that each atom also has its unique quality, its special individual difference. This idea of uniqueness in all individuals is not only true of the classifications of material science; it is true, and still more evidently true, of the species of common thought, it is true of common terms. Take the word chair. When one says chair, one thinks vaguely of an average chair. But collect individual instances, think of armchairs and reading chairs, and dining-room chairs and kitchen chairs, chairs that pass into benches, chairs that cross the boundary and become settees, dentists' chairs, thrones, opera stalls, seats of all sorts, those miraculous fungoid growths that cumber the floor of the Arts and Crafts Exhibition, and you will perceive what a lax bundle in fact is this simple straightforward term. In co-operation with an intelligent joiner I would undertake to defeat any definition of chair or chairishness that you gave me. Chairs just as much as individual organisms, just as much as mineral and rock specimens, are unique things—if you know them well enough you will find an individual difference even in a set of machine-made chairs—and it is only because we do not possess minds of unlimited capacity, because our brain has only a limited number of pigeon-holes for our correspondence with an unlimited universe of objective uniques, that we have to delude ourselves into the belief that there is a chairishness in this species common to and distinctive of all chairs.

You might think of atoms of elements as identical examples of the same thing, but these are concepts from theory, not direct experience. Every phenomenon in chemistry can be equally explained by the idea that the massive quantities of atoms used in any experiment mask, through the law of averages, the fact that each atom has its own unique properties and individual differences. This concept of uniqueness applies not just to material science classifications; it’s even more apparent in common thought and everyday terms. Take the word chair. When you say "chair," you might think of an average chair. But if you collect individual examples—like armchairs, reading chairs, dining-room chairs, kitchen chairs, chairs that become benches, chairs that turn into settees, dentist chairs, thrones, opera seats, and all kinds of seats—even those strange creations at the Arts and Crafts Exhibition—you'll realize how loosely defined this straightforward term is. Working with a skilled carpenter, I could challenge any definition of what a chair is or what makes it "chairish." Chairs, like individual living organisms, and like mineral and rock samples, are unique objects—if you study them closely enough, you'll find individual differences even among a set of mass-produced chairs. It’s only because our minds have limited capacity and can only sort information into a small number of categories, while the universe is filled with limitless unique objects, that we convince ourselves there’s something universally "chairish" that all chairs share.

Let me repeat; this is of the very smallest importance in all the practical affairs of life, or indeed in relation to anything but philosophy and wide generalisations. But in philosophy it matters profoundly. If I order two new-laid eggs for breakfast, up come two unhatched but still unique avian individuals, and the chances are they serve my rude physiological purpose. I can afford to ignore the hens' eggs of the past that were not quite so nearly this sort of thing, and the hens' eggs of the future that will accumulate modification age by age; I can venture to ignore the rare chance of an abnormality in chemical composition and of any startling aberration in my physiological reaction; I can, with a confidence that is practically perfect, say with unqualified simplicity “two eggs,” but not if my concern is not my morning's breakfast but the utmost possible truth.

Let me say it again: this is of very little importance in all the practical aspects of life, or really in relation to anything except philosophy and broad generalizations. But in philosophy, it’s extremely significant. If I order two fresh eggs for breakfast, out come two untouched but still unique birds, and they're likely to fulfill my basic needs. I can ignore the hens' eggs from the past that weren’t quite like this, and the future hens' eggs that will change over time; I can choose to overlook the rare possibility of an unusual chemical makeup and any surprising reactions I might have; I can confidently say “two eggs” with complete simplicity, but not if I'm concerned with uncovering the absolute truth.

Now let me go on to point out whither this idea of uniqueness tends. I submit to you that syllogism is based on classification, that all hard logical reasoning tends to imply and is apt to imply a confidence in the objective reality of classification. Consequently in denying that I deny the absolute validity of logic. Classification and number, which in truth ignore the fine differences of objective realities, have in the past of human thought been imposed upon things. Let me for clearness' sake take a liberty here—commit, as you may perhaps think, an unpardonable insolence. Hindoo thought and Greek thought alike impress me as being overmuch obsessed by an objective treatment of certain necessary preliminary conditions of human thought—number and definition and class and abstract form. But these things, number, definition, class and abstract form, I hold, are merely unavoidable conditions of mental activity—regrettable conditions rather than essential facts. The forceps of our minds are clumsy forceps, and crush the truth a little in taking hold of it.

Now let me point out where this idea of uniqueness leads us. I propose that syllogisms are based on classification, and that all rigorous logical reasoning implies a belief in the objective reality of classification. Therefore, by denying this, I do not reject the absolute validity of logic. Classification and numbers, which actually overlook the subtle differences in objective realities, have historically been imposed upon things by human thought. For clarity, let me take a bold step here—what you might consider an unforgivable audacity. Both Hindu and Greek thought seem overly focused on treating certain necessary preliminary conditions of human thought—like numbers, definitions, classes, and abstract forms—as objective truths. However, I believe that these elements—numbers, definitions, classes, and abstract forms—are simply unavoidable conditions of mental activity—more regrettable than essential facts. The tools of our minds are clumsy instruments, and they crush the truth a bit when we try to grasp it.

It was about this difficulty that the mind of Plato played a little inconclusively all his life. For the most part he tended to regard the idea as the something behind reality, whereas it seems to me that the idea is the more proximate and less perfect thing, the thing by which the mind, by ignoring individual differences, attempts to comprehend an otherwise unmanageable number of unique realities.

Plato grappled with this challenge throughout his life, often without reaching a clear conclusion. Generally, he viewed the idea as the essence behind reality, while I believe the idea is actually a closer and less perfect concept. It's what the mind uses to try to understand a countless variety of unique realities, by setting aside individual differences.

Let me give you a rough figure of what I am trying to convey in this first attack upon the philosophical validity of general terms. You have seen the results of those various methods of black and white reproduction that involve the use of a rectangular net. You know the sort of process picture I mean—it used to be employed very frequently in reproducing photographs. At a little distance you really seem to have a faithful reproduction of the original picture, but when you peer closely you find not the unique form and masses of the original, but a multitude of little rectangles, uniform in shape and size. The more earnestly you go into the thing, the closer you look, the more the picture is lost in reticulations. I submit the world of reasoned inquiry has a very similar relation to the world I call objectively real. For the rough purposes of every day the net-work picture will do, but the finer your purpose the less it will serve, and for an ideally fine purpose, for absolute and general knowledge that will be as true for a man at a distance with a telescope as for a man with a microscope it will not serve at all.

Let me give you a rough idea of what I’m trying to express in this first critique of the philosophical validity of general terms. You’ve seen the results of those different methods of black and white reproduction that use a rectangular grid. You know the kind of process I’m talking about—it used to be very common for reproducing photographs. From a distance, it looks like a faithful reproduction of the original image, but when you look closely, you find that it’s made up of countless little rectangles, all uniform in shape and size. The more you dig into it, the closer you examine, the more the picture disappears into these grid patterns. I propose that the realm of reasoned inquiry has a very similar relationship to the world I call objectively real. For everyday purposes, the grid picture works just fine, but the more refined your goal, the less useful it becomes, and for a goal requiring absolute and general knowledge—knowledge that would be just as true for someone viewing through a telescope as for someone using a microscope—it won’t work at all.

It is true you can make your net of logical interpretation finer and finer, you can fine your classification more and more—up to a certain limit. But essentially you are working in limits, and as you come closer, as you look at finer and subtler things, as you leave the practical purpose for which the method exists, the element of error increases. Every species is vague, every term goes cloudy at its edges, and so in my way of thinking, relentless logic is only another phrase for a stupidity,—for a sort of intellectual pigheadedness. If you push a philosophical or metaphysical inquiry through a series of valid syllogisms—never committing any generally recognised fallacy—you nevertheless leave a certain rubbing and marginal loss of objective truth and you get deflections that are difficult to trace, at each phase in the process. Every species waggles about in its definition, every tool is a little loose in its handle, every scale has its individual error. So long as you are reasoning for practical purposes about the finite things of experience, you can every now and then check your process, and correct your adjustments. But not when you make what are called philosophical and theological inquiries, when you turn your implement towards the final absolute truth of things. Doing that is like firing at an inaccessible, unmarkable and indestructible target at an unknown distance, with a defective rifle and variable cartridges. Even if by chance you hit, you cannot know that you hit, and so it will matter nothing at all.

You can definitely refine your logical reasoning and improve your classifications, but only to a certain point. Ultimately, you're working within boundaries, and as you focus on finer details and move away from the practical purpose of the method, the possibility of error increases. Every category is unclear, every term loses its definition at the edges, and in my view, strict logic is just another term for a kind of intellectual stubbornness. If you carry a philosophical or metaphysical inquiry through a series of valid arguments—without making any recognized errors—you still end up with some loss of objective truth and obscure deviations at each step in the process. Every category is a bit vague in its definition, every tool has some looseness, and every measurement has an individual error. While you're reasoning about practical matters in the tangible world, you can occasionally reassess your process and make corrections. But when you delve into philosophical and theological questions, aiming for the ultimate truth, it's like trying to hit an unreachable, unidentifiable, and indestructible target from an unknown distance, using a faulty rifle and inconsistent ammunition. Even if you happen to hit it, you won't know that you did, so it makes no difference at all.

This assertion of the necessary untrustworthiness of all reasoning processes arising out of the fallacy of classification in what is quite conceivably a universe of uniques, forms only one introductory aspect of my general scepticism of the Instrument of Thought.

This claim about the unavoidable unreliability of all reasoning processes due to the fallacy of classification in what could easily be a universe of unique instances is just one introductory part of my overall skepticism about the Tool of Thought.

I have now to tell you of another aspect of this scepticism of the instrument which concerns negative terms.

I now need to tell you about another aspect of this skepticism regarding the instrument that relates to negative terms.

Classes in logic are not only represented by circles with a hard firm outline, whereas they have no such definite limits, but also there is a constant disposition to think of negative terms as if they represented positive classes. With words just as with numbers and abstract forms there are definite phases of human development. There is, you know, with regard to number, the phase when man can barely count at all, or counts in perfect good faith and sanity upon his fingers. Then there is the phase when he is struggling with the development of number, when he begins to elaborate all sorts of ideas about numbers, until at last he develops complex superstitions about perfect numbers and imperfect numbers, about threes and sevens and the like. The same is the case with abstracted forms, and even to-day we are scarcely more than heads out of the vast subtle muddle of thinking about spheres and ideally perfect forms and so on, that was the price of this little necessary step to clear thinking. You know better than I do how large a part numerical and geometrical magic, numerical and geometrical philosophy has played in the history of the mind. And the whole apparatus of language and mental communication is beset with like dangers. The language of the savage is, I suppose, purely positive; the thing has a name, the name has a thing. This indeed is the tradition of language, and to-day even, we, when we hear a name, are predisposed—and sometimes it is a very vicious disposition—to imagine forthwith something answering to the name. We are disposed, as an incurable mental vice, to accumulate intension in terms. If I say to you Wodget or Crump, you find yourself passing over the fact that these are nothings, these are, so to speak, mere blankety blanks, and trying to think what sort of thing a Wodget or a Crump may be. And where this disposition has come in, in its most alluring guise, is in the case of negative terms. Our instrument of knowledge persists in handling even such openly negative terms as the Absolute, the Infinite, as though they were real existences, and when the negative element is ever so little disguised, as it is in such a word as Omniscience, then the illusion of positive reality may be complete.

Classes in logic aren't just represented by circles with hard outlines, which they don't actually have, but there's also a tendency to think of negative terms as if they represented positive classes. Just like with numbers and abstract concepts, there are definite stages in human development. For instance, there’s the stage when a person can barely count or counts sincerely using their fingers. Then comes the stage where they wrestle with the concept of numbers, creating all kinds of ideas about them, eventually culminating in complex superstitions about perfect numbers, imperfect numbers, threes, sevens, and so on. The same goes for abstract forms, and even today we’re only just beginning to emerge from the complicated chaos of thinking about spheres and ideal forms, which is a small yet necessary step toward clear thinking. You know better than I do how significant numerical and geometrical magic, as well as philosophy, has been in the history of human thought. The entire framework of language and mental communication is fraught with similar risks. Primitive language is likely purely positive; a thing has a name, and the name corresponds to a thing. This is, after all, the tradition of language, and even today, when we hear a name, we tend to—sometimes dangerously—immediately imagine something that fits the name. We tend to, as an unavoidable mental flaw, accumulate meaning in terms. If I say "Wodget" or "Crump," you might overlook the fact that these are essentially meaningless; they are, so to speak, mere placeholders, and instead, you'll try to think of what a Wodget or a Crump could be. The most enticing instance of this tendency appears with negative terms. Our means of understanding continues to treat even clearly negative terms like the Absolute and the Infinite as if they were real entities, and when the negative aspect is just slightly hidden, as in the word Omniscience, the illusion of positive reality can be fully convincing.

Please remember that I am trying to tell you my philosophy, and not arguing about yours. Let me try and express how in my mind this matter of negative terms has shaped itself. I think of something which I may perhaps best describe as being off the stage or out of court, or as the Void without Implications, or as Nothingness or as Outer Darkness. This is a sort of hypothetical Beyond to the visible world of human thought, and thither I think all negative terms reach at last, and merge and become nothing. Whatever positive class you make, whatever boundary you draw, straight away from that boundary begins the corresponding negative class and passes into the illimitable horizon of nothingness. You talk of pink things, you ignore, if you are a trained logician, the more elusive shades of pink, and draw your line. Beyond is the not pink, known and knowable, and still in the not pink region one comes to the Outer Darkness. Not blue, not happy, not iron, all the not classes meet in that Outer Darkness. That same Outer Darkness and nothingness is infinite space, and infinite time, and any being of infinite qualities, and all that region I rule out of court in my philosophy altogether. I will neither affirm nor deny if I can help it about any not things. I will not deal with not things at all, except by accident and inadvertence. If I use the word ‘infinite’ I use it as one often uses ‘countless,’ “the countless hosts of the enemy”—or ‘immeasurable’—“immeasurable cliffs”—that is to say as the limit of measurement rather than as the limit of imaginary measurability, as a convenient equivalent to as many times this cloth yard as you can, and as many again and so on and so on. Now a great number of apparently positive terms are, or have become, practically negative terms and are under the same ban with me. A considerable number of terms that have played a great part in the world of thought, seem to me to be invalidated by this same defect, to have no content or an undefined content or an unjustifiable content. For example, that word Omniscient, as implying infinite knowledge, impresses me as being a word with a delusive air of being solid and full, when it is really hollow with no content whatever. I am persuaded that knowing is the relation of a conscious being to something not itself, that the thing known is defined as a system of parts and aspects and relationships, that knowledge is comprehension, and so that only finite things can know or be known. When you talk of a being of infinite extension and infinite duration, omniscient and omnipotent and Perfect, you seem to me to be talking in negatives of nothing whatever. When you speak of the Absolute you speak to me of nothing. If however you talk of a great yet finite and thinkable being, a being not myself, extending beyond my imagination in time and space, knowing all that I can think of as known and capable of doing all that I can think of as done, you come into the sphere of my mental operations, and into the scheme of my philosophy....

Please remember that I'm sharing my philosophy, not arguing about yours. Let me explain how I see this issue of negative terms. I think of something that I might best describe as being off the stage or out of court, or as the Void without Implications, or as Nothingness, or as Outer Darkness. This represents a sort of hypothetical Beyond to the visible world of human thought, and I believe all negative terms ultimately reach it, merge, and become nothing. Whatever positive category you create, whatever boundary you draw, just beyond that boundary starts the corresponding negative category and extends into the endless horizon of nothingness. You mention pink things, but if you’re a trained logician, you overlook the more subtle shades of pink and draw your line. Beyond is the not pink, known and knowable, yet within the not pink area, you arrive at the Outer Darkness. Not blue, not happy, not iron— all the not categories converge in that Outer Darkness. That same Outer Darkness and nothingness is infinite space, infinite time, and any being with infinite qualities, and I completely rule out that realm in my philosophy. I won’t affirm or deny anything about not things if I can avoid it. I won’t engage with not things at all, except by accident and oversight. When I use the word ‘infinite,’ I use it like one often uses ‘countless,’ as in “the countless hosts of the enemy”—or ‘immeasurable’ as in “immeasurable cliffs”—meaning the limit of measurement rather than the limit of imaginary measurability, as a convenient equivalent to as many times this cloth yard as you can, and then many more and so on. A large number of seemingly positive terms are, or have become, practically negative terms and are under the same restriction for me. Many terms that have held significant roles in the world of thought appear to me to be invalidated by this same issue—they have no content, or undefined content, or unjustifiable content. For instance, the word Omniscient, implying infinite knowledge, strikes me as a term with a deceptive sense of being solid and complete when it’s actually empty and without content. I believe that knowing is the relationship of a conscious being to something other than itself, that the thing known is defined as a system of parts, aspects, and relationships, and that knowledge is comprehension. Thus, only finite things can know or be known. When you describe a being of infinite extension and infinite duration—omniscient, omnipotent, and Perfect—you seem to be speaking about negatives of nothing at all. When you mention the Absolute, it means nothing to me. However, if you discuss a great yet finite and thinkable being—one that is not me, extending beyond my imagination in time and space, knowing all that I can conceive as known, and capable of doing all that I can imagine as done—you enter the realm of my mental operations and the framework of my philosophy.

These then are my first two charges against our Instrument of Knowledge, firstly, that it can work only by disregarding individuality and treating uniques as identically similar objects in this respect or that, so as to group them under one term, and that once it has done so it tends automatically to intensify the significance of that term, and secondly, that it can only deal freely with negative terms by treating them as though they were positive. But I have a further objection to the Instrument of Human Thought, that is not correlated to these former objections and that is also rather more difficult to convey.

These are my first two criticisms of our Knowledge System. First, it operates by ignoring individuality and treating unique individuals as if they were the same in certain ways, just to group them under one label. Once that’s done, it tends to raise the importance of that label. Second, it can only engage with negative concepts by framing them as if they were positive. However, I have another issue with the Human Thought System that isn’t related to these previous criticisms, and it’s a bit harder to explain.

Essentially this idea is to present a sort of stratification in human ideas. I have it very much in mind that various terms in our reasoning lie, as it were, at different levels and in different planes, and that we accomplish a large amount of error and confusion by reasoning terms together that do not lie or nearly lie in the same plane.

Essentially, this idea is to show a kind of hierarchy in human thoughts. I'm very aware that different terms in our reasoning exist at various levels and on different planes, and that we create a lot of mistakes and confusion by mixing terms together that don’t belong to the same plane or are only close to it.

Let me endeavour to make myself a little less obscure by a most flagrant instance from physical things. Suppose some one began to talk seriously of a man seeing an atom through a microscope, or better perhaps of cutting one in half with a knife. There are a number of non-analytical people who would be quite prepared to believe that an atom could be visible to the eye or cut in this manner. But any one at all conversant with physical conceptions would almost as soon think of killing the square root of 2 with a rook rifle as of cutting an atom in half with a knife. Our conception of an atom is reached through a process of hypothesis and analysis, and in the world of atoms there are no knives and no men to cut. If you have thought with a strong consistent mental movement, then when you have thought of your atom under the knife blade, your knife blade has itself become a cloud of swinging grouped atoms, and your microscope lens a little universe of oscillatory and vibratory molecules. If you think of the universe, thinking at the level of atoms, there is neither knife to cut, scale to weigh nor eye to see. The universe at that plane to which the mind of the molecular physicist descends has none of the shapes or forms of our common life whatever. This hand with which I write is in the universe of molecular physics a cloud of warring atoms and molecules, combining and recombining, colliding, rotating, flying hither and thither in the universal atmosphere of ether.

Let me try to make myself a bit clearer with a striking example from the physical world. Imagine someone starts seriously discussing a man seeing an atom through a microscope, or maybe even cutting one in half with a knife. There are quite a few people who would readily believe that an atom could be visible or cut this way. However, anyone familiar with physical concepts would rather think of trying to kill the square root of 2 with a rifle than believe in cutting an atom in half with a knife. Our understanding of an atom comes from a process of hypothesis and analysis, and in the realm of atoms, there are no knives or humans to make cuts. If you think with a strong, consistent mindset, then when you envision your atom under the knife blade, your knife blade itself becomes a cloud of swinging, grouped atoms, and your microscope lens turns into a tiny universe of oscillating and vibrating molecules. When you think about the universe at the atom level, there’s no knife to cut, no scale to measure, and no eye to see. The universe at that level to which the mind of the molecular physicist descends lacks any of the shapes or forms of our everyday life. This hand I write with is, in the universe of molecular physics, a cloud of colliding atoms and molecules, combining and recombining, rotating, and flying around in the universal atmosphere of ether.

You see, I hope, what I mean, when I say that the universe of molecular physics is at a different level from the universe of common experience;—what we call stable and solid is in that world a freely moving system of interlacing centres of force, what we call colour and sound is there no more than this length of vibration or that. We have reached to a conception of that universe of molecular physics by a great enterprise of organised analysis, and our universe of daily experiences stands in relation to that elemental world as if it were a synthesis of those elemental things.

You see, I hope, what I mean when I say that the world of molecular physics is on a different level than our everyday experience; what we consider stable and solid is actually a dynamic system of interconnected forces, and what we perceive as color and sound is just a certain length of vibration. We’ve come to understand that world of molecular physics through a massive effort of organized analysis, and our everyday experiences are related to that fundamental world as if they’re a combination of those basic elements.

I would suggest to you that this is only a very extreme instance of the general state of affairs, that there may be finer and subtler differences of level between one term and another, and that terms may very well be thought of as lying obliquely and as being twisted through different levels.

I would suggest that this is just a very extreme example of the overall situation, and that there might be more refined and nuanced differences in levels between one term and another. Terms can certainly be seen as slanting and being twisted through various levels.

It will perhaps give a clearer idea of what I am seeking to convey if I suggest a concrete image for the whole world of a man's thought and knowledge. Imagine a large clear jelly, in which at all angles and in all states of simplicity or contortion his ideas are imbedded. They are all valid and possible ideas as they lie, none in reality incompatible with any. If you imagine the direction of up or down in this clear jelly being as it were the direction in which one moves by analysis or by synthesis, if you go down for example from matter to atoms and centres of force and up to men and states and countries—if you will imagine the ideas lying in that manner—you will get the beginning of my intention. But our Instrument, our process of thinking, like a drawing before the discovery of perspective, appears to have difficulties with the third dimension, appears capable only of dealing with or reasoning about ideas by projecting them upon the same plane. It will be obvious that a great multitude of things may very well exist together in a solid jelly, which would be overlapping and incompatible and mutually destructive, when projected together upon one plane. Through the bias in our Instrument to do this, through reasoning between terms not in the same plane, an enormous amount of confusion, perplexity and mental deadlocking occurs.

It might help clarify what I'm trying to express if I suggest a concrete image for the entire realm of a person's thoughts and knowledge. Picture a large, clear jelly where all his ideas are embedded at various angles and in different states of simplicity or complexity. All these ideas are valid and possible as they are, with none truly incompatible with the others. If you think of moving up or down in this clear jelly as the process of analysis or synthesis—going down, for instance, from matter to atoms and forces, and up to people, governments, and countries—if you can visualize the ideas in that way, you’ll start to grasp what I mean. However, our thinking process, like a drawing before perspective was discovered, seems to struggle with understanding the third dimension, only able to deal with or reason about ideas by projecting them onto a flat plane. It's clear that a vast number of things could exist together in a solid jelly, which would overlap and conflict with each other when projected onto a single plane. This tendency of our thinking process leads to a great deal of confusion, puzzlement, and mental impasse.

The old theological deadlock between predestination and free-will serves admirably as an example of the sort of deadlock I mean. Take life at the level of common sensation and common experience and there is no more indisputable fact than man's freedom of will, unless it is his complete moral responsibility. But make only the least penetrating of analyses and you perceive a world of inevitable consequences, a rigid succession of cause and effect. Insist upon a flat agreement between the two, and there you are! The Instrument fails.

The old theological standoff between predestination and free will is a great example of the kind of deadlock I’m talking about. When you look at life through the lens of common feeling and experience, the existence of human free will is about as undeniable as the fact that we are completely morally responsible for our actions. But if you dig even a little deeper, you start to see a world full of unavoidable consequences, a strict chain of cause and effect. If you try to force a simple agreement between the two, that’s where you run into trouble! The Instrument fails.

It is upon these three objections, and upon an extreme suspicion of abstract terms which arises materially out of my first and second objections, that I chiefly rest my case for a profound scepticism of the remoter possibilities of the Instrument of Thought. It is a thing no more perfect than the human eye or the human ear, though like those other instruments it may have undefined possibilities of evolution towards increased range, and increased power.

My main argument for serious doubt about the more distant possibilities of the Instrument of Thought is based on these three objections and a strong skepticism about abstract terms, which comes largely from my first two objections. This instrument is no more perfect than the human eye or ear, although, like those tools, it could evolve in ways we can't fully define, leading to greater range and more power.

So much for my main contention. But before I conclude I may—since I am here—say a little more in the autobiographical vein, and with a view to your discussion to show how I reconcile this fundamental scepticism with the very positive beliefs about world-wide issues I possess, and the very definite distinction I make between right and wrong.

So that covers my main point. But before I wrap up, I’d like to say a bit more about my personal experiences, especially since I'm here. I want to explain how I balance this deep skepticism with my strong beliefs about global issues and the clear line I draw between right and wrong.

I reconcile these things by simply pointing out to you that if there is any validity in my image of that three dimensional jelly in which our ideas are suspended, such a reconciliation as you demand in logic, such a projection of the things as in accordance upon one plane, is totally unnecessary and impossible.

I settle these issues by simply pointing out that if my idea of that three-dimensional jelly, where our thoughts are suspended, has any truth to it, then the kind of reconciliation you’re asking for in logic—projecting everything onto one flat plane—is completely unnecessary and impossible.

This insistence upon the element of uniqueness in being, this subordination of the class to the individual difference, not only destroys the universal claim of philosophy, but the universal claim of ethical imperatives, the universal claim of any religious teaching. If you press me back upon my fundamental position I must confess I put faith and standards and rules of conduct upon exactly the same level as I put my belief of what is right in art, and what I consider right practice in art. I have arrived at a certain sort of self-knowledge and there are, I find, very distinct imperatives for me, but I am quite prepared to admit there is no proving them imperative on any one else. One's political proceedings, one's moral acts are, I hold, just as much self-expression as one's poetry or painting or music. But since life has for its primordial elements assimilation and aggression, I try not only to obey my imperatives, but to put them persuasively and convincingly into other minds, to bring about my good and to resist and overcome my evil as though they were the universal Good and the universal Evil in which unthinking men believe. And it is obviously in no way contradictory to this philosophy, for me, if I find others responding sympathetically to any notes of mine or if I find myself responding sympathetically to notes sounding about me, to give that common resemblance between myself and others a name, to refer these others and myself in common to this thing as if it were externalised and spanned us all.

This insistence on the uniqueness of each person, placing individual differences above class, not only undermines the universal claims of philosophy but also those of ethical imperatives and any religious teachings. If you challenge me to defend my fundamental beliefs, I must admit that I see faith, standards, and rules of conduct on the same level as my views on what is right in art and what I consider to be correct artistic practices. I've gained a certain level of self-awareness, and I've identified very specific imperatives for myself, but I'm willing to acknowledge that I can't prove they are essential for anyone else. I believe that one's political actions and moral decisions are just as much expressions of self as one's poetry, painting, or music. However, since life fundamentally involves both assimilation and aggression, I strive not only to follow my own imperatives but also to persuasively share them with others, aiming to achieve my good and to resist and overcome my evil as if they were the universal Good and Evil that many people unthinkingly accept. It’s clearly not contradictory to this philosophy for me to feel a connection to others who resonate with my thoughts or for me to feel a connection to the sounds around me. I can acknowledge that shared resemblance between myself and others and give it a name, referring to both them and myself as if that connection were something external that unites us all.

Scepticism of the Instrument is for example not incompatible with religious association and with organisation upon the basis of a common faith. It is possible to regard God as a Being synthetic in relation to men and societies, just as the idea of a universe of atoms and molecules and inorganic relationships is analytical in relation to human life.

Skepticism about the Instrument, for instance, can coexist with religious affiliation and organization built on a shared faith. It’s possible to see God as a synthetic Being in relation to people and societies, just as the concept of a universe made up of atoms, molecules, and inorganic relationships is analytical when it comes to human life.

The repudiation of demonstration in any but immediate and verifiable cases that this Scepticism of the Instrument amounts to, the abandonment of any universal validity for moral and religious propositions, brings ethical, social and religious teaching into the province of poetry, and does something to correct the estrangement between knowledge and beauty that is a feature of so much mental existence at this time. All these things are self-expression. Such an opinion sets a new and greater value on that penetrating and illuminating quality of mind we call insight, insight which when it faces towards the contradictions that arise out of the imperfections of the mental instrument is called humour. In these innate, unteachable qualities I hold—in humour and the sense of beauty—lies such hope of intellectual salvation from the original sin of our intellectual instrument as we may entertain in this uncertain and fluctuating world of unique appearances....

The rejection of demonstration except in clear and verifiable situations that this Skepticism of the Instrument represents, along with the dismissal of any universal validity for moral and religious statements, shifts ethical, social, and religious teachings into the realm of poetry. It also helps mend the divide between knowledge and beauty that characterizes much of our current mental existence. All of these aspects are forms of self-expression. This perspective places a new and greater value on that insightful and illuminating quality of mind we refer to as insight—an insight that, when it confronts the contradictions arising from the flaws of our mental tools, is known as humor. In these inherent, unteachable qualities—humor and a sense of beauty—lies the potential for intellectual salvation from the inherent flaws of our cognitive abilities in this unpredictable and ever-changing world of unique experiences....

So frankly I spread my little equipment of fundamental assumptions before you, heartily glad of the opportunity you have given me of taking them out, of looking at them with the particularity the presence of hearers ensures, and of hearing the impression they make upon you. Of course, such a sketch must have an inevitable crudity of effect. The time I had for it—I mean the time I was able to give in preparation—was altogether too limited for any exhaustive finish of presentation; but I think on the whole I have got the main lines of this sketch map of my mental basis true. Whether I have made myself comprehensible is a different question altogether. It is for you rather than me to say how this sketch map of mine lies with regard to your own more systematic cartography....

So honestly, I’m laying out my basic assumptions for you, really glad for the chance you’ve given me to pull them out, examine them with the attention that having an audience brings, and hear your thoughts on how they come across. Naturally, this overview will have a certain rawness to it. The time I had for preparation—meaning the time I could dedicate to it—was way too short for a thorough presentation; but overall, I think I’ve captured the main outlines of this map of my thinking accurately. Whether I’ve made myself clear is another question entirely. It’s up to you, rather than me, to decide how this map of mine aligns with your own more organized layout...

Here followed certain comments upon Personal Idealism, and Mr. F. C. S. Schiller's Humanism, of no particular value.

Here are some comments on Personal Idealism and Mr. F. C. S. Schiller's Humanism, which aren’t particularly valuable.


Download ePUB

If you like this ebook, consider a donation!