This is a modern-English version of The first French Republic : A study of the origin and the contents of the declaration of the rights of man, of the constitution, and of the adoption of the republican form of government in 1792, originally written by Conaway, Horace Mann.
It has been thoroughly updated, including changes to sentence structure, words, spelling,
and grammar—to ensure clarity for contemporary readers, while preserving the original spirit and nuance. If
you click on a paragraph, you will see the original text that we modified, and you can toggle between the two versions.
Scroll to the bottom of this page and you will find a free ePUB download link for this book.
THE FIRST FRENCH REPUBLIC
THE FIRST FRENCH REPUBLIC:
A STUDY OF THE ORIGIN AND THE CONTENTS OF THE DECLARATION
OF THE RIGHTS OF MAN, OF THE CONSTITUTION, AND OF
THE ADOPTION OF THE REPUBLICAN FORM OF
GOVERNMENT IN 1792.
THE FIRST FRENCH REPUBLIC:
A STUDY OF THE ORIGIN AND CONTENTS OF THE DECLARATION
OF THE RIGHTS OF MAN, THE CONSTITUTION, AND THE
ADOPTION OF THE REPUBLICAN FORM OF
GOVERNMENT IN 1792.
BY
HORACE MANN CONAWAY,
Sometime Fellow in European History in Columbia University.
BY
HORACE MANN CONAWAY,
Former Fellow in European History at Columbia University.
SUBMITTED IN PARTIAL FULFILLMENT OF THE REQUIREMENTS
FOR THE DEGREE OF DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY
IN THE
Faculty of Political Science
Columbia University.
SUBMITTED IN PARTIAL FULFILLMENT OF THE REQUIREMENTS
FOR THE DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY DEGREE
IN THE
Department of Political Science
Columbia University.
New York.
1902.
New York, 1902.
The present study is one of origins. Our object is to trace from the beginning the gradual development of the Declaration of the Rights of Man, of the first written constitution in France, and to follow the movement which led to the abolition of monarchy and to the adoption of the republican form of government. In view of the complex phenomena of the French Revolutionary period, it is advantageous to our understanding of that surpassingly interesting era to view the various classes of facts from different standpoints. The Revolution was social, religious, political, and economic. While the study of any one of these phases necessarily involves the others, the best results will be secured by considering the movement now as social, now as religious, now as political, and now as economic. This paper is an investigation of the early Revolution from the political point of view. Whence arose in the minds of the French the idea of a Declaration of the Rights of Man? Where did they derive the principles therein contained? How were they led to feel the need of a written constitution? Through what series of events were they brought to suspect, to denounce and to renounce royalty, and to accept the idea of an elective executive? Such questions as these are of interest to the student of political history.
The current study focuses on origins. Our goal is to trace the gradual development of the Declaration of the Rights of Man, the first written constitution in France, and to follow the movement that led to the abolition of the monarchy and the establishment of a republican form of government. Given the complex events of the French Revolutionary period, it's beneficial for our understanding of this incredibly interesting era to look at various classes of facts from different perspectives. The Revolution was social, religious, political, and economic. While studying any one of these aspects naturally involves the others, the best results will come from examining the movement first as social, then as religious, then as political, and finally as economic. This paper investigates the early Revolution from the political perspective. Where did the idea of a Declaration of the Rights of Man arise in the minds of the French? What principles did they draw from? How did they come to see the need for a written constitution? Through what series of events did they begin to suspect, denounce, and reject royalty, and embrace the concept of an elected executive? Questions like these are significant for anyone studying political history.
Though the primary sources for the investigation of this subject are limited in our American libraries, enough has been found to lead to an interpretation suggestive and, we believe, correct.
Though the main sources for exploring this topic are limited in our American libraries, we've found enough to suggest an interpretation that is both insightful and, we believe, accurate.
Recently two important books upon the French Revolution have appeared. M. A. Aulard published last year his Histoire politique de la Révolution française. In this work he has reexamined, in the light of the voluminous material at hand in France, these same questions. Prof. William M. Sloane, of Columbia University, has treated the Revolution primarily in its ecclesiastical aspects in his French Revolution and Religious Reform. The manuscript of this thesis was practically completed[6] before either of these works came into the writer’s hands. It did not seem advisable, therefore, to make any modifications in the conclusions herein reached; they are, however, in the main in accord with those arrived at by these two authors. The Declaration of the Rights of Man and the origin of the idea of a written constitution are here more fully discussed than by these writers.
Recently, two important books on the French Revolution have been published. M. A. Aulard released his Histoire politique de la Révolution française last year. In this work, he has reexamined, considering the extensive material available in France, the same questions. Prof. William M. Sloane from Columbia University has focused mainly on the Revolution’s ecclesiastical aspects in his French Revolution and Religious Reform. The manuscript of this thesis was nearly finished[a id="Page_6"> before either of these works came to the writer’s attention. It didn’t seem wise, therefore, to make any changes to the conclusions reached here; however, they generally align with those of these two authors. The Declaration of the Rights of Man and the origins of the idea of a written constitution are discussed in more detail than by these writers.
H. M. C.
HMC
Sheffield, Pa., August 5, 1902.
Sheffield, PA, August 5, 1902.
The first question that naturally suggests itself in studying the Declaration of the Rights of Man is, whence did the French derive the idea of such an instrument? It has been asserted, and an attempt has been made to prove, that both the notion of such a Declaration and its content were borrowed from the early American State Constitutions.[1] This question, however, really resolves itself into a double inquiry, i. e., whence did the French receive their notion of the guaranty of individual rights against governmental intrusion, and how far did the ideas contained in the Declaration of the Rights of Man represent the political traditions and current thought of France? Only a study of the abuses and of the political theories of pre-revolutionary France and of the facts relative to this document, as they are revealed in the writings of contemporaries and in the records of the Constituent Assembly, can at all satisfactorily answer these inquiries.
The first question that comes to mind when studying the Declaration of the Rights of Man is where the French got the idea for such a document. It has been claimed, and attempts have been made to show, that both the concept of this Declaration and its content were taken from the early American State Constitutions.[1] However, this question really breaks down into two parts: first, where did the French get their idea of protecting individual rights from government interference, and second, how much do the ideas in the Declaration of the Rights of Man reflect the political traditions and contemporary thinking in France? Only by examining the abuses and political theories of pre-revolutionary France, along with the facts about this document as seen in the writings of contemporary observers and records of the Constituent Assembly, can we adequately answer these questions.
The sympathetic relation between France and the colonies during and after the American Revolution, the interest in America of some of the more radical French political theorists, such as Mably and Condorcet, and the community of ideas existing between the two countries, shown by the Jeffersonian school in America, and by the publication of American writings in France, are facts well known. Hence it may be inferred that, when a few of the cahiers asked for a Declaration, their framers were acquainted with and influenced by the American Bills of Rights.[2][8] But not until the States General had assumed the rôle of a Constitutional Convention were the proposals of Declarations numerous. Then it was that the Frenchmen gave abundant proof of their fondness for formulating political documents.
The supportive relationship between France and its colonies during and after the American Revolution, along with the interest from some of the more radical French political thinkers like Mably and Condorcet, and the shared ideas between the two countries, highlighted by the Jeffersonian movement in America and the publication of American writings in France, are well understood. This suggests that when a few of the cahiers requested a Declaration, those who drafted it were familiar with and inspired by the American Bills of Rights.[2][8] However, it wasn't until the States General took on the role of a Constitutional Convention that the proposals for Declarations became widespread. It was then that the French demonstrated their strong inclination to create political documents.
On July 9, 1789, M. Mounier, who had been charged by the Constituent Assembly with the preparation of a scheme for a constitution, presented a report in behalf of the committee, the first article of which reads: “Tout gouvernement doit avoir pour unique but le maintien des droits des hommes; d’où il suit que pour rappeller constamment le gouvernement au but proposé, la constitution doit commencer par la déclaration des droits naturels et imprescriptibles de l’homme.”[3] July 11, Lafayette proposed the form of a Declaration of Rights, containing twelve articles, and pointed out the advantages of such an instrument.[4] M. Lally Tollendal approved this project, but argued that it was dangerous to adopt any such articles separate from the Constitution; he at the same time called the attention of the Assembly to the great difference between a new-born colonial people, who were breaking with a distant government, and an old nation extending over an immense territory, one of the first nations of the world, which for eight centuries had obeyed the same dynasty and had cherished the royal power when it had been tempered by custom. This nation, he said, will idolize this power when it shall be regulated by laws.[5] M. Lally Tollendal certainly believed that they were following the American example.
On July 9, 1789, M. Mounier, who had been assigned by the Constituent Assembly to prepare a draft for a constitution, presented a report on behalf of the committee, the first article of which states: “Every government must have as its sole purpose the protection of human rights; therefore, to keep the government focused on this goal, the constitution must begin with a declaration of the natural and inalienable rights of man.”[3] On July 11, Lafayette proposed the format of a Declaration of Rights, which included twelve articles, and highlighted the benefits of having such a document.[4] M. Lally Tollendal supported this initiative but warned that adopting any such articles separately from the Constitution could be risky; he also pointed out the significant difference between a newly formed colonial people breaking away from a distant government and an established nation with a vast territory, one of the first nations in the world, which had obeyed the same dynasty for eight centuries and had valued royal power when it was balanced by tradition. This nation, he noted, would likely cherish this power when it becomes governed by laws.[5] M. Lally Tollendal certainly believed they were following the American example.
July 14, Lafayette’s motion was discussed. Some thought the Declaration should be put at the head of the Constitution, in order permanently to secure the rights of man before establishing those of society; others thought it should be placed after the Constitution. It was decided at this session that the Constitution should contain a Declaration, but its position was left for later decision.[6] Siéyès read his exposition of the Rights of Man, on July 10, to the Constitutional Committee, and on July 21, to the Assembly.[7] On July 17, M. Target presented a scheme of thirty-one articles for a Declaration, and M. Mounier one of sixteen[9] articles.[8] On July 31, M. D. Servan, advocate to the Parlement of Grenoble, presented a project of thirteen articles. August 1, a long debate occurred upon the position to be given to the Declaration in the Constitution. M. Thouret also offered a scheme for a Declaration. The debate continued. On August 4, M. Camus proposed that the Assembly make a declaration of the rights and duties of man and of a citizen; but this motion was defeated by a vote of 570 to 433.[9] However, at the same session, it was decided almost unanimously that the Constitution should be preceded by the Declaration. On August 12, Abbé Siéyès offered a project of a Declaration of forty-two articles.[9]
July 14, Lafayette’s motion was discussed. Some believed the Declaration should come before the Constitution to ensure the rights of individuals are secured before establishing those of society; others felt it should follow the Constitution. It was decided during this session that the Constitution should include a Declaration, but its placement would be determined later. [6] Siéyès read his explanation of the Rights of Man on July 10 to the Constitutional Committee, and on July 21 to the Assembly. [7] On July 17, M. Target presented a proposal of thirty-one articles for a Declaration, and M. Mounier one of sixteen [9] articles. [8] On July 31, M. D. Servan, an advocate for the Parlement of Grenoble, presented a plan of thirteen articles. On August 1, there was a lengthy debate about where to place the Declaration in the Constitution. M. Thouret also proposed a plan for a Declaration. The debate continued. On August 4, M. Camus suggested that the Assembly create a declaration of the rights and duties of man and of a citizen; however, this motion was defeated by a vote of 570 to 433. [9] Still, in the same session, it was almost unanimously decided that the Constitution should come after the Declaration. On August 12, Abbé Siéyès presented a proposal for a Declaration of forty-two articles. [9]
During discussion in the Assembly, August 1, M. Champion de Cicé, Bishop of Auxerre, opposed a declaration as useless at that time, and said that the example of North America was not conclusive, as that country only contains proprietors, cultivators, and citizens all on the same social footing. M. De la Luzerne, Bishop of Langres, also asserted that the Constitution of an empire did not need a Declaration. M. Malouet, in making strong protest against their placing the Declaration at the head of the Constitution, portrayed the contrast between the situation of France and that of America.[10] M. Delandine spoke in agreement with M. Malouet.
During a discussion in the Assembly on August 1, M. Champion de Cicé, Bishop of Auxerre, argued against a declaration, calling it pointless at that time. He pointed out that the example of North America wasn't definitive since that country only has property owners, farmers, and citizens all on the same social level. M. De la Luzerne, Bishop of Langres, also claimed that an empire's Constitution didn't require a Declaration. M. Malouet strongly protested against placing the Declaration at the beginning of the Constitution, highlighting the differences between the situation in France and that in America. M. Delandine agreed with M. Malouet.
On August 12, two projects for a Declaration of Rights were offered to the Assembly: one of seventy-one articles, by Gonges-Carton of Quercy, and one of twenty-four articles, by the Sixth[10] Bureau of the Assembly. On August 13, a committee of five, consisting of Desmeuniers, Bishop of Langres, M. Tronchet, Count Mirabeau and M. Rhédon, was chosen to receive the drafts of a Constitution and to recast these into one form.[11] August 14, Mirabeau, on behalf of the committee, reported a scheme of a Declaration containing nineteen articles. In speaking of the aim of the committee, he said, that from the score of plans offered them, they had sought, like the Americans, to construct a Declaration not of abstract and scientific principles, but one of political truths that would readily be comprehended by the popular mind.[12] In the debate of August 18 upon the Declaration, M. Rabaud de Saint Étienne said that the Declaration of Rights had been adopted because the cahiers had asked it, and that the cahiers had asked it because the Americans had set the example, but that this was no reason why the Declarations should be similar, for the circumstances of the two nations were different.[13]
On August 12, two proposals for a Declaration of Rights were presented to the Assembly: one with seventy-one articles by Gonges-Carton of Quercy, and another with twenty-four articles from the Sixth[10] Bureau of the Assembly. On August 13, a committee of five members was formed, including Desmeuniers, the Bishop of Langres, M. Tronchet, Count Mirabeau, and M. Rhédon, to compile the drafts of a Constitution and unify them into a single document. On August 14, Mirabeau, representing the committee, introduced a proposal for a Declaration consisting of nineteen articles. In discussing the committee's goal, he stated that from the numerous plans they received, they aimed, like the Americans, to create a Declaration not based on abstract and scientific ideas but on political truths that would be easily understood by the general public. In the debate on August 18 regarding the Declaration, M. Rabaud de Saint Étienne noted that the Declaration of Rights was adopted because the cahiers had requested it, and the cahiers had requested it because the Americans set a precedent, but that was no reason for the Declarations to be the same, as the circumstances of the two nations were different.
August 19, the Assembly decided to discuss first the Declaration of the Sixth Bureau.[14] On August 21, after some debate, the Assembly adopted the preamble of the plan, somewhat modified, presented by the committee of five. M. Mounier then proposed three articles, which were adopted. August 21, on the proposal of M. Alexander de Lameth, articles four, five, and six, after discussion, were adopted.
August 19, the Assembly chose to first discuss the Declaration of the Sixth Bureau.[14] On August 21, after some debate, the Assembly approved the preamble of the plan, with some modifications, as put forth by the committee of five. M. Mounier then proposed three articles, which were accepted. On August 21, at the suggestion of M. Alexander de Lameth, articles four, five, and six were adopted after discussion.
August 21, M. de Boislander proposed a plan of seventy-four articles. August 22, after divers proposals had been made and[11] discussed, articles seven, eight, and nine were adopted.[15] August 23, after many proposals and lengthy debate, article ten was agreed upon. August 24, a liberal discussion of the phraseology resulted in the adoption of articles eleven, twelve, and thirteen.[16] August 26, after some discussion, articles fourteen and fifteen were accepted; later in the same day, articles sixteen and seventeen were agreed upon.[17] Then the Assembly resolved that the consideration of further articles should be postponed until the Constitution should be completed.[18] October 2, the articles previously adopted were presented to the Assembly, with article four changed from “La liberté consiste à faire tout ce qui ne nuit pas à autrui,” to “La liberté consiste à pouvoir faire tout” etc. The change was accepted. The whole Constitution was presented to the king September 13, 1791, and accepted by him. In the Assembly, September 14, the king swore to obey the constitution.[19]
August 21, M. de Boislander proposed a plan of seventy-four articles. August 22, after various proposals had been made and discussed, articles seven, eight, and nine were adopted. August 23, after many proposals and lengthy debate, article ten was agreed upon. August 24, a thorough discussion of the wording resulted in the adoption of articles eleven, twelve, and thirteen. August 26, after some discussion, articles fourteen and fifteen were accepted; later that same day, articles sixteen and seventeen were agreed upon. Then the Assembly decided that the consideration of further articles should be postponed until the Constitution was completed. October 2, the previously adopted articles were presented to the Assembly, with article four changed from “La liberté consiste à faire tout ce qui ne nuit pas à autrui,” to “La liberté consiste à pouvoir faire tout” etc. The change was accepted. The whole Constitution was presented to the king on September 13, 1791, and he accepted it. In the Assembly, on September 14, the king swore to obey the constitution.
These are the facts of historical data relating to the formation of the Declaration of the Rights of Man purposely set forth in detail and in chronological order. What conclusions may we draw from them? The frequent reference to the American Bill of Rights, the number of Declarations proposed in cahiers and before the Assembly, differing in form and in length, but agreeing in fundamental principles, the discussions, the selections and the modifications to which this raw material was subjected in the process of constructing the Declaration finally adopted, warrant these two inferences: (1) the notion of a Declaration of Rights, separate from the Constitution proper, was suggested to the French by the American State Constitutions; (2) the contents of the articles and the language in which they were couched were original.
These are the facts about the historical data related to the creation of the Declaration of the Rights of Man, presented in detail and chronological order. What conclusions can we draw from this? The frequent references to the American Bill of Rights, the various Declarations proposed in cahiers and before the Assembly, which differed in format and length but were consistent in fundamental principles, along with the discussions, selections, and modifications this raw material underwent while constructing the final Declaration, support these two conclusions: (1) the idea of a Declaration of Rights, separate from the Constitution itself, was inspired by the American State Constitutions; (2) the content of the articles and the way they were expressed were original.
A study of the separate articles of the Declaration in the light of contemporary conditions gives additional reason for thinking that the ideas therein contained were not foreign to France. For convenience of consideration in the present study, the articles of the Declaration may be divided into two classes: the first class consists of those articles that were in the main reactive against certain abuses under which the French suffered; the second class[12] comprises those articles which contained principles more especially theoretical. Less proof, perhaps, is necessary for deciding upon the originality of the former class than upon that of the latter. We shall treat these classes in the order named.
A study of the individual articles of the Declaration in relation to current conditions provides more reasons to believe that the ideas expressed were not unfamiliar to France. For the sake of clarity in this study, we can categorize the articles of the Declaration into two groups: the first group includes those articles primarily responding to specific abuses that the French faced; the second group[12] consists of those articles that outline principles that are more theoretical. It may require less evidence to determine the originality of the first group than the second. We will address these groups in the order mentioned.
“Art. 7. No person shall be accused, arrested or imprisoned except in the cases and according to the forms prescribed by law. Any one soliciting, transmitting, executing, or causing to be executed any arbitrary order shall be punished. But any citizen summoned or arrested in virtue of the law shall submit without delay, as resistance constitutes an offense.
“Art. 7. No one shall be accused, arrested, or imprisoned except in the cases and according to the procedures established by law. Anyone requesting, passing on, carrying out, or causing to be carried out any unjust order shall be punished. However, any citizen who is summoned or arrested under the law must comply without delay, as resistance is considered an offense.”
“Art. 8. The law shall provide for such punishments only as are strictly and obviously necessary, and no one shall suffer punishment except it be legally inflicted in virtue of a law, passed and promulgated before the commission of the offence.
“Art. 8. The law will only impose punishments that are strictly and clearly necessary, and no one shall be punished unless it is done legally according to a law that was enacted and announced before the offense was committed.
“Art. 9. As all persons are held innocent until they shall have been declared guilty, if arrest shall be deemed indispensable, all severity not essential to the securing of the prisoner’s person shall be severely repressed by law.”
“Art. 9. Everyone is considered innocent until proven guilty. If an arrest is necessary, any harsh treatment not essential to detaining the person must be strictly punished by law.”
That these three articles were aimed at no imaginary or very distant wrongs is evident from a cursory survey of the administration of the laws of France, and from the protests of French authors. Lettres de cachet, arbitrary imprisonments, retroactive laws, and cruelly exaggerated penalties were not uncommon. Mirabeau and Voltaire had both suffered under arbitrary laws and had painted the injustice of such laws in lurid colors. Mirabeau’s Lettres de cachet and his Essai sur le despotisme bristle with protests against the abuses of the old régime. The following gruesome picture is a suggestive statement of the way in which justice was administered in France in the eighteenth century:
That these three articles were directed at real and pressing issues is clear from a quick look at how laws were enforced in France and from the complaints of French writers. Lettres de cachet, arbitrary imprisonments, retroactive laws, and severely harsh punishments were common. Both Mirabeau and Voltaire experienced the impact of these arbitrary laws and vividly described their injustices. Mirabeau’s Lettres de cachet and his Essai sur le despotisme are filled with objections against the abuses of the old régime. The following disturbing image is a telling statement of how justice was carried out in France during the eighteenth century:
“The disproportion of crimes and of penalties was flagrant. A house thief was hung in 1733; an ecclesiastic, guilty of having found fault with the expulsion of the Jesuits, was also hung in 1762. The procedure was unjust and inhuman. The accused, assumed to be guilty in advance, ignorant of the crime with which he was charged, without counsellor or advocate, interrogated à huis clos, submitted to the preparatory question, was judged secretly. Once condemned, he was tortured before undergoing his punishment. And what punishment! For imprisonment, transportation or hanging was in vogue. The burning at the stake had fallen into desuetude, but the lash, branding with red-hot[13] iron, the galleys, quartering, the rack, still did their savage work.”[20]
“The imbalance between crimes and punishments was outrageous. A thief was executed in 1733; a clergyman who criticized the expulsion of the Jesuits was also executed in 1762. The process was unfair and cruel. The accused was presumed guilty from the start, unaware of the charges against him, without legal representation, questioned in secret, and judged behind closed doors. Once convicted, he was tortured before facing his punishment. And what a punishment it was! Imprisonment, exile, or hanging was common. While burning at the stake had become rare, whipping, branding with hot iron, forced labor, dismemberment, and the rack still inflicted their brutal torture.”[20]
Protests against these enormities were raised by the philosophers, and later by enlightened magistrates, such as Montesquieu, Servan, Linguet, and Malesherbes. In 1780, the “preparatory question” was abolished.[21]
Protests against these wrongs were raised by philosophers and later by progressive officials, like Montesquieu, Servan, Linguet, and Malesherbes. In 1780, the “preparatory question” was eliminated.[21]
Mirabeau, in denouncing retroactive laws, says: “Nulle puissance humaine, ni surhumaine ne peut justifier l’effet rétroactif d’aucune loi.”[22]
Mirabeau, in condemning retroactive laws, says: “No human power, nor superhuman, can justify the retroactive effect of any law.”[22]
“Art. 10. No one shall be disquieted on account of his opinions, including his religious views, provided their manifestation does not disturb the public order established by law.”
“Art. 10. No one shall be disturbed because of their opinions, including their religious beliefs, as long as expressing them does not disrupt the public order established by law.”
Since the sixteenth century, France had been wrestling with the problem of how to adjust two hostile faiths to each other. Farther to complicate the matter, a schism occurred in the seventeenth century within the Catholic Church, which aroused between Jesuits and the Jansenists a feeling of intolerance, well-nigh as violent and determined as that which already existed between the Catholics and the Huguenots. Even in the eighteenth century intolerance, held in partial abeyance, frequently broke out in overt acts, which displayed the vindictiveness of the hostile parties. The philosophers, more interested in humanity than in the prejudices of any faction, championed in the name of tolerance the party persecuted. The new spirit gained support. The writings of the latter half of the eighteenth century abound with denunciations of intolerance and with pleas for tolerance.[23] By and by the movement was fruitful, and on January[14] 19, 1788, the Parlement of Paris registered a decree giving civil rights to Protestants.[24]
Since the sixteenth century, France had been struggling with how to reconcile two opposing faiths. To complicate things further, a schism occurred in the seventeenth century within the Catholic Church, leading to intense intolerance between the Jesuits and the Jansenists, nearly as fierce as the existing conflict between Catholics and Huguenots. Even in the eighteenth century, the intolerance that had been somewhat suppressed frequently flared up in acts that demonstrated the hostility of both sides. Philosophers, more focused on humanity than on the biases of any group, defended the persecuted in the name of tolerance. This new perspective gained traction. The writings from the latter part of the eighteenth century are filled with condemnations of intolerance and calls for tolerance. Gradually, the movement proved effective, and on January[14] 19, 1788, the Parlement of Paris registered a decree granting civil rights to Protestants.
“Art. 11. The free communication of ideas and opinions is one of the most precious of the rights of man. Every citizen may, accordingly, speak, write, and print with freedom, but shall be responsible for the abuse of this freedom as shall be defined by law.”
“Art. 11. The free exchange of ideas and opinions is one of the most valuable rights of individuals. Every citizen can, therefore, speak, write, and publish freely, but will be held accountable for any misuse of this freedom as defined by law.”
Here too is an attempt to secure permanently that for which a long struggle had taken place. Two powers, the Church and Royalty, had labored, now singly and now together, to regulate the expression of ideas. The writing and the writer had been equally the object of royal inclemency—the one being consigned to the flames, the other to prison. But in spite of royal decrees, public sentiment gravitated towards liberty of expression. In 1776, Malesherbes secured the opening of the prisons of Vincennes and the Bastille for the release of prisoners held under Lettres de cachet.[25] Again, in 1784, in response to Mirabeau’s “Lettres de cachet,” the dungeons of Vincennes were opened.[26]
Here is another attempt to permanently secure what had been fought for over a long time. Two powers, the Church and the monarchy, had tried, sometimes separately and sometimes together, to control how ideas were expressed. Both writing and the writer faced harsh treatment from the monarchy—the former ended up burned, and the latter in prison. However, despite royal orders, public opinion leaned towards freedom of expression. In 1776, Malesherbes managed to open the prisons of Vincennes and the Bastille to free prisoners held under Lettres de cachet.[25] Then, in 1784, in response to Mirabeau’s “Lettres de cachet,” the dungeons of Vincennes were opened.[26]
“Art. 12. The security of the rights of man and of the citizen requires a public force. This force is, therefore, established for the good of all and not for the personal advantage of those to whom it shall be entrusted.”
“Art. 12. The protection of human and citizen rights requires a public force. This force is established for the benefit of everyone and not for the personal gain of those who are given the responsibility.”
This twelfth article was at the same time the expression of a political theory and reactionary against past practices. It was the theory of the framers of the Declaration of the Rights of Man that the nation was supreme, the monarch only an hereditary administrative agent. To maintain this status, the power of military force must be employed only for the advantage of the nation. d’Argenson, in 1754, had complained that “Le roi n’emploie plus ses forces que contre ses sujets.”[27] In 1771, when the obstinate parlement had been replaced by the Grand Conseil, troops were used to guard this substitute which was designated “Maupeou’s parlement,” and the people considered the whole procedure as contrary to the French Constitution.[28] Mirabeau had also denounced[15] the royal army in these plain words: “Je dis que les troupes réglées sont l’instrument du despotisme, comme leur institution en fut le signal. L’exemple de nos voisins n’est pas une preuve contradictoire; et ne voit on pas en effet que toute constitution en Europe est dégénérée en arbitraire et s’accélère vers le despotisme; Les troupes réglées ont été et seront toujours le fléau de la liberté; mais ce fléau est intolérable quand il devient le rempart des déprédations.”[29]
This twelfth article was both an expression of a political theory and a reaction against past practices. The theory put forth by the framers of the Declaration of the Rights of Man claimed that the nation was supreme, with the monarch serving merely as a hereditary administrative agent. To uphold this status, military force should be used only for the benefit of the nation. d’Argenson, in 1754, had complained that “The king only uses his forces against his subjects.” In 1771, when the stubborn parlement was replaced by the Grand Conseil, troops were deployed to guard this substitute, which was labeled “Maupeou’s parlement,” and the people viewed the whole process as contrary to the French Constitution. Mirabeau also condemned the royal army with these straightforward words: “I say that regular troops are the instrument of despotism, just as their establishment was the signal for it. The example of our neighbors is not contradictory evidence; and do we not see that every constitution in Europe has degenerated into arbitrariness and is accelerating toward despotism? Regular troops have been and will always be the scourge of freedom; but this scourge becomes intolerable when it is used as a shield for plunder.”
The people in several of the cahiers manifested fear lest the monarch might endanger, by the use of an army, the national rights, and consequently asked for the dismissal of foreign troops, for a new constitution for the army, and for the destruction of internal forts.[30]
The people in several of the cahiers expressed concern that the king might jeopardize national rights by using the military, and therefore requested the removal of foreign troops, a new constitution for the army, and the dismantling of internal forts.[30]
“Art. 13. A common contribution is essential for the maintenance of the public forces and for the cost of administration. This should be equitably distributed among all the citizens in proportion to their means.”
“Art. 13. A common contribution is essential for maintaining the public forces and covering administrative costs. This should be fairly distributed among all citizens according to their means.”
The inequality of taxes was, in France, an abuse recognized and condemned for centuries. Bodin, in his République, written in the sixteenth century, criticised the exemption of the clergy and of the nobility.[31] Already under Louis XIII., throughout two-thirds of France, where the taille was a personal tax, 2,000,000 of richer persons were exempt from the taille, while 8,000,000 were taxable. D’Avenel says that the workmen paid under Louis XIII. four and a half times as much as to-day, though they earned much less.[32] The grievous exemptions continued so that the Third Estate during the eighteenth century supported the chief burden of royal taxes and was subjected to onerous feudal dues besides.[33]
The inequality of taxes was an issue in France that had been recognized and condemned for centuries. Bodin, in his République, written in the sixteenth century, criticized the exemption of the clergy and nobility. [31] Even under Louis XIII, in two-thirds of France, where the taille was a personal tax, 2,000,000 wealthier individuals were exempt from the taille, while 8,000,000 were taxed. D’Avenel notes that workers paid four and a half times more than they do today under Louis XIII, even though their earnings were much lower. [32] The severe exemptions continued, meaning the Third Estate bore the main burden of royal taxes during the eighteenth century and also faced heavy feudal dues. [33]
The Physiocrats advocated as a remedy for this injustice a system which should make the taxes proportionate to each one’s productive riches. Turgot, taking the first step towards the realization of this idea, said, in defense of his proposal for the abolition of corvées, February, 1776: “The expenses of government having for their object the interest of all, all should contribute to them; and the more one enjoys the advantages of society, the more one should regard himself honored in sharing the expenses.[34] But his efforts were vain; for the privileged classes esteemed their exemptions too highly to submit tamely to a burdensome reform; hence they stubbornly persisted in their resistance to innovations in the customary methods of collecting taxes. Nevertheless there was a growing sentiment in favor of reform;[35] so that when the cahiers of 1789 were prepared, the majority of those of the higher orders acceded to an equal partition in the burdens of the fisc.[36]
The Physiocrats suggested a solution for this injustice: a system where taxes were based on each person's productive wealth. Turgot, taking the first step towards making this idea a reality, stated in defense of his proposal to eliminate corvées in February 1776: "Since government expenses serve the interests of everyone, everyone should contribute to them; and the more someone benefits from society, the more they should feel honored to share in the costs.[34] But his efforts were in vain; the privileged classes valued their exemptions too much to accept a major reform lightly; thus, they stubbornly resisted changes to the traditional ways of collecting taxes. Still, there was a growing support for reform;[35] so when the cahiers of 1789 were prepared, most of those from the higher orders agreed to a fair distribution of the financial burdens.[36]
“Art. 14. All the citizens have a right to decide, either personally or by their representatives, upon the necessity of the public contribution; to grant this freely; to know to what uses it is put, and to fix the proportion, the mode of assessment and of collection, and the duration of the taxes.”
“Art. 14. All citizens have the right to decide, either personally or through their representatives, on the necessity of public contributions; to grant this freely; to know how it is used, and to determine the amount, the method of assessment and collection, and the duration of the taxes.”
The French monarch, as in other European countries, from the time that the royal domains were found insufficient to meet the governmental expenses, was engaged in a continual struggle with the nation over the right to grant subsidies. The nation asserted only sporadically and incoherently its right to vote these supplies. For the French did not manifest that persistent and determined resistance to appropriations, unrequited by redress of political grievances, which their English neighbors exhibited so often and in such a marked degree. Nevertheless, during a minority or under a weak monarch, when able popular leaders flourished, the cause of the people was more stubbornly maintained. The States General claimed this guardianship in earlier days; but in the two centuries previous to the Revolution it was the Parlement of Paris that contended with increasing vigor and obstinacy against the arbitrary exactions of the king. As a final resort, it[17] asserted, July 30, 1787, that “le principe constitutionnel de la monarchie française était que les impôts fussent consentis par ceux qui devraient les supporter.”[37] The continued and inextricable confusion of finances was the immediate cause of the calling of the Notables, and later of the States General. So far had the public sentiment reacted against the actual fiscal mismanagement, that the cashier were well-nigh unanimous in seeking for the nation the right to grant subsidies.[38]
The French king, like rulers in other European nations, faced ongoing struggles with the people regarding his authority to impose taxes once the royal lands no longer covered government expenses. The public only occasionally and inconsistently asserted its right to approve these taxes. Unlike their English neighbors, who often showed a strong and persistent resistance to taxation without political reform, the French did not demonstrate the same level of determination. However, during times when a young monarch ruled or a weak king was in power, popular leaders would emerge, fiercely advocating for the people's rights. In earlier times, the States General claimed this responsibility; but in the two centuries leading up to the Revolution, it was the Parlement of Paris that increasingly and stubbornly fought against the king's arbitrary tax demands. As a last resort, it stated on July 30, 1787, that "the constitutional principle of the French monarchy was that taxes should be agreed upon by those who would pay them." The ongoing and tangled financial crisis was the main reason for calling the Notables, and later the States General. Public sentiment had turned so strongly against the government's financial mismanagement that the cashier nearly unanimously sought the people's right to approve taxes.
“Art. 15. Society has a right to require of every public agent an account of his administration.”
“Art. 15. Society has the right to demand accountability from every public agent regarding their administration.”
Article 15 was both theoretical and reactionary against actual abuses. If the nation was to be supreme over all of its agents, it could only hope effectually to maintain that superiority by holding all its functionaries strictly accountable. Practical experience under the monarchy in the collection and the expenditure of finances had impressed an effective lesson upon the French people of the abuses incident to irresponsible officers. The Cour des Aides, in its noteworthy remonstrance of 1775, reviewed the status of the financial administration. The injustice of the ferme, the arbitrariness of the bureaucracy, the complexity of the system, the failure of popular petitions to reach the throne, and the need of thorough reform, were clearly set forth.[39] Then, too, Necker, by the publication of his Compte rendu (1781) and L’Administration des finances (1785), had afforded the nation a glimpse of public finances imperfect, yet in the highest degree stimulating to its curiosity.[40] As an illustration of the status of public opinion, the[18] Notables in 1787 demanded that some report of receipts and expenses should be published annually, and that capable men, foreign to the administration, should be called to the conseil des finances for reviewing the work.[41] Here, too, the cahiers were practically a unit in their demands.
Article 15 was both theoretical and a response to real abuses. If the nation was to be the highest authority over all its agents, it could only effectively maintain that authority by holding all its officials strictly accountable. Practical experience under the monarchy with collecting and spending finances had taught the French people an important lesson about the abuses caused by irresponsible officers. The Cour des Aides, in its significant complaint of 1775, reviewed the state of the financial administration. The unfairness of the ferme, the arbitrary nature of the bureaucracy, the complexity of the system, the failure of popular petitions to reach the throne, and the need for thorough reform were clearly outlined. [39] Additionally, Necker, through the publication of his Compte rendu (1781) and L’Administration des finances (1785), had given the nation a glimpse of public finances that was incomplete yet highly stimulating to its curiosity. [40] As an example of public opinion, the[18] Notables in 1787 demanded that a report of receipts and expenses should be published annually, and that capable individuals, not part of the administration, should be invited to the conseil des finances to review the work. [41] Here, too, the cahiers were practically unanimous in their demands.
“Art. 17. Since property is an inviolable and sacred right, no one shall be deprived thereof except where public necessity, legally determined, shall clearly demand it, and then only on condition that the owner shall have been previously and equitably indemnified.”
“Art. 17. Since property is an inviolable and sacred right, no one can be deprived of it except when public necessity, as legally determined, clearly requires it, and then only if the owner has been fairly compensated beforehand.”
Private property under the ancien régime was not sacred. De Tocqueville cites the following, which may serve us for illustration of the condition: “A royal declaration was made, suspending in time of war repayment of all loans contracted by towns, villages, colleges, communities, hospitals, charitable houses, trade corporations and others, repayable out of town dues by us conceded, though the instrument securing the said loans stipulates for the payment of interest in the case of non-payment at the stipulated time. Thus not only is the obligation of repayment at the stipulated terms suspended, but the security itself is impaired.”[42] This article, seventeenth, was also reactive against the grievous and burdensome corvées, military convoys, and forced transportation of convicts.[43]
Private property under the ancien régime was not inviolable. De Tocqueville mentions the following, which illustrates the situation: “A royal declaration was issued, suspending the repayment of all loans taken on by towns, villages, colleges, communities, hospitals, charitable organizations, trade corporations, and others during wartime, which were to be repaid from the town dues we agreed upon, although the document securing these loans specified the payment of interest if they were not repaid on time. Therefore, not only is the obligation to repay under the agreed terms suspended, but the security itself is also weakened.”[42] This article, the seventeenth, also addressed the heavy and burdensome corvées, military convoys, and the forced transportation of convicts.[43]
The remaining seven articles are more theoretical, covering the doctrines of liberty, equality, natural and inalienable rights, national sovereignty, the social contract and the separation of powers. The views expressed were, in the main, accepted at least in theory in the American States. France was not, however, indebted to the colonies for them; although their germinal ideas had been introduced from the teachings of foreign writers, notably from the English, they had grown up in France largely as a home product.
The last seven articles are more theoretical, focusing on the principles of liberty, equality, natural and inalienable rights, national sovereignty, the social contract, and the separation of powers. The ideas presented were mostly accepted, at least in theory, in the American States. However, France did not owe these concepts to the colonies; while their foundational ideas came from foreign writers, especially the English, they developed in France largely as a domestic creation.
The doctrine of national or popular sovereignty was no new conception for the French nation. It had been appealed to by the Church to check the secular power, and by the Empire to check[19] ecclesiastical encroachments. Thomas Aquinas, the oracle of the Church, had recognized the popular will as a limitation upon the royal power, and had commended the elective form of monarchy.[44] Marsilio of Padua, in his Defensor Pacis, was even more pronounced in favor of popular sovereignty. “The sovereignty of the State,” he said, “rests with the people; by it properly are the laws made and to it they owe their validity. From the nation itself proceeds all rights and powers, it is the authoritative lawgiver among men.”[45] In the sixteenth century the Calvinists and the League alternately made use of the theory of popular sovereignty.[46] This theory was revived in the eighteenth century and popularized by Rousseau and his disciples.
The idea of national or popular sovereignty wasn't new for the French nation. The Church used it to limit secular power, and the Empire used it to curb ecclesiastical overreach. Thomas Aquinas, a key figure for the Church, recognized the people's will as a constraint on royal authority and supported the idea of an elected monarchy. Marsilio of Padua, in his *Defensor Pacis*, was even clearer about supporting popular sovereignty. “The sovereignty of the State,” he stated, “rests with the people; it is they who properly make the laws, and to them the laws owe their validity. All rights and powers come from the nation itself; it is the ultimate lawmaker among humans.” In the sixteenth century, both the Calvinists and the League alternately leveraged the theory of popular sovereignty. This theory saw a revival in the eighteenth century, popularized by Rousseau and his followers.
The doctrine of natural rights has not so remote an origin for France. De Tocqueville rightly pointed out the distinction between liberty, regarded as “the enjoyment of a privilege” and liberty considered as “the exercise of a universal right”; he also showed that the Romans and the feudal aristocracy figured their liberties to themselves under the former type; and that it was not till the eighteenth century that the French nation began to conceive of liberty as a natural right.[47]
The concept of natural rights has its roots not too far back for France. De Tocqueville accurately noted the difference between liberty seen as “enjoying a privilege” and liberty viewed as “exercising a universal right.” He also demonstrated that the Romans and the feudal aristocracy regarded their liberties in the former way. It wasn't until the eighteenth century that the French people started to understand liberty as a natural right.[47]
This transformation of the theory of liberty from a privilege to a natural right was chiefly accomplished after 1734. Boulainvilliers, in L’Histoire de l’ancien gouvernement de la France, published (1727) in Holland after his death, asserted as its fundamental thought: “Le gouvernement féodal est le chef d’oeuvre de l’ésprit humain.” To the author, all progress of royal, civil, or municipal authority is an usurpation of the rights of the nobility, who were the only heirs of the early Franks, conquerors of the Gauls.[48] This champion of the feudal aristocracy was not answered in the name of democracy, but of privileged rights. Abbé Dubois, the secretary of the French Academy, replied in “the name of Roman Gaul, semi-municipal and semi-monarchical.” This reply, entitled, “Histoire critique de l’établissement de la monarchie française”[20] (1734), denied the Frankish conquest and asserted that the French monarchy had succeeded in a peaceable way to the rights of the Roman Empire over the Gauls, and that the feudal system had been established by usurpation several centuries later. Public opinion and the judgment of the savants, says Martin, pronounced in favor of Dubois.[49]
This shift in the theory of liberty from being a privilege to a natural right mainly happened after 1734. Boulainvilliers, in L’Histoire de l’ancien gouvernement de la France, published (1727) in Holland after his death, stated as his main idea: “Feudal government is the masterpiece of the human spirit.” For him, any advancement of royal, civil, or municipal authority was an infringement on the rights of the nobility, who were viewed as the true descendants of the early Franks, conquerors of the Gauls.[48] This defender of the feudal aristocracy was challenged not by advocates of democracy but by supporters of privileged rights. Abbé Dubois, the secretary of the French Academy, responded “in the name of Roman Gaul, semi-municipal and semi-monarchical.” His response, titled “Histoire critique de l’établissement de la monarchie française”[20] (1734), rejected the notion of the Frankish conquest and claimed that the French monarchy peacefully took over the rights of the Roman Empire over the Gauls, arguing that the feudal system was set up through usurpation many centuries later. According to Martin, public opinion and the judgment of the savants favored Dubois.[49]
Saint Pierre, d’Argenson, and Montesquieu contributed to the political literature of the century, but did not formulate a new theory of rights. The Physiocrats applied the natural law to economic problems, but not specifically to political questions; this was reserved for Rousseau. In the Genevan philosopher’s writings, natural rights and kindred democratic ideas were treated in such a popular style that they were able to revolutionize the French political theories in a generation.
Saint Pierre, d’Argenson, and Montesquieu contributed to the political literature of the century, but they didn't create a new theory of rights. The Physiocrats applied natural law to economic issues but not specifically to political questions; that was left to Rousseau. In the writings of the Genevan philosopher, natural rights and similar democratic ideas were presented in such a popular way that they were able to transform French political theories within a generation.
A critical student cannot attribute complete originality to Rousseau; the similarity of his views to those of Locke is too striking. He borrowed from his English predecessor psychological, philosophical and political conceptions.[50] The Contrat Social (1762), however, according with the nascent political Zeit-Geist of France, found conditions favorable to the ready acceptance of its ideas. The philosophers had shaken the authority of dogma, humanitarian views were gaining prominence, men were tired of arbitrary imprisonments and of useless privileges, moreover, the long struggle between the monarch and the parlements was still unsettled, the theory of the right of parlement to refuse to record decrees was found to need a firmer basis than custom. The sympathies of even the nobles were awakened in behalf of the peasants and the curates. The Physiocrats hoped for tax reform, to be effected by a strong sovereign, though, when attempted by Turgot, it had failed. Amid such conditions the Contrat Social[21] was being read. Its striking, stimulating apothegms furnished apt quotations. Its effect was revolutionary. Even philosophers and magistrates were not insensible to its stimulus.[51] When the nation was called to speak, on the eve of the Estates General, in pamphlets and in cahiers, the influence of Rousseau was patent. The speeches made in the National Assembly were constantly interlarded with quotations and ideas from Contrat Social.[52]
A critical student cannot fully credit Rousseau with originality; the similarities between his views and those of Locke are too obvious. He took psychological, philosophical, and political ideas from his English predecessor. The Contrat Social (1762), however, aligned with the emerging political Zeit-Geist of France, found a favorable environment for its ideas to be quickly embraced. Philosophers had challenged the authority of dogma, humanitarian perspectives were becoming popular, people were tired of arbitrary arrests and unnecessary privileges. Additionally, the long conflict between the monarch and the parlements was still unresolved, and the theory of the parlement's right to refuse to record decrees needed a stronger foundation than tradition. Even the nobility began to sympathize with the peasants and the curates. The Physiocrats hoped for tax reform to be enacted by a strong leader, although Turgot's attempts had failed. Under such circumstances, the Contrat Social[21] was being widely read. Its striking and provocative maxims provided great quotes. Its impact was revolutionary. Even philosophers and magistrates were not immune to its influence. When the nation was called to express itself, on the eve of the Estates General, in pamphlets and cahiers, Rousseau's influence was clear. The speeches made in the National Assembly were frequently filled with quotes and ideas from the Contrat Social.[22]
After this general introduction to the political theories of the Revolution, we are ready to examine the remaining articles of the Declaration of the Rights of Man. We shall place in parallel with these some quotations from the Contrat Social that will serve to indicate the similarity of their ideas.
After this broad introduction to the political theories of the Revolution, we are ready to look at the other articles of the Declaration of the Rights of Man. We will compare these with some quotes from the Contrat Social that will show how similar their ideas are.
“1. Men are born and remain free and equal in rights. Social distinctions may only be founded upon the general good.” “1. Everyone is born free and equal in rights. Social distinctions can only be based on the common good.” |
“It is agreed that anything of power or property or liberty which is alienated by the social compact, is only a part of all the use of which is of importance to the community.”[53] “It is agreed that anything of power, property, or freedom that is given up through the social agreement is just a part of the overall benefits that matter to the community.”[53] |
“2. The aim of all political associations is the preservation of the national and imprescriptible rights of man. These rights are liberty, property, security, and resistance of oppression.” “2. The goal of all political groups is to protect the national and inalienable rights of individuals. These rights include freedom, property, safety, and the ability to resist oppression.” |
“To find a form of association which shall defend and protect with the public force the person and property of each associate, and by means of which each, uniting with all, shall obey however only himself, and remain as free as before; such is the fundamental problem of which the Social Contract gives the solution.”[54][22] “To create a type of organization that will defend and protect the individual and their property using the power of the community, and that allows each person to join together while still obeying only themselves and remaining as free as they were before; this is the core issue that the Social Contract addresses.”[54][22] |
“3. The principle [principe] of all sovereignty resides essentially in the nation. No body nor individual may exercise any authority which does not proceed directly from the nation.” “3. The principle of all sovereignty resides essentially in the nation. No body or individual can exercise any authority that doesn’t come directly from the nation.” |
“I say then that the sovereignty, being only the exercise of the general will, can never alienate itself, and that the sovereign, who is not a collective being, can be represented only by himself; power can transmit itself, but not will.”[55] “I say that sovereignty, which is just the expression of the general will, can never give itself away, and that the sovereign, who is not a collective entity, can only represent itself; power can be passed on, but not will.”[55] |
“4. Liberty consists in being able to do everything which injures no one else; hence the exercise of the natural rights of each man has no limits except those which assure to the other member of the society the enjoyment of the same rights. These limits can only be determined by law.” “4. Liberty means being able to do anything that doesn’t harm anyone else; therefore, the exercise of each person’s natural rights has no limits except those that guarantee other members of society the enjoyment of the same rights. These limits can only be defined by law.” |
“Any service that a citizen can render the State is due from him whenever the sovereign demands it; but the sovereign, for his part, cannot place any burden upon his subjects which will not be useful to the community; he can not even desire to do so, for, under the law of reason as under the law of nature, there is nothing done without a purpose.”[56] “Any service that a citizen can provide to the State is required whenever the government demands it; however, the government cannot impose any burden on its citizens that won’t benefit the community. It shouldn't even want to, because both the law of reason and the law of nature dictate that nothing is done without a purpose.”[56] |
“5. Law can only prohibit such actions as are hurtful to society. Nothing may be prevented which is not forbidden by law, and no one may be forced to do anything not provided for by law.” “5. The law can only ban actions that harm society. Nothing can be stopped unless the law prohibits it, and no one can be compelled to do anything that isn't outlined by the law.” |
“When I say that the object of laws is always general, I mean that the law considers subjects in a body, and actions as abstract; a man is never considered as an individual nor an action as an individual action.”[57] “When I say that the purpose of laws is always general, I mean that the law views people as a whole and actions as concepts; a person is never seen as an individual nor an action as a specific action.”[57] |
“6. Law is the expression of the general will. Every citizen has a right to participate personally or through his representatives in its formation. It must be the same for all, whether it protects or punishes. All citizens, being equal in the eyes of the law, are equally eligible to all dignities and to all public positions and occupations, according to their abilities and without distinction except that of their virtues and talents.” “6. Law represents the collective will. Every citizen has the right to participate, either directly or through their representatives, in creating it. It must apply equally to everyone, whether it provides protection or imposes punishment. All citizens, being equal under the law, are equally qualified for all honors, public offices, and jobs based on their abilities, with distinctions only made for their virtues and talents.” |
“By whatever path we return to the principle, we always reach the same conclusion; that the social compact establishes among citizens such an equality that they all engage under the same conditions, and should enjoy the same rights. Thus by the nature of the agreement, an act of sovereignty, that is, any authentic act of the general will, obliges or favors equally all citizens; so that the sovereign knows only the body of the nation and distinguishes no one of those composing it.”[58] “Regardless of how we approach the principle, we always arrive at the same conclusion: the social contract creates an equality among citizens, so that they all participate under the same conditions and should have the same rights. Therefore, by the nature of this agreement, any genuine act of the general will obligates or benefits all citizens equally; thus, the sovereign recognizes only the nation as a whole and does not single out any individual within it.”[58] |
The Physiocrats also had, in a measure, advocated these principles. Both Quesnay and Turgot expressed themselves unequivocally for the protection of private property.[59] Let it be asserted with the strongest emphasis that these six articles were not[23] merely the expression of theories. They had an intensely practical genesis, for they were the slowly-matured product of a reaction against a long-felt vexatious regime. That regime had interfered with private property and with individual action in such ways as to be grievous, yes, intensely grievous to the people.
The Physiocrats also somewhat supported these principles. Both Quesnay and Turgot clearly advocated for the protection of private property.
“Art. 16. A society in which the observance of the law is not assured, nor the separation of powers defined, has no constitution at all.”
“Art. 16. A society where the rule of law isn’t guaranteed, and the separation of powers isn’t clearly defined, doesn’t have a constitution at all.”
The theory of the separation of powers was one idea taught by Montesquieu[60] that had been gradually accepted by his countrymen. He was studied by the would-be-publicists of the Revolutionary era, and much stress was put upon this constitutional principle. The Constitution which they formed is the best example of the thorough application of this impracticable doctrine.[61]
The theory of the separation of powers was one idea taught by Montesquieu[60] that had been gradually accepted by his fellow countrymen. He was studied by the aspiring writers of the Revolutionary era, and a lot of emphasis was placed on this constitutional principle. The Constitution they established is the best example of the complete application of this difficult doctrine.[61]
In this discussion we have shown that while the suggestion of a Declaration of Rights came from the early American State Constitutions, its content was French. Its internal resemblance to the American instruments is attributable to the fact that the abuses to be feared and the recognized political theories were the same in both countries. In truth, France had greater reason to apprehend the return of the long-endured abuses, from which she was even then endeavoring to extricate herself, than had America. Likewise the fact that each country had derived its democratic views from a common source—the teachings of the English Puritans—largely explains the identity of the existing political theories.
In this discussion, we’ve shown that while the idea of a Declaration of Rights originated from the early American State Constitutions, its content was influenced by French ideas. The similarities to American documents can be attributed to the fact that the fears of abuses and the recognized political theories were similar in both countries. In reality, France had more reason to worry about the return of long-standing abuses, from which it was then trying to free itself, than America did. Additionally, the fact that both countries derived their democratic views from a shared source—the teachings of the English Puritans—helps explain the alignment of their political theories.
The States-General which met at Versailles, May 5, 1789, assumed in the following June the name of National Assembly, and undertook the formulation of a written constitution. According to the current views, this epochal transformation was either a political freak of an old monarchy, newly leavened with democratic ideas, or a manifestation of the rare phenomenon of a nation’s being carried sympathetically in the wake of a distant and new-born republic. But a careful consideration of the events, institutions, and conditions of France previous to the action of the National Assembly proves conclusively that the traditional interpretations are not correct.
The States-General that met at Versailles on May 5, 1789, took on the name National Assembly the following June and began working on a written constitution. According to popular opinion, this significant change was seen as either a political oddity of an old monarchy now influenced by democratic ideas, or as a rare case of a nation being inspired by a distant, newly established republic. However, a closer look at the events, institutions, and conditions in France before the National Assembly's actions clearly shows that the traditional interpretations are incorrect.
It is foreign to the province of the present paper to explore minutely the shadowy historical region, whence arose the political institutions of monarchical France, or to analyze exhaustively those institutions themselves. It is sufficient to note that already at the beginning of the XVII. century there had developed certain institutions with a normal mode of procedure, that may justly be called a constitution, not embraced in written documents, but one implied in the institutions and usages. The leading features of that constituted government were four: the King, the States-General, the Conseil d’État and the Parlements.
It’s not the focus of this paper to dive deeply into the vague historical background that gave rise to the political institutions of monarchical France, or to thoroughly analyze those institutions. It’s enough to mention that by the early 17th century, certain institutions had developed a standard way of operating that can rightfully be called a constitution, even though it wasn’t written down, but rather implied through practices and customs. The main components of that governmental structure were four: the King, the States-General, the Conseil d’État, and the Parlements.
The king was not only the executive, but the initiator of laws, and the source of justice.
The king was not just the head of the government, but also the one who created laws and ensured justice.
The States-General, judged by precedents, was an advisory body to the king, about which there existed much uncertainty as to its composition, its powers and its period of assembling. It was dependent upon the monarch for convocation, and for the promulgation of the results of its deliberations.[62]
The States-General, based on past examples, served as an advisory group to the king, creating a lot of confusion regarding who was part of it, what authority it had, and when it would meet. It relied on the monarch to call it together and to announce the outcomes of its discussions.[62]
The Conseil d’État, composed of the nobility, was, in a narrower sense, the permanent advisory council of the king. In this body the laws originated, and under its supervision the administration[25] was accomplished. It also had judicial functions, being superior to the Parlement as a cour de cassation in civil cases.
The Conseil d’État, made up of nobles, was, in a more specific sense, the king's permanent advisory council. This body originated the laws, and under its oversight, the administration[25] was carried out. It also had judicial responsibilities, acting as a higher court than the Parlement in civil cases.
The duties of the Parlements were primarily judicial, but in addition the Parlement of Paris possessed legislative functions, inasmuch as the laws were sent to it for registration. The Parlement by custom had come to make use of remonstrances to the king in case of laws distasteful to them. Though some monarchs, as Louis XI., XII., and Henry IV., had paid some regard to these remonstrances,[63] yet even in the sixteenth century the remonstrance did not stop the determined monarch, but the court was forced to yield to the royal wish in the lit de justice.[64] There existed, therefore, a singular balance of power between the Conseil d’État and the Parlement. The Conseil d’État, as a cour de cassation, might annul the parliamentary remonstrance, and, inversely, the Parlement might, in virtue of its power to register, check the laws originating from the Conseil d’État. It is worthy of remark, however, that even at this period, this normal distribution of functions was not so balanced and guarded as to avoid abnormal procedure. Neither the States General nor the Parlement was put wholly beyond the control of the executive.
The duties of the Parlements were mainly judicial, but the Parlement of Paris also had legislative functions since laws were sent to it for registration. By tradition, the Parlement used remonstrances to the king for laws they found objectionable. While some kings, like Louis XI, XII, and Henry IV, acknowledged these remonstrances, even in the sixteenth century they did not deter a determined monarch, and the court ultimately had to yield to the king’s wishes in the lit de justice. There was, therefore, a unique balance of power between the Conseil d’État and the Parlement. The Conseil d’État, acting as a cour de cassation, could annul parliamentary remonstrances, while the Parlement could, due to its registration power, check laws coming from the Conseil d’État. However, it's important to note that even during this time, this typical distribution of functions was not balanced enough to prevent unusual procedures. Neither the States General nor the Parlement was completely free from executive control.
D’Avenel, expressing a view not uncommon in the earlier days of the Revolution of 1789, asserts in his remarkable book, Richelieu et la monarchie absolue, that France had a constitution before the ministry of the politic Richelieu, yet not thereafter,[65] but it is difficult to defend such a declaration. It may be admitted that the States-General were no longer convoked after 1614, that the personnel of the nobility was altered, that the Parlement was now and then forced into acquiescence to the royal will; nevertheless the two bodies, the Conseil d’État and the Parlement, continued to function very nearly as before, and at times the Parlement emerged from its submissiveness and haughtily asserted its pretensions.
D’Avenel, sharing a common opinion from the early days of the 1789 Revolution, claims in his notable book, Richelieu et la monarchie absolue, that France had a constitution before Richelieu's political leadership, but not afterwards,[65] though it's hard to support such a statement. It can be acknowledged that the States-General were no longer called after 1614, that the makeup of the nobility changed, and that the Parlement was occasionally compelled to accept the king's wishes; however, the two entities, the Conseil d’État and the Parlement, continued to operate almost as they had before, and at times the Parlement broke free from its subservience and boldly asserted its claims.
In a series of conflicts between the court and the Parlement, into which we have not space to go exhaustively, the idea of fundamental or constitutional laws, of which the Parlement declared itself the guardian, was repeatedly asserted; in the later period of[26] this constitutional struggle, partly from the inability of the Parlement to maintain its pretensions and partly from the development of the ideas of natural rights, of the rights of the people and of the rights of the nation, the desire for some more distinct definition of the power of the executive and the rights of the nation became manifest. The Parlement, composed of an aristocracy whose office was an hereditary possession, was naturally alert to extend its political influence; this extension of necessity brought it into conflict with the absolutism of the monarch. When a vigorous monarch, or skillful, energetic minister was at the head of affairs, the Parlement was driven to humble obedience; but where there was a regency, a weak monarch, or a crisis, financial or administrative, the legal aristocracy reasserted and extended their pretensions. By a decree of February 21, 1641, Richelieu declared that the parlements had been established only for granting justice, forbade any modification of decrees, ordered that in financial matters they might remonstrate once, but in administrative matters no remonstrance was allowed. During the remainder of Louis XIII’s reign they were obedient; but on the death of the king they immediately manifested their vitality by breaking his will and fixing the regency.[66]
In a series of conflicts between the court and the Parlement, which we don't have enough space to cover in detail, the idea of fundamental or constitutional laws, which the Parlement claimed to protect, was repeatedly emphasized. In the later stages of this constitutional struggle, partly due to the Parlement's inability to maintain its claims and partly because of the rise of ideas surrounding natural rights, the rights of the people, and the rights of the nation, the demand for a clearer definition of the executive's power and the nation’s rights became evident. The Parlement, made up of an aristocracy with hereditary positions, was naturally keen to expand its political influence; this expansion inevitably led to conflicts with the king's absolute power. When a strong monarch or a skilled, active minister was in charge, the Parlement was forced into submission; however, during a regency, a weak king, or a financial or administrative crisis, the legal aristocracy reasserted and amplified their claims. In a decree on February 21, 1641, Richelieu stated that the parlements were only established to administer justice, prohibited any changes to decrees, mandated that they could only protest financial decisions once, and did not allow any protests regarding administrative matters. During the rest of Louis XIII’s reign, they complied; but upon the king's death, they quickly demonstrated their significance by disregarding his will and establishing the regency.
The Fronde was the acme of the parliamentary resistance of this period. Louis XIV. did not forget this high-handed opposition, and consequently by two decrees he reduced this recalcitrant body to a strictly subordinate position for the last forty years of his reign.[67] But on the death of the Grand Monarch, the Parlement showed its old spirit, annulled the will of the dead king concerning the regency, and for twenty years solemnly reiterated its[27] vague constitutional claims in elaborate remonstrances. To this period of activity succeeded a time of comparative submission, in which the remonstrances are less prompt, haughty, and insistent.
The Fronde was the peak of parliamentary resistance during this time. Louis XIV didn’t forget this strong opposition, so he issued two decrees that put this defiant group in a strictly subordinate role for the last forty years of his reign.[67] However, after the Grand Monarch died, the Parlement displayed its old spirit, canceled the deceased king’s will regarding the regency, and for twenty years, repeatedly asserted its[27] unclear constitutional claims in detailed protests. This active period was followed by a time of relative submission, during which the protests became less immediate, arrogant, and forceful.
In 1748, the struggle renewed itself, and soon each side showed an ardent determination to conquer. The monarch resorted to lits de justice, to exile, and to the institution of irregular courts in order to provoke the magistrates to obey, while they answered with iterative remonstrances and with refusals to dispense justice. From these remonstrances we are able to ascertain the pretensions of the Parlement, and to trace, though with much vagueness and incoherence, those principles which they called constitutional and fundamental. On the other hand, the responses of the king reveal the persistent claims of absolutism as to the royal source of law.
In 1748, the conflict began again, and soon both sides displayed a strong desire to win. The king used lits de justice, exiles, and irregular courts to pressure the magistrates into submission, while the magistrates responded with iterative protests and refused to deliver justice. From these protests, we can understand the claims of the Parlement and identify, albeit somewhat vaguely and incoherently, the principles they considered constitutional and fundamental. On the other side, the king's responses showcase his unwavering belief in absolutism and the royal source of law.
The magistrates based their shadowy claims upon different grounds. Frequently they appealed to precedent; as in 1718, the Parlement of Paris declared that the most absolute kings, specifically Louis XIV., had continually made use of the Parlement for registration.[68] Justice and expediency were also invoked in their support.
The magistrates based their vague claims on different reasons. They often referred to past cases; for example, in 1718, the Parlement of Paris stated that even the most absolute kings, particularly Louis XIV, had consistently used the Parlement for registration.[68] They also cited justice and practicality in their defense.
Already in the period of the regency, following closely after their submissiveness under Louis XIV, we find a hazy but general distinction between statutory and constitutional laws: “While we recognize, Sire, that you alone are lord and master and the sole lawgiver, and that there are laws which changing times, the needs of your people, the maintenance of order and the administration of your kingdom may oblige you to modify, substituting new ones according to the forms always observed in this state, we nevertheless believe it to be our duty to call to your attention the existence of laws as old as the monarchy, which are permanent and invariable, the guardianship of which was committed to you along with the crown itself.... It is by reason of the permanence of such laws that we have you as lord and master. It is this permanence which leads us to hope that the crown, having rested upon your head during a long, just, and glorious reign, will pass to your posterity for all time to come. In recent times [the Parlement adds] it has been clearly shown how much[28] France owes to the maintenance of these original laws of the state, and how important it is in the service of your Majesty that your Parlement, which is responsible to you and to the nation for their exact observations, should assiduously guard them against any encroachment.”[69] Here then is found in embryo the programme which the magistrates pursued in their legislative opposition to the crown. Nevertheless there is, judging from a comparison of these earlier remonstrances and those emitted later, some progress in the distinction of organic and of statutory law, and in the enumeration of the fundamental principles.
Already in the regency period, just after their submission under Louis XIV, we see a vague but general distinction between statutory and constitutional laws: “While we acknowledge, Your Majesty, that you are the sole lord and master and the only lawmaker, and that circumstances, the needs of your people, the maintenance of order, and the administration of your kingdom may require you to change laws, substituting new ones in accordance with the established procedures of this state, we still believe it is our duty to bring to your attention the existence of laws as old as the monarchy itself, which are permanent and unchanging, and whose guardianship was entrusted to you alongside the crown.... It is because of the permanence of such laws that we recognize you as lord and master. This permanence gives us hope that the crown, having been worn by you during a long, just, and glorious reign, will be passed down to your descendants for eternity. Recently [the Parlement adds] it has been clearly demonstrated how much France relies on the maintenance of these original laws of the state, and how vital it is for your Majesty that your Parlement, which is accountable to you and to the nation for their precise observance, should diligently protect them from any violations.”[69] Here we find the beginnings of the agenda that the magistrates pursued in their legislative opposition to the crown. However, based on a comparison of these earlier objections and those made later, there seems to be some progress in distinguishing between organic and statutory law, as well as in outlining the fundamental principles.
The Parlement of Brittany, in a remonstrance of July, 1771, said: “There is an essential difference between the transitory regulations which vary with the times, and the fundamental laws upon which the Constitution of the monarchy rests. In respect to the former [that is the transitory regulations] it is the duty of the courts to direct and enlighten the ruling power (l’autorité), although their opinions must, in the last instance, yield to the decision of your wisdom, since it appertains to you alone to regulate everything relating to the administration. To administer the state is not, however, to change its constitution.... It is, therefore, most indispensable to distinguish or to except the cases where the right of expostulation suffices to enlighten the ruling power in an administration which, in spite of its wide scope, still has its limits, and those cases where the happy inability [of the monarch] to overstep the bounds established by the constitution implies the power necessary legally to oppose what an arbitrary will cannot and may not do.”[70] To determine accurately the content of the lois fondamentales of which the Parlements asserted themselves to be protectors, is difficult. The Parlements themselves did not deem it expedient, either for their own claims or for those of the monarch, to attempt a too explicit formulation of these laws; vagueness was regarded a political virtue. A remonstrance of the cour des comptes, aides et finances of Normandy, openly admitted the disadvantage of such an enumeration: “Deign, Sire, to examine for yourself to what the decree of December[29] tends; it seems destined to draw the line between the power of the sovereign and the liberty of his subjects; this line always undetermined, which no hand has been bold enough to fix, which a salutary veil covers with useful shadows; the tenderness of princes for their people and the love of the people for their princes draw or withdraw these shadows according to the times or the reigns. Those who dare to-day to fix these limits and to say to France: There ends the legitimate liberty of the people, serve your interests badly, even politically.”[71]
The Parlement of Brittany, in a statement from July 1771, said: “There’s a crucial difference between temporary rules that change over time and the fundamental laws that support the monarchy's Constitution. Regarding the temporary rules, it’s the duty of the courts to guide and inform the ruling authority, although ultimately, their opinions must defer to your judgment, as it’s up to you alone to manage everything related to governance. Running the state doesn’t mean altering its constitution.... Therefore, it’s essential to differentiate between situations where the right to express concerns is enough to inform the ruling authority in an administration that, despite its broad reach, has its limits, and instances where the monarch's fortunate inability to overstep constitutional boundaries carries with it the legal power to oppose actions that an arbitrary will cannot and should not take.” [70] Accurately defining the contents of the lois fondamentales, which the Parlements claimed to protect, is challenging. The Parlements themselves didn’t find it wise to explicitly state these laws for the sake of their own claims or those of the monarch; ambiguity was seen as a political strength. A statement from the cour des comptes, aides et finances of Normandy openly acknowledged the drawbacks of such a list: “Please, Your Majesty, consider what the decree of December[29] aims for; it appears to be intended to draw the line between the sovereign's power and the freedom of his subjects; this line remains undefined, with no one daring enough to establish it, shielded by a beneficial veil that casts useful shadows; the affection of princes for their people and the people's love for their princes shift these shadows depending on the times or reigns. Those who dare today to set these boundaries and declare to France: Here lies the legitimate freedom of the people, do a disservice to both your interests and the political landscape.” [71]
The most precise formulation of the organic law of the French monarchy which I have found is the protest of the princes, signed April 4, 1771, and directed against the Maupeou Parlement: “We, the undersigned, consider that the French monarchy has been sustained, together with the glory, the splendor, and the power which it has enjoyed for so many centuries only by the maintenance of the primitive laws which are inherent in it, and form its title (droit) and essence; that the liberty belonging to every Frenchman, the title and the ownership of his property, that of inheriting from fathers or of receiving from relatives or friends, without being able to be deprived or hindered, otherwise than by the legal application of law for some crime previously and competently judged, and not by arbitrary and absolute will, are not the only rights of the nation and of the subjects nor the only fundamental laws of the monarchy; that the right of Frenchmen, one of the most useful to the monarch and one of the most precious to his subjects, is to have certain bodies of citizens, perpetual and irremovable, acknowledged in all times by the kings and by the nation, who under whatever form and name they have existed, concentrated in themselves the general right of every subject to invoke the laws, to demand their rights, and to have recourse to the Prince; whose most important functions have always been to be charged with watching over the maintenance of the established laws, to weigh in new laws their utility or the dangers of contradictions which might occur with the old laws, to verify them, and to represent to the sovereign all that is prejudicial to the rights of his subjects or to the primordial and constitutive laws of his kingdom ...; that this necessary[30] surety cannot exist without irremovability of the title of those to whom are confided so important functions, that they have always been regarded as one of the principal safeguards of public liberty against the abuse of arbitrary power; that they are an integral part of the constitution of the State, and are found as much as any other law in the order of the fundamental laws of the monarchy.”[72] However, the apparent attempt to be explicit here originates primarily, not in a desire to state distinctly the constitutional law, but rather to protect the prerogatives of the Parlements by coupling them with certain principles generally recognized as inviolable.
The clearest explanation of the organic law of the French monarchy that I've come across is the protest from the princes, signed on April 4, 1771, and directed against the Maupeou Parlement: “We, the undersigned, believe that the French monarchy has been upheld, along with the glory, splendor, and power it has enjoyed for so many centuries, only by maintaining the original laws that are intrinsic to it and form its title (droit) and essence; that the freedom belonging to every Frenchman, the title and ownership of his property, the right to inherit from parents or receive from relatives or friends, without being deprived or obstructed unless through the lawful application of law for some crime previously judged, and not by arbitrary and absolute will, are not the only rights of the nation and its subjects or the only fundamental laws of the monarchy; that the right of Frenchmen, which is one of the most beneficial to the monarch and one of the most precious to his subjects, is to have certain permanent and irremovable bodies of citizens, recognized throughout time by the kings and the nation, who, under any form and name they have existed, represent the general right of every subject to invoke the laws, to demand their rights, and to appeal to the Prince; whose main functions have always been to ensure the maintenance of established laws, to evaluate new laws for their usefulness or the potential dangers of contradictions with old laws, to verify them, and to inform the sovereign of anything that harms the rights of his subjects or the fundamental and constitutive laws of his kingdom ...; that this necessary[30] surety cannot exist without the irremovability of the title of those entrusted with such important functions, as they have always been seen as one of the key safeguards of public liberty against the abuse of arbitrary power; that they are an essential part of the constitution of the State and exist just like any other law within the fundamental laws of the monarchy.”[72] However, the apparent attempt to be clear here arises mainly, not from a desire to explicitly state the constitutional law, but rather to protect the prerogatives of the Parlements by linking them with certain principles generally recognized as inviolable.
The Parlements, in their resistance to the royal power, showed, as early as the Fronde, a tendency to support each other, but it is particularly in the period of the Maupeou Parlement that the claims to unity and indivisibility became prominent.[73] These remonstrances, as well as the royal responses, were not withheld from the public, as the ordonnances which imposed upon the magistrates the duty of keeping their deliberations secret implied, but were hawked about the streets and eagerly welcomed by the people. Since in times of opposition, each Parlement aroused the sympathies of the citizens under its jurisdiction, their combination for mutual support against the crown extended the area of popular agitation. This exciting literature, issuing from the different courts, had, therefore, an educative effect upon the popular mind, rather in emphasizing the need of some limitation to royal power than in developing distinct and well-defined notions of political laws.[74] The Parlement, while professing exemplary obedience to the king, said that there were moral limits to their obedience.[75] That also took a popular turn, in professing to represent[31] the nation or the people in the absence of the States-General. The remonstrance of the cour des aides, probably drawn up by Malesherbes, in February, 1771, indicates these popular pretensions. “The courts are to-day the only protectors of the feeble and the unfortunate: there have existed for a long time no States-General and in the greater part of the kingdom no provincial estates; all the bodies, except the courts, are reduced to a mute and passive obedience. No individual in the provinces would venture to expose himself to the vengeance of a commandant, of a commissaire du conseil, and still less to those of a minister of Your Majesty. The courts are then the only ones to whom it is still permitted to raise a voice in favor of the people, and Your Majesty does not wish to take away this last resource from distant provinces. But this decree, exiling the Parlement of Paris, tends to render this resource illusory.”[76]
The Parlements, in their opposition to royal authority, demonstrated, as early as the Fronde, a tendency to support one another. However, it was especially during the time of the Maupeou Parlement that the claims for unity and indivisibility became prominent.[73] These remonstrances, along with the royal responses, were not kept from the public, as the ordonnances that required magistrates to keep their discussions secret implied, but were circulated in the streets and eagerly welcomed by the people. During times of opposition, each Parlement gained the support of the citizens within its jurisdiction, and their combined efforts against the crown expanded the scope of popular agitation. This provocative literature, emerging from the various courts, had an educational impact on the public mindset, focusing more on the necessity of some limitations to royal power than on forming distinct and well-defined political laws.[74] The Parlement, while claiming to be entirely obedient to the king, asserted that there were moral boundaries to their obedience.[75] This idea also had popular appeal, as it claimed to represent the nation or the people in the absence of the States-General. The remonstrance from the cour des aides, likely drafted by Malesherbes, in February 1771, highlights these popular claims. “Today, the courts are the only defenders of the weak and unfortunate: the States-General have long ceased to exist, and in most of the kingdom, there are no provincial estates; all entities, aside from the courts, have been reduced to silent and passive obedience. No individual in the provinces would dare to expose himself to the wrath of a commandant, a commissaire du conseil, and even less to those of a minister of Your Majesty. Thus, the courts are the only ones still permitted to speak up for the people, and Your Majesty does not wish to take away this last resort from distant provinces. However, this decree exiling the Parlement of Paris aims to make this resource pointless.”[76]
Notwithstanding this avowed guardianship of the national rights, the feeling gradually grew that these ill-defined fundamental laws were too vague, that the Parlements, though persistent, stopped short of pertinacity, and that an aristocratic magistracy was not the real representation of the nation.
Notwithstanding this declared protection of national rights, there was a growing sense that these poorly defined fundamental laws were too vague, that the Parlements, although determined, lacked true persistence, and that an aristocratic judiciary did not truly represent the nation.
The first expression, so far as I have noted, of the need of a more definite political rampart against the crown was that of the Marquis de Mirabeau and his brother. In 1754, the Marquis wrote to his brother: “The more I consider the abuses of society and their remedy, the more I return to what you said to me five years ago, ... that twelve principles established in twelve lines, once written in the head of the Prince or of his minister, and exactly followed in details, would correct and regenerate[32] everything.”[77] But this was only a solitary voice crying in the wilderness; it neither found a response in the people, nor became the determined policy of its enunciator.
The first sign, as far as I can tell, of the need for a stronger political barrier against the crown came from the Marquis de Mirabeau and his brother. In 1754, the Marquis wrote to his brother: “The more I think about the problems in society and how to fix them, the more I go back to what you told me five years ago, ... that twelve principles laid out in twelve lines, once ingrained in the mind of the Prince or his minister, and accurately followed in detail, would correct and rejuvenate[32] everything.”[77] But this was just a single voice crying out in the wilderness; it didn’t resonate with the people, nor did it become a clear policy for its speaker.
The people, however, were awakening at least to the abuses of the ancien régime, and were groping after a remedy. Books, dealing with the right of insurrection, of the superiority of the nation to the crown, and with the refutation of divine rights and passive obedience, were written, read and discussed.[78] Humanitarian views, the theory of natural rights, and, consequently, a sense of the importance of the third estate, gained ground by degrees. Meanwhile the contest between the king and his Parlements continued. The Notables, called in 1787, affirmed that the imprescriptible right to determine financial questions belonged only to the representatives of the nation.[79] The States-General were called for 1789,[80] Owing to the failure of the monarch or minister, purposely or otherwise, to take the initiative, the radical element of the nation were able to secure almost universal suffrage and the union of the orders in one body. Judging from the cahier and the pamphlets of 1788 and 1789, we infer that the consciousness of the inadequacy of the old French Constitution was general.[81] The cahiers, upon the question of the French Constitution, were moreover divided; some desired the preservation of the old Constitution, some a declaration of the rights of the nation, some a charte, while one formulated a new, complete constitution; on the whole, a majority favored a more careful guarantee of the nation’s[33] rights.[82] The cahiers, it must be remarked, show a more perfect and uniform programme of civil reform than of political.
The people, however, were starting to wake up to the abuses of the ancien régime and were searching for a solution. Books discussing the right to revolt, the supremacy of the nation over the crown, and challenging divine rights and passive obedience were being written, read, and debated. Humanitarian ideas, the theory of natural rights, and an increasing awareness of the importance of the third estate gradually gained traction. Meanwhile, the conflict between the king and his Parlements continued. The Notables, convened in 1787, stated that the essential right to decide financial matters belonged only to the nation's representatives. The States-General were called for 1789, and due to the failure of the monarch or minister, whether intentional or not, to take action, the radical factions of the nation managed to achieve almost universal suffrage and the unification of the orders into one body. From the cahier and the pamphlets of 1788 and 1789, it is clear that there was a widespread recognition of the inadequacy of the old French Constitution. The cahiers regarding the French Constitution were also divided; some wanted to keep the old Constitution, some sought a declaration of the nation’s rights, some called for a charte, while one proposed a new, complete constitution; overall, most favored stronger protections for the nation’s[33] rights. It should be noted that the cahiers present a more coherent and uniform agenda for civil reform than for political change.
The pamphlets of the day, being the expression of the convictions of individuals, reveal more clearly the political thought of the radical element. Count de Mirabeau’s Lettres de cachet, published in 1783, may be regarded as among the earliest of such personal expressions. Its attitude was rather negative than constructive. It attempted to show that a despotism depended not at all upon the character of the particular sovereign, but on the absence or insufficiency of laws; that France without a veritable constitution was only a despotic state, and that there is no mean between an absolute despotism and the absolute reign of law.[83] In 1787, the Count declared, “What is necessary is a constitution; France is ripe for the Revolution.”[84]
The pamphlets of the time, reflecting individual beliefs, more clearly reveal the political ideas of the radical group. Count de Mirabeau’s Lettres de cachet, published in 1783, can be seen as one of the earliest of these personal expressions. Its approach was more negative than constructive. It tried to show that despotism didn't depend on the nature of the particular ruler but rather on a lack or inadequacy of laws; that France, without a real constitution, was just a despotic state, and that there is no middle ground between absolute despotism and the complete rule of law.[83] In 1787, the Count stated, “What is necessary is a constitution; France is ready for the Revolution.”[84]
Other pamphlets of 1788 and 1789 indicate a tendency to discuss constitutional law from the historical and crudely comparative standpoint, and to apply the conclusions to the present conditions, but in the attempt to formulate their results, they are less clear and coherent. One of these drawn up in 1789 devotes one hundred and thirty-seven pages to the discussion of the influence of Montesquieu in the present Revolution, and denounces him for not declaring boldly that France was a despotism. It concluded that France has in reality no constitution.[85]
Other pamphlets from 1788 and 1789 show a trend of discussing constitutional law from a historical and somewhat comparative angle, applying those insights to the current situation. However, in trying to clearly present their findings, they come off as less organized and coherent. One pamphlet created in 1789 spends one hundred thirty-seven pages discussing Montesquieu's influence on the ongoing Revolution, criticizing him for not clearly stating that France was a despotism. It concluded that France essentially has no real constitution.[85]
How far the king meant that the States-General should possess a constitutional character is difficult to determine. The Letter of Summons repeatedly asserts the desire to affect a “fixed and constant order in all parts of the administration.”[86] Mirabeau claimed that the king himself had recognized “the necessity of giving[35] France a fixed method of government,”[87] and La Marck confirmed this declaration.[88] We shall perhaps have attributed sufficient meaning to these hazy avowals if we say that Louis XVI., partly from his paternal spirit, and partly from a desire for relief from financial crises, meditated, in his more liberal moods, granting the nation some sort of a charter, in the formulation of which he wished the assistance of the States-General. This resuscitated institution convened at Versailles, May 5, 1789.
How far the king intended for the States-General to have a constitutional role is hard to figure out. The Letter of Summons repeatedly expresses a desire to establish a “fixed and constant order in all parts of the administration.”[86] Mirabeau argued that the king himself had acknowledged “the necessity of giving[35] France a fixed method of government,”[87] and La Marck supported this claim.[88] We might have attributed enough significance to these vague statements if we conclude that Louis XVI., partly out of fatherly concern and partly out of a need to ease financial crises, considered, during his more liberal moments, granting the nation some form of a charter, for which he wanted the States-General’s help. This revived institution met at Versailles on May 5, 1789.
The first months were occupied in the disputes over the verification of the powers of the deputies. On May 28, a representative of the nobility, Count de Crillon, said that “he was of the firm opinion that it was less for maintaining than for establishing the Constitution that they were called together.”[89] On June 15, Abbé Siéyès announced that those whose powers had been verified represented ninety-six per cent. of the nation, and suggested as a fitting name, “Assemblée des représentants.” Mirabeau, at the same session, offered a series of resolutions that provoked much discussion, one of which affirmed that their first duty was “to agree upon and to fix legally the principles for the regeneration of the kingdom, to assure the rights of the people, to adopt the basis of a wise and useful constitution, and, to secure these rights from all attempts, they shall be put under the safeguard of the legislative power of the king and of the National Assembly.” Rabaud de Saint Étienne, in another series of resolutions, expressed the same conviction.[90] Two days later, the name “National Assembly” was adopted and an oath taken “to fulfill with zeal and fidelity the duties which devolve upon us.”[91] Debarred from the place usually occupied by the Assembly by the carpenters who were at work upon it, the members of the third estate held their meeting,[36] June 20, in the Tennis Court at Versailles, and there adopted the resolution which declared the National Assembly a Constitutional Convention, and subscribed to the following, known as the Tennis Court Oath: “The National Assembly, regarding itself as called upon to establish the Constitution of the kingdom, effect a regeneration of the state and maintain the true principles of the monarchy, may not be prevented from continuing its deliberations in whatever place it may be forced to take up its sittings. It further maintains that wherever its members are assembled, there is the National Assembly. The Assembly decrees that all its members shall immediately take a solemn oath never to be dissolved and to come together whenever circumstances may dictate, until the Constitution of the kingdom shall be established and placed upon a firm foundation.”[92] It is beyond the sphere of our inquiry to follow this Constituent Assembly in their arduous and complex task of formulating a constitution, and of legislating at the same time for the kingdom, while exposed to court intrigues and popular intrusion.
The first few months were spent arguing over the verification of the deputies' powers. On May 28, Count de Crillon, a representative of the nobility, stated that “he firmly believed they were called together more to establish than to maintain the Constitution.”[89] On June 15, Abbé Siéyès announced that those with verified powers represented ninety-six percent of the nation and suggested the fitting name “Assemblée des représentants.” Mirabeau, in the same session, proposed several resolutions that sparked much debate, one of which asserted that their primary duty was “to agree on and legally establish the principles for regenerating the kingdom, ensuring the rights of the people, adopting a solid and beneficial constitution, and securing these rights from all threats by placing them under the protection of the legislative power of the king and the National Assembly.” Rabaud de Saint Étienne, in another series of resolutions, voiced the same view.[90] Two days later, the name “National Assembly” was officially adopted, and an oath was taken “to carry out our duties with enthusiasm and loyalty.”[91] Blocked from their usual meeting place by carpenters working on it, the members of the third estate held their meeting,[36] on June 20, in the Tennis Court at Versailles. There, they passed the resolution declaring the National Assembly a Constitutional Convention and pledged the following, known as the Tennis Court Oath: “The National Assembly, seeing itself tasked with establishing the Constitution of the kingdom, revitalizing the state, and upholding the genuine principles of the monarchy, cannot be blocked from continuing its discussions no matter where it has to meet. It also asserts that wherever its members gather, that is the National Assembly. The Assembly dictates that all its members shall immediately take a solemn oath never to disband and to reconvene whenever necessary until the Constitution of the kingdom is established and firmly grounded.”[92] It is beyond the scope of our inquiry to follow this Constituent Assembly in their challenging and complex task of formulating a constitution while simultaneously legislating for the kingdom amid court intrigues and public interference.
Therefore, to conclude this chapter as we began, we have shown that the resolution of June 20 was neither a political freak, nor an act of imitation of a foreign nation. The example of the American Republic may have given stimulus and precision, yet the Tennis Court Oath must be regarded as the logical consequence of a transformation, which had been in progress for more than sixty years.
Therefore, to wrap up this chapter as we started, we have demonstrated that the resolution of June 20 was neither an odd political event nor an act of copying a foreign nation. While the example of the American Republic may have provided inspiration and clarity, the Tennis Court Oath should be seen as the logical result of a change that had been underway for more than sixty years.
Louis XVI., in 1789, was praised by the mass of the French nation as the best of monarchs, and as the restorer of national liberties; his name was coupled with that of Henry IV., a king about whom tradition had thrown a halo of glory. But, on September 21, 1792, the newly-chosen Convention abolished the monarchy. So rapid is the transition from the one phase of the national feeling to the other, that it occasions a surmise either that the professed loyalty to the monarch in 1789 was not sincere, or that the action of the Convention was the work of a coterie of radicals, who misrepresented the popular feeling. A review of the period intervening between 1789 and 1792 shows that both of these suppositions are unwarranted, and confirms the conclusion that there was a progressive development of hostility, first to Louis XVI. and the royal family, and then to the monarchical government.
Louis XVI, in 1789, was celebrated by the majority of the French population as the best of kings and the restorer of national freedoms; his name was mentioned alongside that of Henry IV, a king who had become legendary over time. However, on September 21, 1792, the newly elected Convention abolished the monarchy. The shift in national sentiment from one phase to another happened so quickly that it raises questions about whether the loyalty expressed toward the king in 1789 was genuine, or if the Convention's actions were driven by a small group of radicals who distorted the public's feelings. A look at the period between 1789 and 1792 shows that both of these ideas are unfounded and reinforces the conclusion that there was a gradual increase in hostility first toward Louis XVI and the royal family, and then toward the monarchical government.
Previous to 1789, the term Republic is used by French publicists or agitators, but it is either in a sense so qualified as to be consistent with the monarchy, or as a form of government unsuited to France with its actual traditions and conditions.[93] The very nearly unanimous feeling and judgment in 1789 was that the monarchy was the best form of government for France, and that the chief need was to regenerate it. We have said that one hundred and[38] ninety-four cahiers specifically asked for the retention of the monarchy; the silence of the others upon this question must not be construed to mean that their authors were indifferent or opposed to the monarchy, but rather that they believed it unnecessary to ask for what they already had, and against which there was no strong movement. As Paris may rightly be considered the source of the anti-monarchical agitation, the attitude of the third estate in this city at the opening of the Revolution may justly be taken to represent the feeling of the radical element toward the monarchy. In their cahier they said: “In the French monarchy, the legislative power belongs to the nation conjointly with the king; to the king alone belongs the executive power.”[94] The sub-cahiers from the districts of the city expressed the same idea.[95] In truth, in not a single cahier examined do we find a hint of any opposition to the monarchy. Hence, it is to be inferred that, if any individuals had Republican inclinations, these inclinations were not shared by any appreciable part of the nation. A few men of the reform party, Lauragnais, Lally-Tollendal, and Montlosier, ventured to say that the French monarchy had originally been elective and that the elective monarchy would consequently be not an innovation,[39] but a restoration of their early system;[96] but the adherence of these men to the monarchy in the early days of the Constituent Assembly is conclusive that by the elective monarchy they did not mean the Republic of 1792.
Before 1789, French publicists or activists used the term Republic, but it was either in a way that fit with the monarchy or as a type of government that didn’t match France's actual traditions and conditions.[93] The nearly unanimous sentiment in 1789 was that the monarchy was the best system of government for France, and the main need was to reform it. We noted that one hundred and[38] ninety-four cahiers explicitly requested the monarchy to be maintained; the silence of the others on this topic shouldn’t be interpreted as indifference or opposition to the monarchy, but rather as a belief that it was unnecessary to ask for something they already had, and against which there was no significant movement. Since Paris can be seen as the birthplace of anti-monarchical activism, the position of the third estate in this city at the start of the Revolution can fairly represent the radical element's views toward the monarchy. In their cahier, they stated: “In the French monarchy, the legislative power belongs to the nation together with the king; the executive power solely belongs to the king.”[94] The sub-cahiers from the city’s districts reflected the same sentiment.[95] In fact, in not a single cahier reviewed do we find any suggestion of opposition to the monarchy. Therefore, it can be inferred that if any individuals had Republican leanings, those sentiments were not shared by a significant part of the nation. A few members of the reform party, Lauragnais, Lally-Tollendal, and Montlosier, dared to claim that the French monarchy was originally elective and that an elective monarchy would thus not be a new idea, but a restoration of their early system;[96] however, their commitment to the monarchy in the early days of the Constituent Assembly confirms that by an elective monarchy they did not mean the Republic of 1792.
The Constituent Assembly, having been formed out of the States General, had to formulate a constitution for the regeneration of France, and was obliged, therefore, to specify the divisions of government, designate the organs and the functions of each division, prescribe their powers, limitations, sources and transmission; hence the debates and decrees of this national body may be taken as indicative of the public sentiment toward the monarch. Here may be traced the changes worked in the public mind, the censure or the eulogy of persons and institutions. As this national assembly itself became transformed by the withdrawal of the more conservative elements, it reflected rather faithfully the change that was taking place in the minds of the radical classes of France.
The Constituent Assembly, created from the States General, had to draft a constitution to renew France and was therefore required to outline the divisions of government, name the various branches and their roles, define their powers, limits, sources, and how they interact; thus, the discussions and decisions of this national body can be seen as a reflection of public opinion regarding the monarchy. Here, we can observe the shifts in public perception, whether it be criticism or praise of individuals and institutions. As this national assembly evolved with the departure of more conservative members, it accurately mirrored the transformation occurring in the views of France's radical groups.
This Assembly frequently gave expression of its satisfaction with the monarch and with the monarchy. Near the close of the famous session of August 4, 1789, when feudalism had been so enthusiastically renounced by its own favored sons, M. Lally-Tollendal proposed that they should proclaim “Louis XVI. the Restorer of French liberty.” “The proclamation,” we are told, “was made immediately by the deputies, by the people, and by all those who were present, and the National Assembly resounded for a quarter of an hour with the cries ‘Vive le roi; vive Louis XVI., restaurateur de la liberté française.’”[97] As early as July 4, 1789, Gouverneur Morris, a careful observer of the French spirit and movements, wrote: “They wish an American Constitution, with a king in the place of a president.”[98] On August 28, 1789, Mounier presented a project of the monarchical element of the Constitution, and a member made the following statement, the verity of which was not disputed: “Here we should reflect upon the national spirit. For fourteen centuries the French, free to direct themselves by the republican spirit, preferred the peacefulness of the monarchic government to the storms of a republican government.... Louis XVI. is no more upon the throne by the[40] chance of birth, he is there by the choice of the nation; it has raised him there, as formerly our brave ancestors raised Pharamond upon the shield. No one contests the monarchical government. All the cahiers are certainly clear ... we cannot avoid the conclusion, the only government which is suitable to our manners (moeurs), to our climate, to the extent of our provinces, is the monarchical government.”[99] Other speeches made on the same occasion are indicative of the strong monarchical spirit that possessed the Assembly at this stage of its history.
This Assembly often expressed its satisfaction with the king and the monarchy. Near the end of the famous session on August 4, 1789, when feudalism was enthusiastically rejected by its own supporters, M. Lally-Tollendal suggested they should proclaim "Louis XVI. the Restorer of French liberty." "The proclamation," we're told, "was made immediately by the deputies, by the people, and by all those present, and the National Assembly echoed for fifteen minutes with the shouts ‘Vive le roi; vive Louis XVI., restaurateur de la liberté française.’”[97] As early as July 4, 1789, Gouverneur Morris, a keen observer of the French mindset and events, wrote: “They want an American Constitution, with a king instead of a president.”[98] On August 28, 1789, Mounier presented a project for the monarchical part of the Constitution, and a member made the following statement, which was not disputed: “Here we should consider the national spirit. For fourteen centuries, the French, able to guide themselves by a republican spirit, preferred the stability of a monarchy over the upheaval of a republic.... Louis XVI. is not on the throne by chance of birth; he is there by the choice of the nation; it has elevated him there, just as our brave ancestors once lifted Pharamond upon a shield. No one contests the monarchy. All the cahiers are certainly clear... we cannot avoid the conclusion that the only government suited to our customs, our climate, and the extent of our provinces is a monarchical government.”[99] Other speeches made on the same occasion reflect the strong monarchical sentiment that filled the Assembly at this point in its history.
Twenty days later, M. de Baron de Juigne proposed to consecrate the principles of the heredity of the crown and the inviolability of the king’s person. Scarcely were these principles announced, than the Assembly proclaimed them by an unanimous movement.[100] These principles were embodied in the decree of September 17, 1789.[101]
From these citations, we are warranted in the inference that the members of the Constituent Assembly in its earlier period regarded the monarchy as the natural and the most suitable form of government for France. On the question of the division of powers, the number of chambers, the elective or hereditary kingship, the absolute or limited veto, there were differences of opinion; but national tradition and personal attachment to Louis XVI. were of sufficient force to bar any discussion of other possible forms for the executive branch.
From these citations, we can conclude that the members of the Constituent Assembly in its early days believed that monarchy was the natural and best form of government for France. There were differing opinions on the division of powers, the number of chambers, whether kingship should be elective or hereditary, and the nature of the veto—whether it should be absolute or limited. However, national tradition and personal loyalty to Louis XVI. were strong enough to prevent any discussion of alternative forms for the executive branch.
The first strong manifestation of personal displeasure toward the king reflected in the Assembly, was aroused by his attempt to escape from the country with the royal family, on June 20 and 21, 1791. Fearing to be held longer as a hostage by the revolutionary party and to be supplanted by the invading émigrés, the king with his family sought to reach the eastern frontier and there to be free to act independently of both factions; but at Varennes he was arrested and brought back to face the enraged Parisians. It is then that words of displeasure were first heard in the Assembly. What shall be done with the royal fugitive? was then the living question. Some contended that he was inviolable and could not be called to account; others, that his inviolability extended only to public actions, not to private; while still others[41] maintained that he had, by his treason, forfeited his inviolability. The agitation which reigned without found some expression within the Assembly. A committee reported, July 13, that the flight of the king was not a constitutional offense, that the principle of inviolability did not permit Louis XVI. to be put on trial. For three days the discussion over the king’s inviolability was carried on. Pétion, Putraink, Vadier, Robespierre, Prieur, Grégoire, Buzot spoke against, and Larochefoucault, Liancourt, Prugnon, Duport, Goupil de Prefeln, Salles and Barnave for the inviolability. Only Condorcet attempted to show the fitness of France for a Republic.[102] The people were astir without; they met on the squares, in the public places, crowded around the Assembly, and urged the dethronement of the king or the reference of the question to the people of the eighty-three departments. Petitions, posters, and ardent declamations were instruments by which the radicals sought to turn public opinion their way.[103] On July 16, 1791, a decree of the Assembly defined the acts whereby the king should be considered as no longer inviolable. Should he, having taken the oath to the Constitution, violate it: or should he put himself at the head of an army against the nation, or should he fail to oppose such an act on the part of his generals, he should be considered to have abdicated, and might be brought to trial like any ordinary citizen. His executive functions, suspended June 25, were not to be restored till the completion of the Constitution.[104]
The first strong expression of personal dissatisfaction with the king in the Assembly came from his attempt to flee the country with the royal family on June 20 and 21, 1791. Fearing that he would be held as a hostage by the revolutionary faction and replaced by the invading émigrés, the king and his family tried to reach the eastern border to act independently of both sides. However, they were arrested in Varennes and taken back to face the angry Parisians. It was at this point that expressions of discontent were first voiced in the Assembly. The pressing question became: what should be done with the royal fugitive? Some argued that he was inviolable and could not be held accountable; others claimed his inviolability applied only to public actions, not private ones; while still others maintained that he had forfeited his inviolability through his treason. The unrest outside found some reflection within the Assembly. A committee reported on July 13 that the king’s flight was not a constitutional offense and that the principle of inviolability meant Louis XVI. could not be put on trial. The debate over the king’s inviolability went on for three days. Pétion, Putraink, Vadier, Robespierre, Prieur, Grégoire, and Buzot spoke against it, while Larochefoucault, Liancourt, Prugnon, Duport, Goupil de Prefeln, Salles, and Barnave spoke in favor. Only Condorcet tried to argue for France's readiness for a Republic. The people were agitated outside; they gathered in squares and public places, crowding around the Assembly, demanding the king's dethronement or that the issue be referred to the citizens of the eighty-three departments. Petitions, posters, and passionate speeches were tools the radicals used to sway public opinion. On July 16, 1791, the Assembly passed a decree outlining the circumstances under which the king would no longer be considered inviolable. If he violated the Constitution after taking the oath, if he led an army against the nation, or if he failed to oppose such actions by his generals, he would be seen as having abdicated and could be tried like any ordinary citizen. His executive powers, suspended on June 25, would not be restored until the Constitution was completed.
The Constitution was completed and reviewed, and on September 14, 1791, the king went to the Constituent Assembly, accepted the Constitution, and, amid prolonged applause, subscribed to this new instrument that was to give liberty to France. He was escorted back to the Tuileries by the entire Assembly. The flight of the monarch seemed forgotten or forgiven.[105]
The Constitution was finished and reviewed, and on September 14, 1791, the king went to the Constituent Assembly, accepted the Constitution, and, amid long applause, signed this new document that was meant to bring freedom to France. He was escorted back to the Tuileries by the whole Assembly. The king's earlier flight seemed forgotten or forgiven. [105]
On September 30th, the monarch made the closing speech to the Assembly and was greeted with repeated shouts of Vive le Roi. The President responded to the royal speech by an eulogy upon the monarch and a compliment upon the form of government inaugurated[42] under the Constitution.[106] Though the Constituent Assembly had not laid sacrilegious hands upon the time-honored monarchy of France further than to divest it of some of its privileges and prerogatives, though the storm of displeasure, incurred by the ill-advised flight of June 20th, had apparently subsided and the Assembly and the king had exchanged expressions of mutual esteem, and had sworn to preserve the great document so laboriously wrought out by the French Lycurguses, yet the leaven had been engendered which, under favorable circumstances, would leaven the whole lump and transform the limited monarchy into a republic. Ideas have their origin in individual minds, are advocated by these individuals, and by and by the nucleus of devotees has grown into a party that serves as an organ of propagation and makes use of the instrumentalities of their age for the dissemination of their views and for the moulding of public opinion into conformity thereto. If the conditions are favorable, the new ideas secure acceptance and are embodied in institutions; but if the conditions are hostile, the conceptions are rejected and relegated to that vast repository where are accumulated the world’s Utopias; thence some ardent soul may bring forward the idea at a time which is propitious, and the Utopia may become a practical reality. It is our task to endeavor to discover the notion of a republic for France as it was conceived and promulgated by those individuals who may be called the precursors of French republicanism, to trace the formation of an organic body for its promulgation, and to find the means used in the formation of a public opinion sufficiently strong to secure the adoption of the Republic of 1792.
On September 30th, the king gave his closing speech to the Assembly and was met with loud cheers of Vive le Roi. The President responded to the royal speech with praise for the king and expressed approval of the new government established[42] under the Constitution. Even though the Constituent Assembly had not seriously challenged the long-standing monarchy of France beyond taking away some privileges and powers, and despite the earlier dissatisfaction following the ill-fated escape on June 20th seemingly calming down, the Assembly and the king had exchanged words of mutual respect and promised to uphold the important document painstakingly created by the French Lycurguses. However, the seeds of change were planted that, under the right circumstances, could potentially evolve the limited monarchy into a republic. Ideas start in individual minds, are promoted by those people, and eventually, a core group of supporters can grow into a party that acts as a platform for spreading those ideas and shaping public opinion accordingly. When conditions are right, new ideas gain traction and become part of established institutions; but if the conditions are unfavorable, these ideas are dismissed and stored away with the world’s Utopias. Then, an enthusiastic individual might revive the idea at a more favorable time, making the Utopia a practical reality. Our goal is to explore the concept of a republic for France as envisioned and shared by those who could be seen as the forerunners of French republicanism, to examine how an organized body was formed to promote it, and to identify the methods used to create a strong public opinion capable of ensuring the success of the Republic of 1792.
There were already in 1789 a few ardent natures enthusiastic over the transformation to be wrought in France, who harbored a vague desire to see the monarchy abolished and a more liberal government instituted. Whence had come this hazy notion which wrought up their feelings may only be conjectured. Perhaps the[43] classic studies upon which the Jesuits and Oratorians nourished their pupils had made them familiar with the Greek and Roman Republics.[107] Either the Social Contract, or the example of the American colonies, may have given them their republican notions.
There were already, in 1789, a few passionate individuals excited about the changes happening in France, who had a vague desire to see the monarchy ended and a more liberal government established. The origin of this unclear idea that stirred their emotions can only be guessed at. Perhaps the classic studies that the Jesuits and Oratorians provided their students made them aware of the Greek and Roman Republics. Either the Social Contract or the example of the American colonies might have inspired their republican ideas.[43]
Camille Desmoulins, an ardent, impetuous son of liberty, gave unequivocal expression of republican sentiments as early as 1789, and even asserted that the republican form of government was best suited for France.[108] In May, 1793, in two addresses, made in answer to Brissot, he confirms his early preference for republicanism. He said: “In the month of July, 1789, the number of Republicans in Paris did not probably exceed ten: and this it is which crowns with eternal glory those old members of the Club of Cordeliers, who began building the edifice of the republic with such slight materials.”[109] In June, 1790, he used the term Congress of the Republic of France in speaking of the Constituent Assembly, and said that only four republicans had had the courage to resist the royal budget of 25,000,000 voted upon in the Assembly. Again in the Jacobin Club, October 21, 1791, at the time when France was big with hope that the new Constitution would work, Desmoulins pointed out its imperfections and favored republican institutions. Here then was one mind already thinking of a republic[44] and claiming that in the Cordelier Club there were others who, at that early period, shared his opinions. Who these were he does not say.[110] The district of the city called the Cordeliers had formed a popular society which manifested a severely critical spirit toward the monarchical and aristocratic legislation. This district clamored for liberty of the press,[111] and championed the political rights of passive citizens.[112] It took the side of the sixty districts which kept up their popular electoral assemblies and which continued to meet in the interim of elections, as against the forty-eight sections, which convened only for elections. The ardent opposition of the Cordeliers to the Assembly and to the municipality doubtless provoked the enactment of the law which, on May 27, 1790, transformed these districts into the sections.[113] Then forming the Club of Cordeliers, the Society of the Rights of Man and of Citizens, this district continued its policy of aggression upon the conservatives, until their more democratic programme became an accomplished fact. Here then was a company of men, having a common interest in extreme radicalism, meeting frequently and fanning into fuller heat by their addresses the embers of opposition. This society, anti-aristocratic, anti-monarchical, occasionally uttered republican sentiments and indulged in the word republic. They remarked the inconsistency between the principles contained in the Declaration of the Rights of Man and an hereditary monarchy, resting upon the divine right of[45] kings.[114] On June 22, 1791, the Club of Cordeliers issued an address to the Assembly showing its republican proclivities, much to the displeasure of the Jacobins. They said: “We conjure you, in the name of the country, either to declare immediately that France is no more a monarchy, that it is a republic, or at least to wait until all the departments, until all the primary assemblies, have expressed their wish upon this important question, before thinking of replacing a second time the most fair Empire of the world in chains and in the limits of monarchism.”[115] The flight of the king was the occasion that called for this expression of animosity to the monarchy and the preference for a republic. Even before the attempted escape, another newspaper had joined with Desmoulins in his strong anti-monarchical views and in the suggestion of a more suitable form of government for France. Prudhomme, the publisher of booklets and pamphlets of the liberal party previous to, and during the Revolution, had established a paper devoted to the new ideas, the Révolutions de Paris. The experienced publisher had discovered the practical sagacity and the sincere democratic proclivities of a young advocate from Bourdeaux, recently come to Paris, Loustallot, who had already in 1789 proved himself a good pamphleteer for the reformers. These two men began the issue of their sheet July 12, 1789. In its earlier numbers the slavery of the Frenchmen to the aristocracy was bitterly censured, but the king is not treated so much with hostility as with pity for his weakness.[116] Whether Loustallot would have[46] continued to advocate liberal monarchical views had he lived,[117] we shall not venture to say; but in the spring of 1791,[118] the paper had changed its spirit toward the king. The issue of April 21-30 gave notice of a decree proposed to the National Assembly advocating the abolition of royalty. After citing a long list of considerations, chiefly of the evils of kings and of the inconsistency of such an institution with the rights of man, twenty-one articles were given proposing the abolition of royalty and the substitution of a President.[119] Subsequent numbers continued to discuss favorably the abolition of the monarchy. In No. 91 a letter was printed which suggested the placing of a ballot-box in each of the churches to receive the vote of the people upon the question at issue. The writer shows himself friendly to the change. Another friend of the proposal, in a letter printed in No. 92[120], opposed this mode of voting, lest the monarchists should take advantage of it. Instead, he proposed that the vote should be collected viva voce, a list made of those voting; this list should be sent to the Assembly, yet care should be taken to keep a duplicate in order to avoid any surprise. No. 96 contained an article upon “The White Elephant,” advocating, in a facetious manner, similar ideas. The same number entered into an examination of these three propositions, the first two of which it decided affirmatively, the last one[47] negatively. I. Whether the elements and the principles of our Constitution are not in continual opposition to the form of our government. II. Whether every hereditary delegation is not a violation of rights and a contradiction in principles. III. Whether the illustrious citizen of Geneva is mistaken when he says that the monarchy is a government contrary to nature.
Camille Desmoulins, a passionate and impulsive advocate for liberty, openly expressed his republican beliefs as early as 1789, claiming that a republican government was the best fit for France.[108] In May 1793, in two speeches responding to Brissot, he reaffirmed his early preference for republicanism. He stated: “In July 1789, the number of Republicans in Paris was probably no more than ten; and this is what gives eternal glory to those early members of the Club of Cordeliers, who started building the foundation of the republic with such limited resources.”[109] In June 1790, he referred to the Constituent Assembly as the Congress of the Republic of France, mentioning that only four republicans had the courage to oppose the royal budget of 25,000,000 approved by the Assembly. Again, at the Jacobin Club on October 21, 1791, during a hopeful time for France regarding the new Constitution, Desmoulins pointed out its flaws and supported republican institutions. Here was one person already envisioning a republic[44] and asserting that there were others in the Cordelier Club who shared his views at that early stage. He does not specify who they were.[110] The neighborhood known as the Cordeliers formed a popular society that was highly critical of monarchical and aristocratic laws. This area advocated for freedom of the press,[111] and supported the political rights of ordinary citizens.[112] It sided with the sixty districts that maintained their popular electoral assemblies and continued to meet between elections, in contrast to the forty-eight sections, which only convened for elections. The strong opposition of the Cordeliers to the Assembly and the municipality likely led to the legislation passed on May 27, 1790, that transformed these districts into sections.[113] Then forming the Club of Cordeliers, the Society of the Rights of Man and of Citizens, this neighborhood continued its aggressive stance against conservatives until their more democratic agenda became a reality. This was a group of men with a shared interest in extreme radicalism, frequently gathering to fan the flames of opposition through their speeches. This society, anti-aristocratic and anti-monarchical, sometimes expressed republican ideals and embraced the term republic. They noted the contradiction between the principles outlined in the Declaration of the Rights of Man and a hereditary monarchy, which rested on the divine right of[45] kings.[114] On June 22, 1791, the Club of Cordeliers issued a statement to the Assembly showcasing its republican tendencies, much to the annoyance of the Jacobins. They said: “We urge you, on behalf of the country, to either immediately declare that France is no longer a monarchy, that it is a republic, or at least to wait until all departments and primary assemblies have expressed their views on this crucial matter before thinking of chaining the fairest Empire in the world once again in the confines of monarchism.”[115] The king's flight was the catalyst for this expression of hostility towards the monarchy and preference for a republic. Even before the attempted escape, another newspaper had joined Desmoulins in his strong anti-monarchical stance and in suggesting a more appropriate form of government for France. Prudhomme, who published materials for the liberal party before and during the Revolution, had started a publication dedicated to new ideas, the Révolutions de Paris. The experienced publisher recognized the practical wisdom and genuine democratic inclinations of a young advocate from Bordeaux, Loustallot, who had recently arrived in Paris and had already proven himself a good pamphleteer for the reformers in 1789. These two men launched their publication on July 12, 1789. In its earlier issues, the subjugation of French citizens to the aristocracy was harshly criticized, although the king was portrayed more with pity for his weakness than hostility.[116] Whether Loustallot would have continued to support liberal monarchical views if he had lived,[117] we cannot say; however, by the spring of 1791,[118] the publication's tone had shifted towards the king. The issue from April 21-30 noted a proposal to the National Assembly advocating the abolition of royalty. After listing several reasons, primarily the problems with kings and the inconsistency of such an institution with the rights of man, twenty-one articles were put forth advocating the abolition of monarchy and the establishment of a President.[119] Subsequent issues continued to favor the abolition of the monarchy. In No. 91, a letter was printed suggesting placing a ballot box in each church to collect votes on the issue. The writer showed support for the change. Another supporter of the proposal, in a letter printed in No. 92[120], opposed this voting method, fearing monarchists could exploit it. Instead, he proposed that the vote should be recorded viva voce, a list made of those voting; this list should be sent to the Assembly, with a duplicate kept to avoid surprises. No. 96 included an article on "The White Elephant," humorously advocating similar ideas. The same issue also examined three propositions, deciding positively on the first two and negatively on the last. I. Whether the elements and principles of our Constitution are consistently opposed to the form of our government. II. Whether every hereditary delegation violates rights and contradicts principles. III. Whether the distinguished citizen of Geneva is mistaken when he claims that monarchy is a government against nature.
But the most venomous assault upon the king and upon royalty appeared in the number of June 18-25, which reported the king’s flight. Denunciatory epithets were heaped upon the faithless monarch. “Julius Cæsar, poigniarded by the Romans; Charles I., decapitated by the English, were innocent, if we compare them to Louis XVI.... If the President of the National Assembly had put to vote upon the question whether we should have a republican form of government, in the Place de Grève, in the Garden of Tuileries and in the Palace of Orléans, France would no more be a monarchy.” Such were some of the contents of this liberal Parisian paper.[121] The next issue (No. 103) found fault with the National Assembly for not dealing severely with the king, and said that, inasmuch as war would come anyway, it had better come under a republic than under a monarch or[48] a regent. Here also appeared an announcement of the propagandism of liberty, of which the Girondists spoke so enthusiastically a year later.[122] A few numbers later, an article censured the indifference of the people in regard to the elections for the coming Legislative Assembly, saying that upon the composition of this body would depend the safety of the republic. The Constituent Assembly is not spared criticism for making the Constitution unalterable by the Legislative Assembly.[123] In subsequent numbers of the autumn of 1791, the monarchical features of the Constitution were pointed out and criticised.[124] Later on, the republic was mentioned less frequently, nevertheless royalty was still attacked. The issue which gave an account of the events of August 10, 1792, the determination of the Legislative Assembly to suspend the king and to call a National Convention to determine the nature of the executive office, referred to the king as “Louis XVI., whom we shall call no more the king of the French.” The number following advised the members of the convention that their first work should be to dethrone the monarch, but a republic was not explicitly recommended.[125] That this paper exercised[49] considerable influence in arousing hostility to the king and to the monarchy, and in suggesting a republic, seems quite reasonable, when we remember that its weekly circulation reached nearly two hundred thousand copies.[126]
But the most aggressive attack on the king and royalty appeared in the issue from June 18-25, which reported the king’s escape. Insults were thrown at the unfaithful monarch. “Julius Caesar, stabbed by the Romans; Charles I, executed by the English, were innocent compared to Louis XVI.... If the President of the National Assembly had put to a vote whether we should have a republican form of government, in the Place de Grève, in the Garden of Tuileries, and in the Palace of Orléans, France would no longer be a monarchy.” These were some of the contents of this progressive Parisian paper.[121] The next issue (No. 103) criticized the National Assembly for not being tough enough on the king, stating that since war was inevitable, it would be better to face it under a republic than under a monarch or[48] a regent. This issue also included an announcement about the promotion of liberty, which the Girondists would enthusiastically discuss a year later.[122] A few issues later, an article condemned the public's apathy regarding the elections for the upcoming Legislative Assembly, arguing that the composition of this body would determine the safety of the republic. The Constituent Assembly also faced criticism for making the Constitution unchangeable by the Legislative Assembly.[123] In later issues from the autumn of 1791, the monarchical aspects of the Constitution were highlighted and criticized.[124] Eventually, mentions of the republic decreased, but attacks on royalty continued. The issue covering the events of August 10, 1792, indicated the Legislative Assembly's decision to suspend the king and call a National Convention to define the executive position, referring to the king as “Louis XVI., whom we shall no longer call the king of the French.” The following issue urged the members of the convention that their first action should be to dethrone the monarch, though a republic wasn’t explicitly recommended.[125] It seems reasonable to conclude that this paper played a significant role in inciting hostility toward the king and the monarchy while promoting the idea of a republic, especially considering its weekly circulation reached nearly two hundred thousand copies.[126]
We have deemed it advisable to follow the Révolutions de Paris through to the proclamation of the republic, in order to give a connected account of the direction in which this popular publication attempted to sway public opinion. Having noted that its positive republicanism was manifest in April, two months before Louis XVI’s unsuccessful attempt at exodus, we shall endeavor to see what was the strength which this party possessed in the summer of 1791.
We decided it would be wise to track the Révolutions de Paris up to the announcement of the republic, so we can provide a clear account of how this popular publication tried to influence public opinion. We've observed that its strong support for republicanism was evident in April, two months before Louis XVI’s failed escape attempt, and we will explore the strength this party had in the summer of 1791.
Bonneville’s paper, Bouche de fer, in June, 1791, pronounced against a monarchy, a protectorate, and a regency, and urged an united declaration to the effect that they wanted no more of these.[127] A placard was posted at the door of the Assembly, July 1st, announcing that a society of republicans had resolved to publish a paper, Le Republican, for pointing out the abuses of monarchy and for enlightening the minds of the people upon republicanism. This was signed by Duchastellet.[128] A few copies of this paper were published within this month.[129] Montlosier mentions the existence of a republican party after the flight of the king,[130] and Gouverneur Morris wrote, July 13, 1791, what confirms the same fact. Here is what he said: “This step was a very foolish one.... His departure changed everything, and now the general wish seems to be for a republic, which is quite in the natural order of things.”[131][50] On the eve of the convening of the Legislative Assembly, September 30, 1791, Morris wrote to Washington the following explicit observations upon the status of the republican movement: “The new Assembly, as far as can at present be determined, is deeply imbued with republican or, rather, democratic principles. The southern part of the kingdom is in the same disposition; the eastern is attached to Germany and would gladly be united to the empire; Normandy is aristocratical, and so is part of Brittany; the interior part of the kingdom is monarchal. This map is (you may rely on it) just, for it is the result of great and expensive investigation made by the Government.”[132] Brissot’s paper, Patriote français, of June 25, 1791, in analyzing the proposals then made for the executive department of the government, said: “The first opinion which has been presented to the public is decisive,—No more kings, let us be republicans,—such has been the cry of the Palais Royal, of some societies, of some writers.”[133] Thomas Paine’s letter in response to Siéyès, published in the Patriote français, July 11, declares the American system of government superior to every other, and closes the letter with these suggestive words: “Enfin c’est à tout l’enfer de la monarchie que j’ai déclaré la guerre.”[134]
Bonneville’s paper, Bouche de fer, in June 1791, spoke out against monarchy, protectorates, and regencies, calling for a united declaration that they no longer wanted any of these. [127] On July 1st, a notice was posted at the door of the Assembly, announcing that a society of republicans had decided to publish a paper, Le Republican, to highlight the abuses of monarchy and educate the public about republicanism. This was signed by Duchastellet.[128] A few copies of this paper were published during that month.[129] Montlosier noted the presence of a republican party after the king's escape,[130] and Gouverneur Morris wrote on July 13, 1791, confirming the same point. He stated: “This move was very unwise.... His departure changed everything, and now the general sentiment seems to be leaning towards a republic, which is quite natural.”[131] [50] On the eve of the Legislative Assembly's opening on September 30, 1791, Morris wrote to Washington with clear observations about the republican movement: “The new Assembly, as far as can be determined at this moment, is strongly influenced by republican or, rather, democratic principles. The southern part of the country shares this view; the east is loyal to Germany and would happily join the empire; Normandy is aristocratic, as is part of Brittany; while the interior is monarchal. This layout is (you can trust me) accurate, as it is based on extensive investigations conducted by the Government.”[132] Brissot’s paper, Patriote français, on June 25, 1791, in analyzing the proposals for the government's executive branch, stated: “The first opinion presented to the public is clear—No more kings, let’s be republicans—such has been the cry from the Palais Royal, from certain societies, and among certain writers.”[133] Thomas Paine’s letter in response to Siéyès, published in the Patriote français on July 11, proclaimed that the American system of government is superior to all others and concluded the letter with these telling words: “Finally, it is against the entire hell of monarchy that I have declared war.”[134]
From these accumulated statements, we infer that about Paris, in the spring of 1791, especially after the 20th of June, there was much agitation in favor of the dethronement of Louis XVI, some for the change of the royal family, and a perceptible tendency in favor of a republic. After the acceptance of the Constitution by the king and by the Legislative Assembly, the constitutional question of the kingship is little discussed till in the summer of 1792. Then the Legislative Assembly was frightened over the defeat of the French army at Lille and at Tournay, the disastrous defeat of Biron’s army at Mons, and the probable advance of the Austrian army upon Paris. The king, following the advice of Montmorin and Malouet, had sent Mallet du Pan on a mission to the German courts to secure a manifesto of intimidation against the factious Frenchmen.[135] The Austrian committee was denounced boldly in the journals and in the Assembly.[136]
From all these statements, we can gather that around Paris, in the spring of 1791, especially after June 20th, there was significant unrest calling for the removal of Louis XVI, some advocating for a change in the royal family, and a noticeable shift towards favoring a republic. After the king and the Legislative Assembly accepted the Constitution, the issue of the monarchy was hardly discussed until the summer of 1792. Then, the Legislative Assembly became alarmed by the defeat of the French army at Lille and Tournay, the disastrous loss of Biron’s army at Mons, and the impending advance of the Austrian army towards Paris. Following the advice of Montmorin and Malouet, the king had sent Mallet du Pan on a mission to the German courts to secure a threatening manifesto against the rebellious Frenchmen. [135] The Austrian committee was boldly criticized in the newspapers and in the Assembly. [136]
Incited by this array of reverses, royal intrigues, and threatened invasion, the Assembly passed three decrees for the protection of the country: May 27, the deportation of the non-juring priests; May 29, the dismissal of the king’s guard; June 8, the formation of a camp of 20,000 fédérés at Paris. The king opposed his veto to the first and last of these. The Girondin ministry was dismissed early in June.[137] The invasion of the Tuileries, June 20, was the result of these aggravations. The petition presented to the Legislative Assembly by the crowd on that day does not solicit the establishment of a republic, but urges that the king should fulfill his constitutional function of protecting liberty.[138] The king continued to be disturbed by the people. The manifesto of the Duke of Brunswick, July 27, greatly excited the Parisians, already much aroused. Then from the sections of Paris, from administrative bodies, and from communes, addresses were sent in asking for the suspension or the dethronement of the king.[139] The significant fact about this outcry for the removal of Louis is the silence about what is to supersede him. The commune representing the forty-eight sections of Paris, through Pétion, presented at the bar of the Assembly, August 3, a petition most vehement in its denunciation of the faithless monarch and most startling in the picture presented of the country’s danger; but this commune, the most radical, perhaps, in France, invoked the Constitution in praying for his dethronement.[140]
Driven by a series of setbacks, royal conspiracies, and looming invasion, the Assembly enacted three decrees to protect the nation: on May 27, the expulsion of the non-juring priests; on May 29, the dismissal of the king’s guard; and on June 8, the creation of a camp of 20,000 fédérés in Paris. The king exercised his veto against the first and last decrees. The Girondin ministry was dismissed in early June.[137] The invasion of the Tuileries on June 20 was a direct outcome of these tensions. The petition presented to the Legislative Assembly by the crowd that day didn’t call for the establishment of a republic, but rather urged the king to fulfill his constitutional role of protecting liberty.[138] The people continued to unsettle the king. The Duke of Brunswick’s manifesto on July 27 incited intense reactions among the already agitated Parisians. Then, from the sections of Paris, from administrative bodies, and from various communes, requests for the king's suspension or abdication began to pour in.[139] What’s notable about this demand for Louis's removal is the absence of any clear alternative. The commune representing the forty-eight sections of Paris, led by Pétion, presented a petition to the Assembly on August 3 that strongly condemned the unfaithful monarch and painted a shocking picture of the nation’s peril; yet this commune, possibly the most radical in France, appealed to the Constitution in seeking his dethronement.[140]
The Legislative Assembly hesitated to take upon itself the work of deposition. The sections gave it till midnight of the 9th of August to decide; if at that time the dethronement had not been voted, the tocsin should sound and the générale should beat for the insurrection. The Assembly adjourned at 7 o’clock without deciding the question. The 10th of August the King was driven from the Tuileries, and took refuge in the Assembly.[52] Even then the legislators only suspended the King until “the National Convention should pronounce upon the measures which it believes ought to be adopted for assuring the sovereignty of the people and the reign of liberty and equality.”[141]
The Legislative Assembly hesitated to take on the task of removing the King. They were given until midnight on August 9th to make a decision; if they hadn’t voted for his dethronement by then, an alarm would sound, and the call for an uprising would go out. The Assembly adjourned at 7 PM without making a decision. On August 10th, the King was forced out of the Tuileries and sought refuge in the Assembly.[52] Even then, the lawmakers only suspended the King until “the National Convention decides on the measures it thinks should be taken to ensure the sovereignty of the people and the reign of liberty and equality.”[141]
August 11, the Assembly provided for the mode of election for the members of the new Convention, and gave universal suffrage to males over 21 years. Did it ask that the delegates should be instructed to vote for the monarchy or the republic? No; but they were to be given “unlimited confidence.”[142] M. Aulard has analyzed for us the powers given by the primary assemblies to the electoral assemblies of the Departments and by the latter to the deputies. He notes that almost universally the primary assemblies conformed to the advice to grant unlimited powers to the departmental electors. At the final election of deputies, September 2, in thirty-four Departments the electors made no allusion to what powers should be bestowed upon their representatives; in thirty-six they gave them “unlimited powers” or “unlimited confidence;” in two Departments, the Lower Pyrenees and Somme, the previous question was raised upon the powers to be given; in a single one (Charente) they gave as mandate the oath taken by the electors, “to maintain equality and liberty.” In three Departments, Aisne, Eure-et-Soir, and Paris, they gave full powers with the restriction that the constitutional laws to be made shall be submitted to the ratification of the people. Thus all either “inscribed the formula prescribed by the Legislature or omitted it as useless and self-evident.”
On August 11, the Assembly established how the members of the new Convention would be elected, granting universal suffrage to men over 21. Did they ask that the delegates be instructed to vote for either the monarchy or the republic? No; instead, they were to be given “unlimited confidence.” [142] M. Aulard has examined the powers that the primary assemblies granted to the electoral assemblies of the Departments and how these were passed on to the deputies. He notes that nearly all primary assemblies followed the advice to give unlimited powers to the departmental electors. During the final election of deputies on September 2, in thirty-four Departments, the electors made no reference to what powers should be given to their representatives; in thirty-six, they granted “unlimited powers” or “unlimited confidence;” in two Departments, the Lower Pyrenees and Somme, there was discussion about what powers to confer; and in only one (Charente), they directed that the mandate was the oath taken by the electors “to maintain equality and liberty.” In three Departments, Aisne, Eure-et-Soir, and Paris, they granted full powers with the stipulation that any constitutional laws made would need to be ratified by the people. Thus, all either “inscribed the formula prescribed by the Legislature or dismissed it as unnecessary and obvious.”
Shall there be a monarchy or a republic? What was the voice of the departments upon this question? Only one out of the eighty-three Departments expressed a clear demand upon this point. This one, that which includes Paris, asked for “the form of a republican government.” In the other eighty-two the word republic was not pronounced. One Department, Jura, however, attempted to define in rather express terms the sort of government to be formed, “A temporary executive power, removable at the option of the people,” but it does not use the term republic.[143] Four Departments were pronounced against royalty,[53] and swore eternal hostility thereto; these were Aube, Charente-Inférieure, Jura, and Paris. No Department asked the continuance of the monarchy, and only a few primary assemblies asked this. These assemblies were in four Departments, i. e., five in Allier, one in Ariége, three in the Gironde, and two in Lot-et-Garonne.
Should we have a monarchy or a republic? What did the departments say about this? Only one of the eighty-three departments clearly expressed a preference. That one, which includes Paris, requested “the form of a republican government.” In the other eighty-two, the word republic wasn't mentioned. One department, Jura, tried to specify the type of government to be established, saying “A temporary executive power, removable at the choice of the people,” but it didn’t use the term republic.[143] Four departments were against royalty,[53] and swore eternal opposition to it; these were Aube, Charente-Inférieure, Jura, and Paris. No department asked for the continuation of the monarchy, and only a few local assemblies did. These assemblies were located in four departments, i. e., five in Allier, one in Ariège, three in the Gironde, and two in Lot-et-Garonne.
If we examine the proceedings of the Jacobin Club, we find that this society was devoted for some time to the King and to the constitution.[144] No bitter opposition to the monarch is found till after June 20, 1791. Then it was his violation of the constitution that caused his denunciation. After the two famous vetoes, a member proposed in the Club that they make use of Art. vi, Sec. 10, Chapt. 2, of the Constitution, “If the King puts himself at the head of an army and directs the forces against the nation ... he will be considered to have abdicated royalty.”[145] The printing of this discourse was urged on all hands. The Club frequently mentioned the calling of a convention. Its sympathy with the work of August 10 is evident,[146] and its hostility to the monarchy is more pronounced from this period.[147]
If we look at what the Jacobin Club did, we see that this group was committed to supporting the King and the constitution for a while. No strong opposition to the monarchy appears until after June 20, 1791. It was then his breach of the constitution that led to his condemnation. After the two well-known vetoes, a member suggested in the Club that they reference Art. vi, Sec. 10, Chapt. 2, of the Constitution, “If the King puts himself at the head of an army and directs the forces against the nation... he will be considered to have abdicated royalty.” The printing of this statement was advocated by many. The Club often discussed the idea of calling a convention. Its support for the events of August 10 is clear, and its opposition to the monarchy became more obvious from this point on.
A definite suggestion of the constructive scheme was made in the Club, September 7; Chabot introduced the discussion of the form of government, and referred to two kinds, (1) the federation of the departments, and (2) a National Council, which should be presided over in turn by one of the deputies of one of the portions of the empire. Chabot favored the latter.[148] Again returning to[54] the same question, September 10, Terrasson pronounced a preference for the federation, and cited Rousseau as his authority and America for a successful example.[149] Two days after, September 12, a letter was proposed and was adopted in the Jacobin Club of Paris, to be sent to the affiliated societies. In it were contained these three proposals, which may be regarded as setting forth the policy of the democratic party of Paris; the popular sanction or popular revision of all the constitutional decrees of the National Convention; the total abolition of royalty, and the penalty of death against those who proposed to re-establish it; the republican form of government.[150]
A clear proposal for a new government structure was made in the Club on September 7; Chabot started the discussion about the type of government and mentioned two options: (1) the federation of the departments, and (2) a National Council, which would be led in rotation by one of the representatives from different parts of the empire. Chabot supported the second option. [148] On September 10, returning to the same topic, Terrasson expressed a preference for the federation and referenced Rousseau as his authority, citing America as a successful example. [149] Two days later, on September 12, a letter was proposed and adopted in the Jacobin Club of Paris to be sent to affiliated societies. This letter included three proposals that can be seen as outlining the policy of the democratic party in Paris: the need for popular approval or review of all the constitutional decrees from the National Convention; the complete abolition of monarchy, with a death penalty for anyone suggesting its restoration; and the establishment of a republican form of government. [150]
The significance of this movement on the part of the parent Jacobin Club must not be overlooked in tracing the progress of republicanism. The affiliation of well nigh a thousand societies in other parts of France with the parent society afforded a strong and thoroughly organized means for concerted political action.[151] The nominees of the popular societies were nearly everywhere[55] chosen to represent the provinces in the Convention.[152] In the list of deputies from Paris appeared the names of pronounced republicans and radical Jacobins who might be expected to take a stand for a popular form of government.[153]
The importance of this movement by the parent Jacobin Club shouldn't be ignored when looking at the development of republicanism. The connection of almost a thousand societies in other parts of France with the parent society provided a strong and well-organized way for united political action.[151] The candidates from the popular societies were almost always selected to represent the provinces in the Convention.[152] The list of deputies from Paris included the names of outspoken republicans and radical Jacobins who were expected to support a popular form of government.[153]
The Convention held its first meeting in the Tuileries; only 371 members were present. They verified their powers, organized by choosing Pétion as President, and by naming five Secretaries. September 21, they occupied the place of the Legislative Assembly in the Riding School. Here they had declared in favor of the following measures suitable for allaying the fears of disorder: (1) The National Convention declares that there can only be a constitution when it is accepted by the people; (2) that the security of person and of property is under the safeguard of the nation; (3) that all laws not abrogated, and all powers not revoked or suspended are maintained; (4) that the existing taxes shall be collected as in the past.
The Convention held its first meeting at the Tuileries, with only 371 members present. They confirmed their authority, organizing themselves by electing Pétion as President and appointing five Secretaries. On September 21, they took over the Legislative Assembly’s space in the Riding School. Here, they declared support for the following measures aimed at easing concerns about disorder: (1) The National Convention states that a constitution can only exist if it is accepted by the people; (2) that personal and property security is protected by the nation; (3) that all laws not repealed, and all powers not revoked or suspended, remain in effect; (4) that existing taxes will be collected as before.
This effected, they were about to adjourn, when Collot d’Herbois ascended the tribune and said: “You have just passed a wise resolution, but there is one which you can not put off till tomorrow, which you can not put off till this evening, which you can not put off a single instant without being unfaithful to the wish of the nation; that is the abolition of royalty.” Unanimous applause greeted this speech. M. Grégoire proposed that “by a solemn law they sanction the abolition of royalty,” and the[56] entire Assembly by a spontaneous movement arose and voted this proclamation by acclamation; a brief discussion followed, and then with loud bursts of applause they voted, “The National Convention decrees that royalty is abolished in France.” For some time the cry “Vive la Nation” was prolonged. At this juncture a company of 150 chasseurs were admitted to the hall and swore upon their arms to return only after having triumphed over all the enemies of liberty and equality. But as yet the word Republic had not been mentioned in the new Convention.
This done, they were about to close the meeting when Collot d’Herbois stepped up to the podium and said: “You’ve just made a smart decision, but there’s one thing you can’t postpone until tomorrow, you can’t put it off until this evening, you can’t delay it for even a second without betraying the will of the people; that’s the abolition of royalty.” This speech was met with unanimous applause. M. Grégoire proposed that “through a formal law they endorse the abolition of royalty,” and the[56] entire Assembly, in a spontaneous show of support, stood up and voted for this proclamation by acclamation. A brief discussion followed, and then, with loud bursts of applause, they voted, “The National Convention decrees that royalty is abolished in France.” For some time, the chant “Vive la Nation” continued. At this moment, a group of 150 chasseurs was allowed into the hall and swore on their weapons to return only after defeating all enemies of liberty and equality. But at this point, the word Republic had not yet been mentioned in the new Convention.
At the evening session of that day the time was consumed in hearing of the discourses of divers deputations that had come to congratulate the Convention upon the great work done that day. Two of these spoke of the Republic as an already established fact,[154] while on the streets, however, of the city the cry was resounding, “Vive la République.” One orator spoke of nine battalions already sent to the front, and reported that another was on the way. “They were coming,” he said, “to pray your blessing upon their arms, when they learned on the way that they were to fight no more for kings. They were happy to go to save the Republic. When they were informed that all your moments must be consecrated to it, they renounced the enjoyment of receiving your blessing and went on their way. Our Department is busy forming new battalions, in seeking to arm them, and especially in inspiring them with republican manners.” This was greeted with new applause. The section of Quatre-Nations was represented by its orator, who said among other things; “We have given three thousand men for the frontier; these are three thousand republicans.... We ask to defile through your midst. If arms are needed, speak, we shall hasten to use them in the defense of the country, too happy to pay with our blood for the Republic which you have decreed for us.” Applause greeted this expression of devotion.[155] The newspapers signaled the decree of abolition in enthusiastic[57] descriptions, but only Brissot’s Patriote français proclaimed, “Royalty is abolished; France is a Republic.”[156]
At the evening session that day, the time was spent listening to speeches from various groups that had come to congratulate the Convention on the significant work accomplished that day. Two of these groups referred to the Republic as already a reality, while on the streets of the city, the cry was echoing, “Vive la République.” One speaker mentioned nine battalions already dispatched to the front and reported that another was on the way. “They were coming,” he said, “to seek your blessing on their arms, when they learned en route that they would fight no more for kings. They were eager to go and defend the Republic. When they heard that every moment must be dedicated to it, they chose to forgo receiving your blessing and continued on their path. Our Department is actively forming new battalions, working to arm them, and especially to instill them with republican values.” This was met with renewed applause. The Quatre-Nations section was represented by its speaker, who stated among other things, “We have contributed three thousand men for the frontier; these are three thousand republicans.... We ask to parade among you. If arms are needed, let us know; we will rush to use them in defense of our country, more than willing to shed our blood for the Republic that you have established for us.” This expression of loyalty was met with applause. The newspapers celebrated the decree of abolition with enthusiastic descriptions, but only Brissot’s Patriote français announced, “Royalty is abolished; France is a Republic.”
On the morrow early in the session, Billaud-Varenne moved, and the Convention decreed, that “all public acts were to be dated from the first year of the Republic.” A new seal of State bearing the words “République de France” decided upon and national colors were proposed, but not adopted.[157] The journals took little notice of this new name with which France had been baptized. Nevertheless, the members of the Convention seemed to take it as a matter of course and to make repeated use of the term Republic. For instance, on September 22, it appeared in the following decree: “The National Convention decrees that the committees of the legislative assembly and the members of the executive council shall render an account to the National Convention of the state of their work and of the condition of the different parts of the French Republic....” The report of the Minister of the Interior, M. Gorsas, in the session of September 23, contained this report of the state of public opinion: “The will of the French is pronounced. Liberty and equality are their supreme good; they will sacrifice all to preserve these. They have a horror for the crimes of the nobles, the hypocrisy of the priests, the tyranny of kings. Kings! they wish no more of them, they know that outside of a Republic there is no liberty.” Again on September 24, the Convention decreed “that there shall be named six commissioners charged with rendering as full an account as shall be possible, of the present state of the Republic and that of Paris.” On September 25, the Convention declared “the French Republic is one and indivisible.”[158]
The next morning during the session, Billaud-Varenne proposed, and the Convention agreed, that “all public acts should be dated from the first year of the Republic.” A new State seal featuring the words “République de France” was decided upon, and national colors were suggested, but not adopted. The journals paid little attention to this new name that France had been given. Still, the members of the Convention seemed to accept it as a given and frequently used the term Republic. For example, on September 22, it appeared in this decree: “The National Convention decrees that the committees of the legislative assembly and the members of the executive council shall report to the National Convention on the state of their work and the condition of the different parts of the French Republic....” The report from the Minister of the Interior, M. Gorsas, during the session of September 23, included this assessment of public opinion: “The will of the French is clear. Liberty and equality are their highest priorities; they will sacrifice everything to protect these. They have a deep aversion to the crimes of the nobles, the hypocrisy of the priests, and the tyranny of kings. Kings! They want no more of them; they understand that outside of a Republic there is no liberty.” Again on September 24, the Convention decreed “that six commissioners shall be appointed to provide as thorough an account as possible of the current state of the Republic and that of Paris.” On September 25, the Convention declared “the French Republic is one and indivisible.”
Here we have passed to the period in which the Republic had become an accepted fact for France. Robespierre said truly that it had “glided in furtively among the factions,” and we may say that to Frenchmen, interested in the national defence, it was a welcome change. Gouverneur Morris is authority for this in a note of October, 1792, in which he said: “These are the outlines made use of on either side to convince the public that each is exclusively[58] the author of a Republic which the people find themselves possessed of by a kind of magic, or at least, a sleight of hand, and which, nevertheless, they are as fond of as if it were their own offspring.”[159]
Here we find ourselves in a time when the Republic had become an accepted reality for France. Robespierre correctly noted that it had “sneaked in quietly among the factions,” and we can say that for the French, who were concerned about national defense, it was a welcome change. Gouverneur Morris supports this in a note from October 1792, stating: “These are the arguments used by both sides to convince the public that each is solely responsible for a Republic that the people feel they have, almost as if by magic, or at least through some trick, and which they nevertheless cherish as if it were their own child.”[58]
It would be interesting to know how completely this Parisian enthusiasm was shared by the nation. Grave objections may have been offered, but it soon came about that to be disloyal to the Republic was to be a foe of liberty and equality, and, worse yet, a traitor to France. So far as we are able to discover, the army accepted the Republic with enthusiasm. On September 9, General Valence wrote to Dumouriez that he would run to the Republic with transport. Prieur (de la Marne) awakened enthusiasm in the army of the Ardennes by announcing to them on September 29, the news of the birth of the Republic.[160] And a report from the camp of volunteers at Châlons speaks of a like worthy sentiment.[161]
It would be interesting to know just how much this excitement in Paris was felt across the country. There may have been serious objections, but it quickly became clear that being disloyal to the Republic meant being against liberty and equality, and even worse, a traitor to France. As far as we can tell, the army embraced the Republic with enthusiasm. On September 9, General Valence wrote to Dumouriez that he would eagerly support the Republic. Prieur (de la Marne) inspired enthusiasm in the army of the Ardennes by announcing to them on September 29 the news of the Republic's birth.[160] And a report from the camp of volunteers at Châlons describes a similar positive sentiment.[161]
These are the facts about the growth of republican ideas in Revolutionary France and of the proclamation of the Republic. We can sum them up as follows: At the meeting of the States-General in 1789 France was pronouncedly monarchic. A little coterie of men became anti-monarchical; these developed the Club of Cordeliers. In 1791, when Louis XVI showed his distrust of the French people and tried to escape, hostility to the monarch and also to the monarchy was strong. Even republicanism was championed by an orator in the Assembly and by a few newspapers; one of these journals, the Révolutions de Paris, had a large circulation. The king however accepted the Constitution in September, 1791, and the outcry against him and in favor of the abolition of the monarchy subsided. Not until in the summer of 1792 did the royal vetoes, the menacing manifesto of the allies, the actual advance of the Prussian army toward Paris, call forth many petitions and requests for the suspension or for the dethronement of the king, or for the abolition of the monarchy.
These are the facts about the rise of republican ideas in Revolutionary France and the announcement of the Republic. We can summarize them like this: At the meeting of the States-General in 1789, France was clearly monarchic. A small group of people became anti-monarchical; they formed the Club of Cordeliers. In 1791, when Louis XVI revealed his distrust of the French people and attempted to flee, opposition to the king and the monarchy was strong. Republicanism was supported by a speaker in the Assembly and a few newspapers; one of these publications, the Révolutions de Paris, had a large readership. However, the king accepted the Constitution in September 1791, and the outcry against him and in favor of abolishing the monarchy quieted down. Not until the summer of 1792 did the royal vetoes, the threatening manifesto from the allies, and the Prussian army's actual advance toward Paris spark many petitions and demands for the king's suspension or dethronement, or for the abolition of the monarchy.
Comparatively little was said, however, about the form to be given to the executive. On August 10, the Legislative[59] Assembly only “suspended Louis XVI provisionally, until the National Convention should pronounce upon the measures it believed ought to be adopted for assuring the sovereignty of the people and the reign of liberty and equality.” Clubs, sections, journals, and provinces, and even radical democrats, are rather silent about a substitute for the monarchy. When the abolition came on September 21, it was received as the news of a national victory; but at first the term Republic, used on the 22nd, was little greeted by the nation. It however became the shibboleth of the army and of the patriots. For this revival of republicanism, Paris, and perhaps the army, are responsible. The Jacobin Club of Paris also made use of its influential position to encourage republican inclinations in the affiliated societies throughout France, and, what was more important still, to secure the election of anti-monarchical and of democratic deputies to the Convention.
However, not much was said about the structure of the executive. On August 10, the Legislative[59] Assembly only “suspended Louis XVI temporarily, until the National Convention could decide on the actions needed to ensure the sovereignty of the people and the reign of liberty and equality.” Clubs, sections, journals, and provinces, along with radical democrats, were mostly quiet about a replacement for the monarchy. When abolition was declared on September 21, it was celebrated as a national victory; however, the term Republic, used on the 22nd, received a lukewarm response from the nation. Nevertheless, it became a rallying cry for the army and the patriots. The revival of republicanism can be attributed to Paris, and possibly the army. The Jacobin Club in Paris leveraged its influential position to promote republican sentiments in affiliated societies across France, and, more importantly, to ensure the election of anti-monarchical and democratic representatives to the Convention.
A few questions remain to be answered. First among these is, What was the relation between the republican movement of 1791 and that of 1792? The earlier movement must have had a tendency to increase the number in France who perceived the inconsistency between individual rights and the equality of men on the one hand, and the hereditary kingship on the other. It also increased the number of those who believed a republic suited for France and who, though they recognized that the realization of their opinions was for the time being impossible, yet were ready to strive for its establishment when the circumstances should give opportunity. To this group of men belongs the credit of having secured an expression from Paris in favor of the Republic, and of having secured its early recognition in the city on the abolition of royalty.
A few questions are still left to answer. The first one is, what was the connection between the republican movement of 1791 and that of 1792? The earlier movement likely made more people in France aware of the contradiction between individual rights and equality among men on one side, and hereditary kingship on the other. It also increased the number of those who believed a republic was suitable for France and who, although they understood that achieving their views was impossible for the moment, were still willing to work towards its establishment when the opportunity arose. This group of people deserves credit for voicing support for the Republic in Paris and for ensuring its early recognition in the city following the abolition of monarchy.
A second question is, Why was there so much said in 1792 about the abolition of monarchy, and so little about the Republic that should replace it? Why were those of republican preferences so slow to say it? This may be answered by the statement that generally, in movements depending upon public opinion, the people are more pronounced against an abuse or misuse which they have experienced than about an untried theory; are more capable to pronounce upon a destructive than upon a constructive scheme, are more enlightened in their negative than in their positive actions. The Constituent Assembly was happy in its negative work of destroying the abuses of the old régime, but less[60] felicitous in its positive work of reconstruction. The French people of 1792 were conversant with the vacillations of the king, the treasonable intrigues and anti-popular feelings of the court, but a Republic was as yet an untried and unproved expedient. Under its name anarchy, or, what to the Parisians was little less odious, federalism, might become the order of the day. Hence the very friends of a strong united Republic hesitated to use the word till the form of the institution should be shaped by the tendency of affairs. The very friends of Republican government might have remembered that their use of the word Republic in 1791 had been fraught with bitter schismatic tendencies among the friends of the Revolution; and how much more dangerous such a schism in 1792, when the nation found itself called upon to resist the humiliating invasion of its territory by the allies. They also knew that to be a republican in 1791 had been unpopular,[162] and were chary of exposing themselves to unnecessary odium, knowing that the monarchy once abolished, they would be by necessity under a liberal form of government, call it what they might.
A second question is, why was there so much talk in 1792 about abolishing the monarchy, and so little about what kind of Republic should take its place? Why were those who preferred a Republic so slow to express it? This can be explained by the fact that generally, in movements driven by public opinion, people are more vocal against an abuse or misuse they've experienced than they are about an untested theory; they are better at criticizing destructive actions than at promoting constructive ones, and they're generally more aware of what they oppose than what they support. The Constituent Assembly was effective in its role of dismantling the abuses of the old regime, but less successful in its task of rebuilding. The French people of 1792 were familiar with the king's inconsistencies, the treasonous schemes, and the anti-popular sentiments of the court, but a Republic was still an unfamiliar and unproven concept. Under its name, anarchy, or what was nearly as undesirable to Parisians, federalism, could easily take hold. Because of this, even the supporters of a strong united Republic hesitated to use the term until they saw how events would unfold. The supporters of Republican governance likely recalled that their use of the term Republic in 1791 had led to bitter divisions among Revolution supporters; and how much more dangerous such divisions were in 1792, when the nation faced the humiliating threat of invasion by foreign allies. They also knew that being a republican in 1791 had been unpopular, and therefore were cautious about exposing themselves to unnecessary backlash, knowing that once the monarchy was abolished, they would inevitably have to adopt some form of liberal government, regardless of what it was called.
A third query is, Why did the Conventionalists choose the republican government? The question is easily answered by another question, i. e., What other expedient was possible, considering the state of public opinion? Was it an aristocracy? But the Revolution in its incipient stages was a revolt against an aristocracy. Was it a regency? But here the difficulty was to find a regent who did not share the obloquy of the dethroned monarch, or was not incapable of commanding the respect of the nation. Was it under the protection of a foreign prince or power? Not so; the spirit of national independence was too strong to suffer even a dispassionate consideration of this. What way could the Constitutionalists turn? Sorel has truly said: “The abolition of royalty was the acknowledgment of a fact; the proclamation of the Republic was the recognition of a necessity. A government was necessary to France, and no other than a republican government was possible.”[163] And the Republic had existed in[61] fact in France for two short, but very critical periods. From June 21 to September 14, 1791, the king had been suspended and the Constituent Assembly had conducted through the ministry the work of the executive. And again from August 10 to September 21, 1792, the same expedient was resorted to. But it may be said that the Republic was not in accord with French national traditions, and that, therefore, it could never be accepted by the nation. True, France had been a monarchy for centuries, and the history of her kings was dear to the people in 1789; but there was a stronger tradition to which the people were more devotedly attached than to royalty, and now the king had forced the issue between these two traditions, that is, the tradition of the monarchy and the tradition of nationality and independence. So soon as it seemed clear that the French must choose between these, the choice was made by the abolition of royalty.
A third question is, why did the Conventionalists opt for a republican government? The answer is straightforward when posed with another question: what other option was available given the public opinion at the time? Was it an aristocracy? However, the Revolution's early stages were a reaction against an aristocracy. Was it a regency? The challenge here was finding a regent who didn’t share the disgrace of the deposed monarch or who commanded the respect of the nation. Was it going to be under the protection of a foreign prince or power? No, the spirit of national independence was too strong to even allow for a detached consideration of that. What options did the Constitutionalists have? Sorel has accurately stated: “The abolition of royalty was the acknowledgment of a fact; the proclamation of the Republic was the recognition of a necessity. A government was necessary for France, and only a republican government was viable.”[163] And the Republic had actually existed in France during two brief but significant periods. From June 21 to September 14, 1791, the king was suspended, and the Constituent Assembly managed executive functions. Again, from August 10 to September 21, 1792, the same approach was taken. It might be argued that the Republic didn’t align with French national traditions, and thus it could never be embraced by the nation. It's true that France had been a monarchy for centuries, and the history of its kings was cherished by the people in 1789; however, there was a more powerful tradition to which the people were more deeply committed than to the monarchy, and now the king had forced the issue between these two traditions: the tradition of the monarchy and the tradition of nationality and independence. As soon as it became evident that the French had to choose between these, they opted for the abolition of royalty.
Royalty was thus abolished on September 21, 1792: the republic was recognized by the Convention as its legitimate successor. The name had been adopted, now a new constitution was necessary; not one like that of 1791, a base accommodation of hereditary powers and democratic rights; but one consistently constructed. The Convention early appointed its Committee of Constitution. The leader in the committee was Condorcet, and the majority were Girondists. Their work was ready to be reported February 15 and 16, 1793. But by this time the republicans themselves had formed two antagonistic factions, the Girondists and the Montagnards. The latter were the men of action, and now held the power in the Convention. Condorcet’s Constitution was not submitted to the nation.
Royalty was abolished on September 21, 1792: the Convention recognized the republic as its legitimate successor. The name had been adopted, and now a new constitution was needed; not one like that of 1791, a flawed compromise between hereditary powers and democratic rights; but one that was consistently structured. The Convention quickly appointed its Committee of Constitution. The leader of the committee was Condorcet, and the majority were Girondists. Their work was ready to be reported on February 15 and 16, 1793. But by this time, the republicans themselves had split into two opposing factions, the Girondists and the Montagnards. The latter were the men of action and now held power in the Convention. Condorcet’s Constitution was never submitted to the nation.
On May 30, 1793, the Committee of Public Safety was augmented by five members. These were Couthon, Herault de Séchelles, Mathieu, Ramel, and Saint Just. They lost no time in the elaboration of a Constitution, and by June 22, were ready to report. Herault de Séchelles made the final reading June 24. Delegates were sent all over France to receive the vote of the primary assemblies for the acceptance of the Constitutional Act; 1,801,918 votes were cast for its adoption. Their glowing report was made August 9th by Gossuin, and the next day was fixed as a national festival “consecrated to the inauguration of the Constitution of the Republic.” The artist, David, planned the ceremonies.
On May 30, 1793, the Committee of Public Safety was expanded by five members: Couthon, Herault de Séchelles, Mathieu, Ramel, and Saint Just. They quickly got to work on a Constitution and by June 22, they were ready to present it. Herault de Séchelles conducted the final reading on June 24. Delegates were sent throughout France to gather votes from the primary assemblies for the acceptance of the Constitutional Act; 1,801,918 votes were cast in favor of its adoption. Gossuin made their enthusiastic report on August 9th, and the next day was designated as a national festival “dedicated to the inauguration of the Constitution of the Republic.” The artist, David, organized the ceremonies.
The glorious fundamental law was not, however, to reign in France. France must be defended from invasion, civil war must be subdued, and then the rest of Europe must be delivered from political slavery. In just two months after this inaugural festival, the Convention decreed that the provisional government should be revolutionary till peace. When peace came, a new monarch was enthroned. But these enthusiastic men of 1792 and 1793 had given France a name and an ideal; they had placed above her horizon a star of hope. When oppression shall make them weary, or when the popular spirits shall rise, they shall think of a republic as the aim and end of political effort.
The glorious fundamental law was not meant to take hold in France. France needed to be protected from invasion, civil war had to be put down, and then the rest of Europe needed to be freed from political oppression. Just two months after this inaugural event, the Convention declared that the provisional government would remain revolutionary until peace was achieved. When peace finally arrived, a new monarch took the throne. But these passionate people of 1792 and 1793 had given France a name and an ideal; they had placed a star of hope in her future. When they grow tired of oppression, or when the public spirit rises, they will envision a republic as the goal and ultimate purpose of political efforts.
FOOTNOTES
[1] Ritchie, Natural Rights, p. 1; M. Charles Borgeaud, Établissement et Revision des Constitutions en Amérique et en Europe, 240-242; Dr. Geo. Jellinek, Die Erklärung der Menschen- und Bürgerrechte, p. 10.
[1] Ritchie, Natural Rights, p. 1; M. Charles Borgeaud, Establishment and Revision of Constitutions in America and Europe, 240-242; Dr. Geo. Jellinek, The Declaration of Human and Civil Rights, p. 10.
[2] Two requests for a Declaration of the Rights of Man came from Paris, intra muros; one from the Nobility, Archives parlementaires, v, 271; the other from the Third Estate, Ibid., v, 281. The latter cahier contains a formulated Declaration of thirteen articles. The general cahier of Rennes, Arch. Parl., v, 538, that of the Third Estate of Annonay, Arch. Parl., ii, 50, and that of the Third Estate of Nemours, Arch. Parl., iv, 161, ask for the Declaration of Rights.
[2] Two requests for a Declaration of the Rights of Man came from Paris, intra muros; one from the Nobility, Archives parlementaires, v, 271; the other from the Third Estate, Ibid., v, 281. The latter document includes a structured Declaration of thirteen articles. The general document from Rennes, Arch. Parl., v, 538, that of the Third Estate of Annonay, Arch. Parl., ii, 50, and that of the Third Estate of Nemours, Arch. Parl., iv, 161, request the Declaration of Rights.
[3] Arch. Parl., viii, 216.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Arch. Parl., vol. viii, p. 216.
[4] Ibid., 221 et seq.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Ibid., 221 and following.
[5] Ibid., 221-222.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Same source., 221-222.
[6] Ibid., 230-231.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Same source., 230-231.
[7] Ibid.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Same source.
[8] Arch. Parl., 341.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Arch. Parl., 341.
[9] Ibid., 422.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Same source., 422.
[10] “Convertions nous en acte législatif cet exposé métaphysique, ou présenterons nous les principes avec leur modification dans la constitution que nous allons faire? Je sais que les Américains n’ont pas pris cette précaution; ils ont pris l’homme dans le sein de la nature, et le présentent à l’univers dans sa souveraineté primitive, mais la société Américaine nouvellement formée, est composée, en totalité de propriétaires déjà accoutumés à l’égalité, étrangers au luxe ainsi qu’à l’indulgence, connaissant à peine le joug des impôts, des préjugés qui nous dominent, n’ayant trouvé sur la terre qu’ils cultivent aucune trace de féodalité. De tels hommes étaient sans doute préparés à recevoir la liberté dans toute son energie; car leurs goûts, leurs moeurs, leur position les appelaient à la démocratie. Mais, nous, Messieurs, nous avons pour concitoyens une multitude immense d’hommes sans propriétés, qui attendent, avant toute chose, leur subsistence d’un travail assuré, d’une police exacte, d’une protection continue, qui s’irritent quelquefois, non sans de justes motifs, du spectacle du luxe et de l’opulence,” etc. Arch. Parl., viii, 322.
[10] “Should we turn this metaphysical discussion into legislation, or should we present the principles along with their modifications in the constitution we are about to create? I know that the Americans didn’t take this precaution; they accepted man as he is in nature and presented him to the world in his original sovereignty. However, the newly formed American society is made up entirely of property owners who are already accustomed to equality, unfamiliar with luxury or indulgence, knowing hardly anything about the burdens of taxes or the prejudices that dominate us, and having found no trace of feudalism in the land they cultivate. Such individuals were undoubtedly prepared to embrace freedom in all its strength; for their tastes, their customs, and their position drew them towards democracy. But we, gentlemen, have among us a vast multitude of property-less individuals, who expect, above all, their livelihood from assured work, accurate law enforcement, and continuous protection, and who sometimes become justifiably irritated by the display of luxury and wealth,” etc. Arch. Parl., viii, 322.
[11] Arch. Parl., viii, 434.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Arch. Parl., vol. viii, 434.
[12] “Nous avons cherché cette forme populaire qui rappelle au peuple, non ce qu’on a étudié dans les livres ou dans les méditations abstraites, mais ce qu’il a lui même éprouvé.... C’est ainsi que les Américains ont fait leur déclaration de droits; ils en ont à dessein écarté la science; ils ont présenté les vérités politiques qu’il s’agissait de fixer sous une forme qui pût devenir facilement celle du peuple, à qui seul la liberté importe, et qui seul peut la maintenir.” Arch. Parl., viii, 438-440.
[12] “We sought this popular form that reminds the people, not of what they've studied from books or in abstract thoughts, but of what they have personally experienced.... This is how Americans crafted their declaration of rights; they deliberately set aside science; they presented the political truths that needed to be established in a way that could easily resonate with the people, who alone care about freedom, and who alone can preserve it.” Arch. Parl., viii, 438-440.
[13] Arch. Parl., viii, 452 et seq.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Arch. Parl., viii, 452 and following
[14] A comparison of the Declaration offered by the Sixth Bureau with the Bill of Rights of the Revolutionary Constitutions of Massachusetts and of Virginia, shows that the Bill of Rights of the Virginia Constitution contained sixteen articles, that of the Massachusetts thirty, and that of the Sixth Bureau, twenty-four. The same general ideas are found in all three, but they are couched in different words, that of the Sixth Bureau being the least extreme.
[14] A comparison of the Declaration from the Sixth Bureau with the Bill of Rights from the Revolutionary Constitutions of Massachusetts and Virginia shows that the Bill of Rights in the Virginia Constitution had sixteen articles, Massachusetts had thirty, and the Sixth Bureau had twenty-four. While the same general ideas are present in all three, they are expressed in different wording, with the Sixth Bureau's version being the least extreme.
[15] Arch. Parl., viii, 470 et seq.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Arch. Parl., viii, 470 and following
[16] Ibid., 483-484.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Same source., 483-484.
[17] Ibid., 487, 489.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Same source., 487, 489.
[18] Ibid., 492.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Same source., 492.
[19] Histoire Parlementaire, 395-402.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Parliamentary History, 395-402.
[21] Ibid., vii, 360.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Same source., vii, 360.
[22] Dict. Universelle, under Rétroactif.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Universal Dictionary, under Retroactive.
[23] Three friends of tolerance were Voltaire, D’Argenson and Turgot. Voltaire in his Discourse Historique et Critique placed as an introduction to the tragedy Les Guebres (Oeuvres, by M. Beuchet, ix, 26, Paris, 1831), and in his Traité sur la tolérance, written upon the death of Jean Calas, 1763 (Oeuvres, ix, 141 and 243 et seq.), pleads for tolerance. For d’Argenson’s views on tolérance in 1744, see Rocquain, L’ésprit révolutionnaire, 116 and 138, and d’Argenson, Mémoires, v, 328 et seq. Turgot in a letter to an ecclesiastic, his schoolmate at the Sorbonne, expressed himself in 1753 in favor of tolerance; another letter of the year following was of like import. His Conciliateur was printed about the same time. Oeuvres, ii, 353 et seq., Paris, 1808. June, 1755, he presented a Memoir to the king on “Toleration, or Religious Equality.” Life and Writings of Turgot, by W. Walker Stephens, 256 et seq.
[23] Three friends of tolerance were Voltaire, D’Argenson, and Turgot. Voltaire, in his Discourse Historique et Critique, introduced the tragedy Les Guebres (Oeuvres, by M. Beuchet, ix, 26, Paris, 1831) and in his Traité sur la tolérance, written after the death of Jean Calas in 1763 (Oeuvres, ix, 141 and 243 et seq.), advocated for tolerance. For d’Argenson’s views on tolerance in 1744, see Rocquain, L’ésprit révolutionnaire, 116 and 138, as well as d’Argenson, Mémoires, v, 328 et seq. Turgot expressed his support for tolerance in a letter to a fellow student at Sorbonne in 1753; he wrote another similar letter the following year. His Conciliateur was published around the same time. Oeuvres, ii, 353 et seq., Paris, 1808. In June 1755, he presented a Memoir to the king on "Toleration, or Religious Equality." Life and Writings of Turgot, by W. Walker Stephens, 256 et seq.
[24] Rocquain, L’ésprit rév., p. 463.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Rocquain, L'ésprit rév., p. 463.
[25] Ibid., 336.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Same source., 336.
[28] Rocquain, L’ésprit rév., 286.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Rocquain, The Spirit Revealed, 286.
[30] The cahier of the Nobility of Sisteron asked: “Qu’il sera fait des réglements, et pris des précautions pour que les troupes nécessaires au maintien de la tranquilité générale ne puissent jamais servir à opprimer le citoyen et à enchaîner la liberté publique.” Arch. Parl., iii, 364. The cahier of the Nobility and the Third Estate of Péronne asked: “Que ... les officiers et les soldats, en prêtant le serment de fidélité au Roi, le prêtent aussi à la nation et jurent d n’exécuter aucun ordre qui soit contraire aux lois constitutionelles.” Arch. Parl., v, 356.
[30] The notebook of the Nobility of Sisteron asked: “What regulations will be put in place to ensure that the troops needed to maintain general peace can never be used to oppress citizens or restrict public freedom?” Arch. Parl., iii, 364. The notebook of the Nobility and the Third Estate of Péronne asked: “That ... the officers and soldiers, in taking the oath of loyalty to the King, also swear loyalty to the nation and promise not to carry out any orders that contradict constitutional laws.” Arch. Parl., v, 356.
[32] Hist. Gén., v, 362.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Gen. Hist., v, 362.
[35] Hist. Gén., vii, chap. xii.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Gen. Hist., vol. vii, chap. xii.
[37] Rocquain, L’ésprit rév., 448.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Rocquain, The spirit revealed., 448.
[38] For the part taken by the States General in granting subsidies, see Henri Hervieu, Recherches sur les premiers États généraux, Paris, 1879; G. Picot, Hist. des États Généraux Paris, 1885, 5 vols.; Ch. V. Langlois, États généraux in La Grande Encyclopédie; for that of the parlements, see Rocquain, L’ésprit rév., and Ch. Gomel, Les Causes financières de la révolution française.
[38] For the role of the States General in providing subsidies, see Henri Hervieu, Recherches sur les premiers États généraux, Paris, 1879; G. Picot, Hist. des États Généraux Paris, 1885, 5 vols.; Ch. V. Langlois, États généraux in La Grande Encyclopédie; for the parliaments, see Rocquain, L’ésprit rév., and Ch. Gomel, Les Causes financières de la révolution française.
[39] Protest of the Cour des Aides of Paris, April 10, 1775, in Translations and Reprints from the Original Sources of European History, edited by James Harvey Robinson, Ph. D., with an English version by Grace Read Robinson.
[39] Protest of the Cour des Aides of Paris, April 10, 1775, in Translations and Reprints from the Original Sources of European History, edited by James Harvey Robinson, Ph. D., with an English version by Grace Read Robinson.
[40] Gomel in Les Causes financières de la révolution française, p. 113, gives the following quotation from a contemporary writer: “Le livre de Necker sur L’administration des finances produisit autant d’effet que si l’auteur avait encore dirigé celles du royaume.... Des magistrats, des juriconsultes, des militaires, des prélats l’étudieraient, non pour devenir administrateurs, mais pour se rendre des censeurs redoubtables de l’administration.”
[40] Gomel in Les Causes financières de la révolution française, p. 113, gives the following quotation from a contemporary writer: “Necker's book on L’administration des finances had as much impact as if the author were still in charge of the kingdom's finances.... Judges, legal experts, military leaders, and clergy studied it, not to become administrators, but to become fearsome critics of the administration.”
[41] Rocquain, L’ésprit rév., 444.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Rocquain, The Spirit Rev., 444.
[45] Ibid., p. 267.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Same source., p. 267.
[49] Martin, Histoire de France, 355.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Martin, History of France, 355.
[50] R. L. Corwin, Entwicklung und Vergleichung der Erziehungslehren von John Locke und Jean Jacques Rousseau, Heidelberg, 1894; Vasille Saftu, Ein Vergleich der physichen Erziehung bei Locke und Rousseau, Bucarest, 1889; David G. Ritchie, The Social Contract, in vi. vol. of Pol. Sc. Quart.; Jaeger, Geschichte der sozialen Bewegung und des Socialismus in Franckreiche, vol. ii, 342, Berlin, 1890; Prof. J. Horning, Les idées politiques de Rousseau, in J. J. Rousseau jugé par les Génevois d’aujourd’hui, p. 135 et seq.; also M. Jules Vuy in Bulletin de L’Institut National Génevois for 1883, pp. 273-344; Rousseau et Locke, Henri Marion; J. Locke, Sa Vie et son Oeuvre d’après des documents nouveaux, Paris, 1893.
[50] R. L. Corwin, Development and Comparison of the Educational Theories of John Locke and Jean Jacques Rousseau, Heidelberg, 1894; Vasille Saftu, A Comparison of Physical Education in Locke and Rousseau, Bucharest, 1889; David G. Ritchie, The Social Contract, in vi. vol. of Pol. Sc. Quart.; Jaeger, History of the Social Movement and Socialism in France, vol. ii, 342, Berlin, 1890; Prof. J. Horning, The Political Ideas of Rousseau, in J. J. Rousseau Judged by Today's Genevans, p. 135 et seq.; also M. Jules Vuy in Bulletin de L’Institut National Genevois for 1883, pp. 273-344; Rousseau et Locke, Henri Marion; J. Locke, His Life and Work Based on New Documents, Paris, 1893.
[51] Voltaire in a letter of April 2, 1764, wrote: “Tout ce que je vois jeté les semences d’une révolution qui arrivera immanquablement, et dont je n’aurai pas le plaisir d’être témoin.... Les jeunes gens sont bien heureux: ils verront de belles choses.” Quoted in Martin, Hist. de Fr., vol. xvi, 136. Malesherbes, in speaking to the king as the organ of the parlement in 1770, said: “You hold your crown, Sire, from God alone; but you will not refuse yourself the satisfaction of believing that, for your power, you are likewise indebted to the voluntary submission of your subjects. There exist in France some inviolable rights, which belong to the nation.” Quoted from Remontrances de la Cours des Aides, 1770, by De Tocqueville; Mémoires, etc., i, 259-60. For Rousseau’s literary influence, see Joseph Texte, Jean Jacques Rousseau et les Origines du Cosmopolitisme Littéraire, Liv. ii, Paris, 1895.
[51] Voltaire wrote in a letter on April 2, 1764: “Everything I see is sowing the seeds of a revolution that will inevitably come, and I won’t have the pleasure of witnessing it.... The young people are very lucky: they will see amazing things.” Quoted in Martin, Hist. de Fr., vol. xvi, 136. Malesherbes, speaking to the king as a representative of the parlement in 1770, said: “You hold your crown, Sire, by the grace of God alone; but you won’t deny yourself the satisfaction of believing that, for your power, you are also indebted to the willing submission of your subjects. There are some inviolable rights in France that belong to the nation.” Quoted from Remontrances de la Cours des Aides, 1770, by De Tocqueville; Mémoires, etc., i, 259-60. For Rousseau’s literary influence, see Joseph Texte, Jean Jacques Rousseau et les Origines du Cosmopolitisme Littéraire, Liv. ii, Paris, 1895.
[52] A pamphlet of 1789, “Lettre d’un Curé de Picardie à un évêque sur le droit des curés d’assister aux assemblées du clergé et aux États-généraux,” etc., illustrates how the curates applied the natural rights doctrine: “Les droits des hommes réunis en société ne sont point fondés sur leur histoire mais sur leur nature. Il ne peut y avoir de raisons de perpétuer les établissements faits sans raisons, 3 p.” In vol. 84 of French Revolution Collection of the Pennsylvania Historical Society.
[52] A pamphlet from 1789, “Letter from a Curate of Picardy to a Bishop on the Right of Curates to Attend Clergy Assemblies and the Estates-General,” etc., shows how the curates applied the doctrine of natural rights: “The rights of men united in society are not based on their history but on their nature. There can be no justification for perpetuating institutions established without reason, 3 p.” In vol. 84 of French Revolution Collection of the Pennsylvania Historical Society.
[59] Quesnay said: “The security of property is the essential foundation of the economic order of society.” Maximes générales au gouvernement, Physiocrates, ii, 83, Paris, 1846. Turgot, writing of the omnipotence of the State, said: “This principle that nothing should limit the rights of society upon the individual, save the greater good of society, appears to me false and dangerous. Every man is born free, and this liberty can never be limited unless it degenerate into license, that is to say, ceases to be liberty.... It is forgotten that society is made for the individual, that is, instituted only for protecting the rights of all, by assuring the accomplishment of all mutual duties.” Quoted by M. E. Daire, Physiocrates, ii, Introd., xxi, xxii.
[59] Quesnay said: “The security of property is the essential foundation of the economic order of society.” Maximes générales au gouvernement, Physiocrates, ii, 83, Paris, 1846. Turgot, writing about the absolute power of the State, said: “This principle that nothing should limit the rights of society over the individual except for the greater good of society seems to me false and dangerous. Every person is born free, and this freedom can never be restricted unless it turns into license, meaning it stops being freedom... It's forgotten that society exists for the individual; it is established solely to protect everyone's rights by ensuring the fulfillment of all mutual duties.” Quoted by M. E. Daire, Physiocrates, ii, Introd., xxi, xxii.
[60] Ésprit des Lois, Liv. xi.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Spirit of the Laws, Book 11.
[61] Saint Girons, Droit public français, treats thoroughly the question of separation of powers. Mirabeau in referring to the separation of powers, in a speech delivered in the Assembly July 16, 1789, pointed out the general misapprehension of this theory: “Nous aurons bientôt occasion d’examiner cette théorie des trois pouvoirs, laquelle exactement analysée montrera peut être la facilité de l’ésprit humain à prendre des mots pour des choses, des formules pour des arguments et à se routiner vers un certain ordre d’idées sans revenir jamais à examiner l’intelligible définition qu’il a prise pour un axiome.” Arch. Parl., VIII, 243.
[61] Saint Girons, Droit public français, thoroughly discusses the question of the separation of powers. Mirabeau, in a speech delivered in the Assembly on July 16, 1789, highlighted the common misunderstanding of this theory: “We'll soon have a chance to examine this theory of the three powers, which, when analyzed closely, may reveal how easily the human mind attaches words to concepts, formulas to arguments, and tends to stick to a certain order of ideas without ever going back to examine the clear definition it has taken as an axiom.” Arch. Parl., VIII, 243.
[64] Dictionnaire Nouvelle, Parlements.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ New Dictionary, Parliaments.
[65] T. i, 78, 266.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ T. i, 78, 266.
[66] Martin, Histoire de France, xi, 543.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Martin, History of France, xi, 543.
[67] These two decrees, one 1667, the other 1673, are given in substance in Jules Flammermont, Remontrances, Intro. i and ii. The second was the more sweeping: “Dès que les gens du Roi auraient reçu les ordonnances, édits, déclarations ou lettres patents, ils devraient dorénavant les présenter tout de suite aux cours toutes chambres assemblées, qui auraient à les enregistrer purement et simplement sans aucune modification, restriction, ni autres clauses qui en pussent surseoir ou empêcher la pleine et entière exécution. Dans le cas où les cours auraient des remontrances à présenter elles ne pourraient plus le faire qu’après que l’arrêt d’enregistrement aurait été donné et séparément rédigé. Mais que le Roi donnôit suite ou non à ces remontrances, qui devaient être dressées dans la huitaine après l’enregistrement, les cours ne devaient pas faire d’itératives remontrances.”
[67] These two decrees, one from 1667 and the other from 1673, are summarized in Jules Flammermont's Remontrances, Intro. i and ii. The second decree was more comprehensive: “As soon as the royal officials received the ordinances, edicts, declarations, or letters patent, they were required to present them immediately to the assembled courts, which had to register them exactly as they were, without any modifications, restrictions, or other clauses that could delay or prevent their full and complete execution. If the courts had any objections to raise, they could only do so after the registration order had been issued and separately drafted. However, whether the King responded to these objections or not, which were to be submitted within a week after registration, the courts were not to make repeated objections.”
[68] Flammermont, Remontrances, 95.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Flammermont, Remontrances, 95.
[69] Cited in Prof. J. H. Robinson’s very suggestive article, The Tennis Court Oath (Political Science Quarterly, Sept., 1895); from the Itératives Remontrances sur la Refonte des Monnaies, July 26, 1718, Flammermont’s Remontrances, 94, 95.
[69] Cited in Prof. J. H. Robinson’s insightful article, The Tennis Court Oath (Political Science Quarterly, Sept., 1895); from the Itératives Remontrances sur la Refonte des Monnaies, July 26, 1718, Flammermont’s Remontrances, 94, 95.
[73] Ibid., 117.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Same source., 117.
[74] Barbier has left record of how intimate was the sympathy of the people with the Parlement in the struggle over Jansenism: “Le bonne Ville de Paris est janséniste de la tête aux pieds.... Tous degrés de Paris, hommes, femmes, petites enfants, tiennent pour cette doctrine, sans savoir la matière, sans rien entendre à ces distinctions et interprétations, par haine contre Rome et les jésuites, tout ce monde est entêté comme un diable. Les femmes, femmelettes et jusqu’aux femmes de chambre s’y feraient hocher.” Cited in Aubertin, l’Ésprit public au XVIII siècle, 263, 264.
[74] Barbier has recorded how deeply the people connected with the Parlement during the struggle over Jansenism: “The good city of Paris is Jansenist from head to toe.... All levels of Paris, men, women, and little children support this doctrine, without knowing the details, without understanding these distinctions and interpretations, out of hatred for Rome and the Jesuits; everyone is stubborn as a devil. Women, girls, and even maids would be swayed by it.” Cited in Aubertin, l’Ésprit public au XVIII siècle, 263, 264.
[75] “Votre parlement s’est toujours fait gloire de leur donner l’exemple de l’obéissance. Il vous a toujours prouvé par sa conduite que, si l’obéissance due à la Majesté du Roi était perdue, elle se retrouverait dans sa cour de parlement. Mais s’il y a des occasions où son attachement inviolable aux lois et au bien public semble ne pouvoir pas s’allier avec une obéissance sans bornes, alors il serait criminel envers vous même et envers l’État d’oublier ce que lui disait en 1567 un chancelier de France: Vous avez juré de garder tous les communs éléments du Roi, bien de garder les ordonnances qui sont ses vrais commandements. Ou ce qu’il disait lui-même en 1604 au Souverain: Si c’est désobéissance de bien servir, le Parlement fait ordinairement cette faute, et quand il se trouve conflit entre la puissance absolue du Roi et le bien de son service, il juge l’un préférable à l’autre, non par désobéissance, mais pour son devoir, à la décharge de sa conscience.” Grandes Remontrances, April 9, 1753; Flammermont, Remontrances, 529.
[75] “Your parliament has always prided itself on setting an example of obedience. It has consistently shown through its actions that if the obedience owed to the Majesty of the King is lost, it can be found in its parliamentary court. However, if there are times when its unwavering commitment to the laws and the public good seems incompatible with limitless obedience, then it would be wrong for it to forget what a chancellor of France said in 1567: You have sworn to uphold all the common rights of the King, and to uphold the ordinances which are his true commands. Or what he himself said in 1604 to the Sovereign: If it’s disobedience to serve well, the Parliament usually commits that fault, and when there’s a conflict between the absolute power of the King and the good of his service, it finds one preferable to the other, not out of disobedience, but out of duty, for the sake of its conscience.” Grandes Remontrances, April 9, 1753; Flammermont, Remontrances, 529.
[76] Flammermont, Le Chancelier Maupeou, 269.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Flammermont, Chancellor Maupeou, 269.
[78] Aubertin, 391, 392: Voltaire complained in the ’60’s of being tired of people, “qui gouvernaient les États du fond de leurs greniers.” Rocquain, L’ésprit rév., 244.
[78] Aubertin, 391, 392: Voltaire complained in the ’60s about being tired of people, “who governed the states from the confines of their attics.” Rocquain, L’ésprit rév., 244.
[79] Gomel, 334.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Gomel, 334.
[80] The calling of the États généraux had been suggested by la Rochefoucauld, 1774; by d’Espremenil, 1775, and in remonstrances of the cour des aides of Paris and the Parlement of Besançon 1775 and 1781, and in the Assembly of Notables by Lafayette in 1787.
[80] The idea of calling the États généraux was proposed by la Rochefoucauld in 1774; by d’Espremenil in 1775, and in petitions from the cour des aides of Paris and the Parlement of Besançon in 1775 and 1781, as well as in the Assembly of Notables by Lafayette in 1787.
[81] The contents of the cahiers are difficult to tabulate, owing to their various modes of expression. The following summary will, however, give an approximate idea of their import upon constitutional questions: Of 448 primary and secondary cahiers examined, 305 demanded or implied a constitution; 194, the monarchy; 401, periodic États généraux; 372, granting of taxes by the États généraux; 269, legislation by the États généraux; 331, ministerial responsibility; and 366, proportional taxation.
[81] The contents of the cahiers are hard to categorize because of their different styles of expression. However, the following summary will give a rough idea of their relevance to constitutional issues: Of the 448 primary and secondary cahiers analyzed, 305 called for or suggested a constitution; 194, the monarchy; 401, regular États généraux; 372, tax approval by the États généraux; 269, legislation by the États généraux; 331, accountability for ministers; and 366, fair taxation.
[82] The cahier of the nobility of the bailliage of Aumont asked: “Que l’ancienne constitution française est monarchique, que les lois fondamentales du royaume subsisteront dans leur intégrité et qu’elles ne pourront être changées par les députés aux États généraux, Que la formation des États généraux fait partie de la constitution.”... Arch. Parl., i, 766. Somewhat similar views are found in the cahiers of the clergy of Lectoure, Ibid., ii, 66; of the clergy of Auten, ii, 100; of the clergy of Aval, ii, 137; of the clergy of Carcassonne, ii, 257; of the clergy of Blois, ii, 376; of the nobility of Guyenne, ii, 394; of the clergy of Châlons-sur-Marne, ii, 582; of the clergy of Clermont-Ferrand, ii, 766; of the third estate of Comte de Comminges, iii, 26; of the nobility of Constances, iii, 52; of the clergy of Etampes, iii, 279; of the nobility of Libourne, iii, 506; of the nobility of Timoux, iii, 577; of the nobility of Mâcon, iii, 623; of the nobility of Gevaudan, iii, 754; of the third estate of the parish of Ferrières en Brie, iv, 545; of the nobility of Provins and Monterau, v, 448; of the nobility of Touraine, vi, 39; of the clergy of Vermandois, vi, 134; of the clergy of Villers-Catterels, vi, 187; of the clergy of Vitry le François, vi, 207; of the nobility of Besançon, vi, 516. Some wished to re-establish in more definite terms the old constitution. The cahier of the clergy of Auxerre asked: “Que les États généraux s’occuperont d’abord de reconnaître, conserver, fixer irrévocablement, et rendre publiques les lois constitutionnelles de la monarchie, les droits du Roi et ceux de la nation,” ii, 111. Of similar import were the cahiers of the clergy of Argenois, i, 675; of the third estate of Albert, i, 704; of the third estate of Alençon, i, 716; of the third estate of Exemes, i, 727; of the nobility of Pont-à-Mousson, ii, 229; of the nobility of Castres, ii, 566; of the clergy of Caux, ii, 573; of the nobility of Caux, ii, 575; of the nobility of Châlons-sur-Saône, ii, 604; of the clergy of Châteauneuf en Thimerais, ii, 639; of the nobility of Launes, iii, 94; of the nobility of Évreux, iii, 295; of the third estate of Province of Forez, iii, 385; of the clergy of Pays de Labourt, iii, 424; of the nobility of Montagres, iv, 20; of the Parish of Clermont-Mendon, iv, 440; of the third estate of Agenois, i, 687. A smaller number of the cahiers asked for a new constitution. The cahier of the third estate of Paris intra muros presented a model constitution, essentially similar to the one actually framed, v, 581. The Parish of Toussus-le-Noble, of Paris, hors des murs, instructed that: Les députés demanderont une nouvelle constitution nationale, la suppression de toutes les lois, qui, jusqu’à présent, ont été considérées constitutionnelles, comme illégalement établies et n’ayant pas reçu l’approbation de la nation, v, 138. The third estate of Mont de Morsan said: Il est temps qu’on pose les règles fixes, et qu’on assure à la France une Constitution qui garantisse les droits naturels et imprescriptibles des hommes, iv, 34. The third estate of Etampes, after referring to the abuses, said: Nos premiers voeux doivent naturellement se porter sur ce qui doit former à l’avenir la constitution du royaume. Le anciens monuments nous offrent si peu de conformité et de certitude, que nous devons profiter des lumières actuelles pour opérer un plus grand bien, iii, 283. The nobility of Blois said: Le malheur de la France vient de ce qu’elle n’a jamais eu de constitution fixe, ii, 379.
[82] The cahier from the nobility of the Aumont bailliage stated: “The old French constitution is monarchical, that the fundamental laws of the kingdom will remain intact and cannot be changed by the deputies at the Estates General. The formation of the Estates General is part of the constitution.”... Arch. Parl., i, 766. Similar views can be found in the cahiers of the clergy from Lectoure, Ibid., ii, 66; the clergy from Auten, ii, 100; the clergy from Aval, ii, 137; the clergy from Carcassonne, ii, 257; the clergy from Blois, ii, 376; the nobility from Guyenne, ii, 394; the clergy from Châlons-sur-Marne, ii, 582; the clergy from Clermont-Ferrand, ii, 766; the third estate of Comte de Comminges, iii, 26; the nobility from Constances, iii, 52; the clergy from Etampes, iii, 279; the nobility from Libourne, iii, 506; the nobility from Timoux, iii, 577; the nobility from Mâcon, iii, 623; the nobility from Gevaudan, iii, 754; the third estate from the parish of Ferrières en Brie, iv, 545; the nobility from Provins and Monterau, v, 448; the nobility from Touraine, vi, 39; the clergy from Vermandois, vi, 134; the clergy from Villers-Catterels, vi, 187; the clergy from Vitry le François, vi, 207; the nobility from Besançon, vi, 516. Some wished to re-establish the old constitution in clearer terms. The cahier of the clergy from Auxerre requested: “That the Estates General will first focus on recognizing, preserving, setting firm and public the constitutional laws of the monarchy, the rights of the King, and those of the nation,” ii, 111. Similar sentiments were expressed in the cahiers of the clergy from Argenois, i, 675; the third estate from Albert, i, 704; the third estate from Alençon, i, 716; the third estate from Exemes, i, 727; the nobility from Pont-à-Mousson, ii, 229; the nobility from Castres, ii, 566; the clergy from Caux, ii, 573; the nobility from Caux, ii, 575; the nobility from Châlons-sur-Saône, ii, 604; the clergy from Châteauneuf en Thimerais, ii, 639; the nobility from Launes, iii, 94; the nobility from Évreux, iii, 295; the third estate from the Province of Forez, iii, 385; the clergy from Pays de Labourt, iii, 424; the nobility from Montagres, iv, 20; the Parish of Clermont-Mendon, iv, 440; the third estate from Agenois, i, 687. A smaller number of the cahiers called for a new constitution. The cahier of the third estate from Paris intra muros proposed a model constitution, essentially similar to the one ultimately framed, v, 581. The Parish of Toussus-le-Noble, from Paris, hors des murs, instructed that: The deputies would demand a new national constitution, the elimination of all laws that have been previously deemed constitutional, as illegally established and lacking the nation’s approval, v, 138. The third estate of Mont de Morsan stated: It is time to set fixed rules and ensure a Constitution for France that guarantees the natural and inalienable rights of individuals, iv, 34. The third estate of Etampes, after referring to the abuses, said: Our initial wishes should naturally be directed towards what will form the future constitution of the kingdom. The ancient monuments offer so little conformity and certainty that we must take advantage of current insights to achieve a greater good, iii, 283. The nobility from Blois remarked: France's misfortune stems from never having had a fixed constitution, ii, 379.
[84] Cited in Rocquain, L’Ésprit, 457.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Cited in Rocquain, *L’Ésprit*, 457.
[85] Qu’est-ce que donc qu’une Constitution, si ce n’est l’ordre, la distribution des deux grands pouvoirs politiques et de leur séparation dans différentes mains, et leur exercise ou différentes formes: le tout sanctionné et constitué, c’est à dire statué avec la nation assemblée, représentant l’également la volonté générale, et voulant librement pour l’intérêt commun? Si l’on recherche en France ces deux pouvoirs, on les trouve, par le fait, réunis dans la même main, sans qu’on puisse voir l’apparence d’un droit contraire qu’en remontant vers les âges ténébreux de l’ignorance et de la servitude. Or la collection de ces pouvoirs ne peut former que l’autorité arbitraire d’un despote; ce qui exclut toute idée de Lois fondamentales et constitutionnelles: aussi n’en trouve-t-on en assumé. Donc point de Constitution, Vol. 87 of Fr. Rev. Col. of Penn. Hist. Soc., 114, 115.
[85] What is a Constitution if not the organization, distribution of the two main political powers, their separation into different hands, and their exercise in various forms: all of it endorsed and established, meaning agreed upon with the nation assembled, representing the general will, and wanting freely for the common good? If we look for these two powers in France, we find them, in fact, united in the same hands, without any appearance of a contrary right except when we look back to the dark ages of ignorance and servitude. Thus, the accumulation of these powers can only create the arbitrary authority of a despot; this excludes any idea of fundamental and constitutional laws: hence, they are not found in practice. Therefore, no Constitution, Vol. 87 of Fr. Rev. Col. of Penn. Hist. Soc., 114, 115.
[86] Arch. Parl., i, 543, 544.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Arch. Parl., vol. 1, pp. 543, 544.
[87] Hist. Parl., i, 445.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Hist. Parl., vol. 1, p. 445.
[88] He said of Mirabeau: “Nous n’avons l’un et l’autre entrevu rien de mieux pour la France qu’un gouvernement monarchique constitutionnel. De tous les rois, Louis XVI. était le plus propre à résoudre le problème.... Il croyait le gouvernement constitutionnel plus convenable, et il le désirait; et je puis le dire avec autant de certitude que conviction, la reine partageait à cet égard les opinions et les penchants de Louis XVI.; les matériaux qui sont dans mon portefeuille rendent ces assertions incontestables.” Correspondence entre Mirabeau et La Marck, i, 67, 95.
[88] He said of Mirabeau: “Neither of us has seen anything better for France than a constitutional monarchy. Among all the kings, Louis XVI was the most suited to solve the problem.... He believed that a constitutional government was more appropriate, and he wanted it; I can say this with as much certainty as conviction: the queen shared Louis XVI's views and inclinations on this matter; the materials in my portfolio make these claims indisputable.” Correspondence between Mirabeau and La Marck, i, 67, 95.
[89] Arch. Parl., viii, 55.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Arch. Parl., vol. viii, 55.
[90] Ibid., 113.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Same source., 113.
[91] Ibid., 127.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Same source., 127.
[92] Arch. Parl., viii, 138.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Arch. Parl., vol. viii, 138.
[93] D’Argenson in 1752 said: “Quant à moi je tiens pour l’avènement du second article et même du républicanisme.” He meant Republicanism not in the modern sense, but in the sense of a monarchy with democratic local institutions. Aubertin, L’Ésprit public, 278, 279. Even the Ésprit des Lois gave some sanction to a Republic as an ideal form of government when it recognized virtue as the temper of society required for this form of government. Voltaire, friend of the monarchy and critic of Rousseau as he was, wrote: “Le plus tolérable des gouvernements est le républicain, parce-que c’est celui qui rapproche le plus les hommes de l’égalité naturelle.” He also compared the frequency of crimes under a monarchy with their infrequency under republics. Martin, Histoire de France, xvi, 136. Mably held that France should pass by degrees from a monarchy to a republic. Ibid., 149 et seq., Cerutti, the coadjutor of Mirabeau at a later date, had published a book on Republics. This book had been generally attributed to Rousseau. Dictionnaire Universelle.
[93] D’Argenson in 1752 said: “As for me, I support the rise of the second article and even republicanism.” He meant republicanism not in the modern sense, but as a monarchy with democratic local institutions. Aubertin, L’Ésprit public, 278, 279. Even the Ésprit des Lois endorsed a Republic as an ideal form of government by recognizing virtue as the quality of society needed for this type of government. Voltaire, a supporter of the monarchy and critic of Rousseau, wrote: “The most tolerable form of government is republican, because it brings people closer to natural equality.” He also compared the frequency of crimes under a monarchy to their rarity under republics. Martin, Histoire de France, xvi, 136. Mably believed that France should gradually transition from a monarchy to a republic. Ibid., 149 et seq., Cerutti, Mirabeau’s associate later on, published a book on Republics. This book was often mistakenly attributed to Rousseau. Dictionnaire Universelle.
[94] Arch. Parl., v, 282.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Arch. Parl., vol. 5, p. 282.
[95] The cahier of the district of Abbey Saint Germain des Près said: Il sera arrêté qu’à la nation assemblée, réunie au Roi, appartient le droit de faire les lois de royaume, Arch. Parl., v, 306; that of Saint Gervais: Le pouvoir législatif appartient conjointement au Roi et à la nation.... Le pouvoir exécutif appartient au Roi, comme chef suprême et premier magistrat de la nation, Ibid., 308; that of Saint Louis de-la-Culture: Qu’il soit reconnu que l’état est monarchique, que la couronne est héréditaire en ligne masculine, etc., Ibid., 311; that of Theatins: Le Roi en (of the army) aura la discipline et le commandement général, Ibid., 316; that of Sorbonne: that the States-General and the king jointly make the laws; that of Filles de Saint Thomas: that the nation and the king make the laws, and that the executive power be guaranteed to the king and to the reigning family without restriction or division; that of Bonne Nouvelle: that the laws should be made by the States-General and announced by the king; that of Saint Joseph Quartier des Halles: that laws be made by the nation and king jointly; that of Sainte Elizabeth: that the nation make the laws and the king sanction them; that of Enfants Rouges: that the laws be made by the nation and the king jointly; that of Blancs Manteaux: that France should have an hereditary monarchy in the male line of the reigning house, laws made by the nation and sanctioned by the king, and that the executive power should belong to the monarch; that of Capucins du Marais: that the laws be made by the nation and the king jointly; that of Minimes de la Place Royale: that the laws be made jointly by the nation and the king. Chassin, Les Élection et Cahiers de Paris, ii, ch. xvi-xviii.
[95] The report from the district of Abbey Saint Germain des Près stated: It shall be agreed that the power to create the laws of the realm belongs to the assembled nation, gathered with the King, Arch. Parl., v, 306; that of Saint Gervais: The legislative power belongs jointly to the King and the nation.... The executive power belongs to the King as the supreme leader and chief magistrate of the nation, Ibid., 308; that of Saint Louis de-la-Culture: It should be acknowledged that the state is monarchical, that the crown is hereditary in the male line, etc., Ibid., 311; that of Theatins: The King has the discipline and overall command of the army, Ibid., 316; that of Sorbonne: that the States-General and the King together make the laws; that of Filles de Saint Thomas: that the nation and the King make the laws, and that the executive power be guaranteed to the King and the reigning family with no restrictions or divisions; that of Bonne Nouvelle: that the laws should be made by the States-General and announced by the King; that of Saint Joseph Quartier des Halles: that laws be made jointly by the nation and the King; that of Sainte Elizabeth: that the nation make the laws and the King approve them; that of Enfants Rouges: that the laws be made by the nation and the King together; that of Blancs Manteaux: that France should have a hereditary monarchy in the male line of the ruling house, laws made by the nation and approved by the King, and that the executive power should belong to the monarch; that of Capucins du Marais: that the laws be made jointly by the nation and the King; that of Minimes de la Place Royale: that the laws be made together by the nation and the King. Chassin, Les Élection et Cahiers de Paris, ii, ch. xvi-xviii.
[96] Chassin, Les Élections et Cahiers, i, 453.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Chassin, Election and Notebooks, p. 453.
[97] Arch. Parl., viii. 350.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Arch. Parl., vol. 8, p. 350.
[99] Arch. Parl., viii, 505.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Arch. Parl., vol. viii, 505.
[100] Ibid., 642.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Same source, 642.
[101] Ibid., ix, 26.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Same source., ix, 26.
[102] Arch Parl., xxviii, 336-338.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Arch Parl., 28, 336-338.
[104] Arch. Parl., xxviii, 377.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Arch. Parl., 28, 377.
[105] Ibid., xxx, 635, 636.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Same source., xxx, 635, 636.
[106] “Convaincue que le gouvernement qui convient le mieux aux prérogatives respectables du trône avec les droits inaliénables du peuple, elle a donné à l’État une constitution qui garantit également et la royauté et la liberté nationale.... Et vous, Sire, déjà vous avez presque tout fait. Votre Majesté a fini la Révolution par Son acceptation si loyale et si franche de la Constitution. Elle a porté au dehors le découragement, ramené au dedans la confiance, rétabli par elle le principal nerf du gouvernement et préparé l’utile activité de l’administration.” Arch. Parl., xxxi 688, 689.
[106] “Convinced that the government best suited to the rightful prerogatives of the throne aligns with the inalienable rights of the people, she provided the state with a constitution that equally guarantees both the monarchy and national freedom.... And you, Sire, you have already accomplished almost everything. Your Majesty concluded the Revolution with your loyal and honest acceptance of the Constitution. You have conveyed discouragement outward, restored confidence inward, reestablished the key functions of the government, and prepared for the effective operation of the administration.” Arch. Parl., xxxi 688, 689.
[107] It is noteworthy that the French had not followed the history of their own development. “Pendant toute la durée de la monarchie, tandis que le peuple n’apprenait presque rien les hautes classes, en général, apprenaient mal. Leur ignorance de l’histoire nationale explique pourquoi, au moment de la Révolution, on ne put se rendre un compte exact des faits sociaux et politiques que nous léguait l’ancien régime, pourquoi on détruisit pêle-mêle ce qu’il y avait de bon et de mauvais dans les institutions du passé, pourquoi, lorsqu’il s’agit de constituer une nation moderne, le nation française, on n’eut à la bouche que des exemples empruntés à l’antiquité, à Athènes, à Sparte, à Rome. Cette instruction incomplète, cette fausse éducation classique était, en somme, une médiocre préparation au métier de législateurs, si nouveau pour nos pères de la Révolution.” M. Alfred Rambaud, Histoire de la Civilisation française, ii, 280. An English lady who was traveling in France writes in August, 1792: “Their studies are chiefly confined to Rollin and Plutarch, the deistical works of Voltaire and the visionary politics of Jean Jacques. Hence they amuse their hearers with allusions to Cæsar and Lycurgus, the Rubicon and Thermopylæ. Hence they pretend to be too enlightened for belief, and despise all governments not founded on the contrat social or the profession de foi.... They talk familiarly of Sparta and Lacedemon.” A Residence in France during 1792-95, London, 1797.
[107] It's important to note that the French had not kept up with their own history. “Throughout the monarchy, while the people learned almost nothing, the upper classes generally learned poorly. Their ignorance of national history explains why, at the time of the Revolution, they couldn’t accurately grasp the social and political realities left by the old regime, why they indiscriminately destroyed both the good and bad aspects of past institutions, and why, when it came to forming a modern nation, the French nation could only speak of examples borrowed from antiquity, such as Athens, Sparta, and Rome. This incomplete education, this flawed classical training was, ultimately, a mediocre preparation for the role of legislators, which was so new for our revolutionary forefathers.” M. Alfred Rambaud, Histoire de la Civilisation française, ii, 280. An English lady traveling in France writes in August 1792: “Their studies are mainly focused on Rollin and Plutarch, the deistical works of Voltaire, and the fanciful politics of Jean Jacques. That's why they entertain their listeners with references to Cæsar and Lycurgus, the Rubicon and Thermopylæ. That's why they claim to be too enlightened to believe, and look down on any governments not based on the contrat social or the profession de foi... They casually discuss Sparta and Lacedemon.” A Residence in France during 1792-95, London, 1797.
[110] Camille Desmoulins’ La France Libre contained three striking utterances. “For forty years philosophy had undermined all the parts of the foundations of despotism; and as Rome before Cæsar was already enslaved by its vices, France before Necker was already freed by its intelligence,” 56. In various parts of this article of 1789 he speaks of a republic as being the best suited to France. “Before the Royal Sitting I regarded Louis XVI. with admiration, for he had some virtues, as he walked not at all in the steps of his fathers, was not at all a despot, and had convoked the States-General. While in the province I read in the gazette his beautiful speech: ‘What does it matter that my authority suffer provided my people should be happy?’ We have, I said to myself, a greater king than the Trojans, the Marcus Aurelius, the Antonines, who did not at all limit their power. Personally I loved Louis XVI.; but the monarchy was not less odious,” 60-61. “I declare then boldly for democracy,” 64.
[110] Camille Desmoulins’ La France Libre had three powerful statements. “For forty years, philosophy has chipped away at the foundations of despotism; just as Rome was already trapped by its vices before Cæsar, France was already liberated by its intellect before Necker,” 56. In different sections of this 1789 article, he talks about a republic being the best fit for France. “Before the Royal Sitting, I admired Louis XVI. because he had some virtues; he didn’t follow in his ancestors' footsteps, wasn't a despot at all, and had called the States-General. While in the province, I read in the gazette his beautiful speech: ‘What does it matter if my authority suffers as long as my people are happy?’ I thought to myself that we have a greater king than the Trojans, a Marcus Aurelius, the Antonines, who didn’t restrict their power at all. Personally, I liked Louis XVI.; but the monarchy was still detestable,” 60-61. “I boldly declare for democracy,” 64.
[112] Ibid., iii, 433.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Same source., iii, 433.
[113] Hist. Gén., viii, 104.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Hist. Gén., vol. viii, 104.
[115] Hist. Parl., x, 416-418. It seems to have been the Cordeliers who planned for the public signing of the petition upon the altar of the country, July 17, 1791, on the Champs de Mars. This petition prayed the Assembly to accept the abdication of the king, and to convoke a new constituent power for the trial of the guilty and for the replacing and organization of a new executive power. Hist. Gén., viii, 100; Hist. Parl., xi, 115. Six thousand petitioners had signed this instrument.
[115] Hist. Parl., x, 416-418. It appears that the Cordeliers organized the public signing of the petition at the country's altar on July 17, 1791, at the Champs de Mars. This petition requested the Assembly to accept the king's abdication and to assemble a new constituent body to try the guilty and establish a new executive power. Hist. Gén., viii, 100; Hist. Parl., xi, 115. Six thousand people signed this document.
[116] Henry Morse Stephens, The French Revolution, i, 96 et seq. The number of February 4, 1790, contained these words: “Il est impossible dans de pareils moments de se livrer à aucunes réflexions; il faut être tout à sentir. Nous dirons donc seulement et du fond du coeur: Puisse cette journée étouffer la discorde qui régnoit entre les citoyens, et ramener à la nation ceux qui ne vouloient pas reconnoitre ses droits: Et nous, patriotes, faisons au bien de la paix tous les sacrifices qui peuvent s’allier avec la liberté, soyons dignes d’être libres, soyons dignes d’être les sujets d’un tel roi.” Rév. de Paris, Vol. 3, No. 31. In referring to a company about to go to Ohio, the editor would dissuade them by saying: “Nous allons en jouir par une constitution plus heureusement conçue que celle des États-Unis.” Vol. 3, No. 32. In No. 52 of July, 1790, former kings are calumniated and Louis XVI. was praised. The last number of 1790 paid its respects to the king in laudable terms. “Louis tu as pris, comme par instinct, le parti le plus sage. Tu as cessé d’être l’oint du Seigneur, pour devenir le fils aîné de la patrie. Notre mère commune t’a confirmé dans ta place, à la tête de la grande famille. Dis n’est il pas plus doux de présider des frères, que de fouler aux pieds des sujets?” No. 77.
[116] Henry Morse Stephens, The French Revolution, i, 96 et seq. The number of February 4, 1790, contained these words: “It is impossible in such moments to engage in any reflections; one must feel entirely. So we will simply say from the bottom of our hearts: May this day put an end to the discord that reigns among the citizens, and bring back to the nation those who refused to recognize its rights: And we, patriots, will make all the sacrifices for the sake of peace that can coexist with freedom, let us be worthy of being free, let us be worthy of being subjects of such a king.” Rév. de Paris, Vol. 3, No. 31. When referring to a group about to go to Ohio, the editor would try to dissuade them by saying: “We are going to enjoy it through a constitution better designed than that of the United States.” Vol. 3, No. 32. In No. 52 of July, 1790, former kings were slandered and Louis XVI was praised. The last issue of 1790 paid its respects to the king in commendable terms. “Louis, you have instinctively chosen the wisest course. You have ceased to be the anointed of the Lord, to become the elder son of the nation. Our common mother has confirmed you in your position, at the head of the great family. Isn’t it sweeter to preside over brothers, than to trample on subjects?” No. 77.
[117] He died September, 1790.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ He died in September 1790.
[118] March 26-April 2.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ March 26-April 2.
[119] I. La nation ne reconnoît pour chef suprême de l’empire que le président de son assemblée représentative et permanente. II. On ne pourra être élu président avant sa cinquantième année, ni pour plus d’un mois, ni plus d’une fois en sa vie.... XIX. La nation supprime, abolit et annulle à jamais les titres de roi, de reine, de prince du sang royal, ces mots cesseront d’avoir un sens dans la langue française.... XXI. A l’imitation de la pâque des Hébreux, il sera instituté une fête commémorative qui tombera le premier juin, jour de l’expulsion des Tarquins à Rome, et consacrée à célébrer l’abolition de la royauté le plus grand des fléaux dont l’espèce humaine ait été la victime. No. 90.
[119] I. The nation recognizes only the president of its representative and permanent assembly as the supreme leader of the empire. II. No one can be elected president before turning fifty, nor for more than one month, nor more than once in their lifetime.... XIX. The nation abolishes and permanently nullifies the titles of king, queen, and royal prince; these words will cease to have meaning in the French language.... XXI. Following the example of the Passover of the Hebrews, there will be an established commemorative festival on June 1st, the day of the Tarquin expulsion in Rome, dedicated to celebrating the abolition of royalty, the greatest scourge to which humanity has ever fallen victim. No. 90.
[120] May 7-14, 1791
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ May 7-14, 1791
[121] The picture which the editor gives of the feeling in Paris after the flight of Louis shows him to be an extreme radical, and that the people of the city were greatly aroused by the escape. “L’opinion dominante était une antipathie pour les rois, un mépris pour la personne de Louis XVI., qui se manifestérent jusque dans les plus petits détails. A la Grève, on fit tomber en morceaux le buste de Louis XVI., qu’éclairait la célèbre lanterne, l’effroi des ennemis de la révolution. Quand donc le peuple se fera t-il justice de tous ces rois de bronze, monuments de notre idôlatrie? Rue Saint-Honoré, on exigea d’un marchand le sacrifice d’une tête de plâtre, à la ressemblance de Louis XVI.; dans un autre magasin, on se contenta de lui poser sur les yeux un bandeau de papier; les noms de roi, reine, royale, Bourbon, Louis, cour, monsieur, frère du roi furent effacés par tout où on les trouva écrits sur tous les tableaux et enseignes des magasins et des boutiques. Le Palais royal est aujourd’hui le Palais d’Orléans. Les couronnes peintes furent même proscrites, et le jour de la Fête-Dieu on les couvrit d’un voile sur les tapisseries où elles se trouvoient, afin de ne point souiller par leur aspect la sainteté de le procession.... Un piquet de cinquante lances fit des patrouilles jusque dans les Tuileries, portant pour bannière un écriteau, avec cette inscription:
[121] The picture the editor paints of the mood in Paris after Louis's escape shows him to be a hardcore radical, and that the citizens were deeply stirred by the event. “The prevailing opinion was a strong dislike for kings, a disdain for Louis XVI himself, which was evident even in the smallest details. At Grève, the bust of Louis XVI, illuminated by the famous lantern, was shattered, striking fear into the hearts of the enemies of the revolution. When will the people take justice into their own hands against all these bronze kings, monuments of our idolatry? On Rue Saint-Honoré, a merchant was demanded to sacrifice a plaster head resembling Louis XVI; in another shop, they simply placed a paper blindfold over its eyes; the names of king, queen, royal, Bourbon, Louis, court, mister, king’s brother were erased wherever they were found written on all the paintings and signs of shops and boutiques. The Royal Palace is now the Orléans Palace. Even painted crowns were banned, and on the day of the Feast of Corpus Christi, they were covered with a veil on the tapestries where they were depicted, so as not to tarnish the sanctity of the procession.... A squad of fifty spears patrolled all the way to the Tuileries, carrying a banner with this inscription:
[122] “Il ne nous faut qu’un seul chef du pouvoir exécutif, mais un chef à temps, un chef impuissant par lui même, qui n’ait d’autorité que celle de la loi. Il est temps, il est plus que temps de frapper un grand coup: que la tête de Louis tombe; ou bien qu’on le dédaigne, elle est assez méprisable; que le trône et tous les pompeux hochets de la royauté soient livrés aux flammes; que l’assemblée nationale de la monarchie fasse place au sénat de la république; que celui-ci adresse un manifesta à tous les tyrans de l’Europe; qu’il invite tous les peuples à la liberté; qu’à la première hostilité d’immenses légions de nos nouveaux républicains aillent exterminer tous les despotes, et planter le drapeau de la liberté jusque dans le fond de l’Allemagne; nous serons libres alors, nous préviendrons la guerre qu’on vent apporter chez nous, et la France aura la gloire, inconnue jusqu’ à ce jour, devoir non pas conquis l’Europe à la France, mais conquis l’univers à la liberté, en le purgeant des rois, empereurs, et tyrans de touts espèces.” No. 103.
[122] “We need just one leader of the executive power, but a temporary leader, a leader who has no power on his own, who only has authority through the law. It’s time, it’s more than time to take decisive action: let Louis's head fall; or let’s ignore him, he’s already contemptible enough; let the throne and all the extravagant trappings of royalty be set ablaze; let the national assembly of the monarchy make way for the senate of the republic; let this senate issue a manifesto to all the tyrants of Europe; let it invite all peoples to freedom; and at the first sign of hostility, let vast legions of our new republicans go and eliminate all despots, planting the flag of liberty deep into Germany; only then will we be free, we will prevent the war they want to bring to our shores, and France will achieve the glory, unknown until now, of not just conquering Europe for France, but conquering the world for freedom, purging it of kings, emperors, and tyrants of all kinds.” No. 103.
[123] T. 8, 606 et seq.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ T. 8, 606 et seq.
[124] In No. 115, September 17-24, reference was made to the prize offered by the Jacobin Club for an Almanac to be distributed among the people teaching the advantages of the constitution, but the editor suggests that they had better offer a prize for an almanac revealing the defects of the constitution.
[124] In No. 115, September 17-24, it was mentioned that the Jacobin Club was offering a prize for an Almanac to be shared with the public that would highlight the benefits of the constitution, but the editor proposes that they should instead offer a prize for an almanac that points out the flaws in the constitution.
[125] “Il n’est pas besoin d’examiner l’abolition de la royauté. Le voeu de la nation sans doute, est assez prononcé; sans doute ceux-mêmes qui prétendaient que les adresses de tous les départements sur la déchéance ne suffisoient pas à l’assemblée nationale avant le 10 août, sont à présent convaincus que les Français ne veulent ni d’un roi de leur nation, ni d’un étranger.” Noting the weakness in the American constitution which made it possible for one man, Washington or Adams, to acquire too great power, the article urged that the French should imitate no country, but should work out their own plan. However, this same number told of the first meeting of the Convention and of the abolition of the monarchy.
[125] “There’s no need to discuss the abolition of the monarchy. The wish of the nation, without a doubt, is clear; surely even those who argued that the addresses from all the departments regarding the king’s removal weren’t enough for the national assembly before August 10th are now convinced that the French do not want either a king from their nation or a foreign one.” Highlighting the flaws in the American constitution that allowed one person, whether Washington or Adams, to gain too much power, the article encouraged the French to avoid copying any other country and instead create their own plan. However, this edition also reported on the first meeting of the Convention and the end of the monarchy.
[126] Stephens, The French Revolution, i, 102.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Stephens, The French Revolution, Vol. 1, p. 102.
[127] Hist. Parl., x, 414.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Hist. Parl., x, 414.
[128] Hist. Gén., x, 449.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Hist. Gén., x, 449.
[130] “Trois différentes opinions partageaient donc l’Assemblée et la France. La première, de rétablir le roi, et de maintenir la monarchie d’après les bases de la constitution; la seconde, d’abolir la royauté et d’élever une république; la troisième mitoyenne entre les deux autres, de rétablir le roi ou de placer le dauphin sur le trône, mais de l’environner d’un conseil exécutif indépendant dont les membres amovibles fussent élus par le peuple,” Montlosier, Mémoires, t. i, 467 et seq.
[130] “Three different opinions were therefore shared by the Assembly and France. The first was to restore the king and maintain the monarchy according to the principles of the constitution; the second was to abolish the monarchy and establish a republic; the third, a middle ground between the two, was to restore the king or place the dauphin on the throne, but to surround him with an independent executive council whose members would be elected by the people,” Montlosier, Mémoires, t. i, 467 et seq.
[131] Diary and Letters, i, 436.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Diary and Letters, vol. 1, p. 436.
[133] Hist. Parl., x, 414 et seq.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Hist. Parl., x, 414 and following
[134] Ibid., 452.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Same source., 452.
[135] Ibid., xxv, 422 et seq.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Ibid., 25, 422 et seq.
[137] Hist. Parl., xv, 32 et seq.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Hist. Parl., xv, 32 and following
[138] La liberté ne peut être suspendue; si le pouvoir exécutif n’agit point, il ne peut y avoir d’alternatives, c’est lui qui doit l’être: un seul homme ne doit point influencer la volonté de vingt-cinq millions d’hommes. Si, par égard, nous le maintenons dans son poste, c’est à condition qu’il le remplira constitutionellement; s’il s’en écarte, il n’est plus rien pour le peuple français. Hist. Parl., xv, 139.
[138] Freedom cannot be put on hold; if the executive power does not act, there can be no alternatives; it must be the one held accountable: one man should not have the power to sway the will of twenty-five million people. If we keep him in his position out of respect, it’s on the condition that he fulfills his role constitutionally; if he strays from that, he means nothing to the French people. Hist. Parl., xv, 139.
[139] Hist. Parl., 324 et seq.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Hist. Parl., 324 et seq.
[141] Hist. Parl., xvii, 48.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Hist. Parl., 17, 48.
[142] Ibid., 44.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Same source., 44.
[143] From some Department of Jura there is some reason to believe a political club had addressed a letter at the beginning of 1792 to the Jacobin Club in Paris, asking for the establishment of a republic. Biré, Diary of a Citizen, etc., i, 45.
[143] There's some reason to think that a political club from a department in Jura sent a letter to the Jacobin Club in Paris at the start of 1792, requesting the formation of a republic. Biré, Diary of a Citizen, etc., i, 45.
[145] Ibid., iv, 80.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Same source., iv, 80.
[146] The club decreed August 12: “Qu’il sera fait une adresse aux Sociétés affiliés, pour leur donner une connaissance exacte des événements du 10 Août, les instruire du courage et du patriotisme qu’ont déployé dans cette journée à jamais mémorable les fédérés des quatre-vingt-trois départments, qui avec leurs frères d’armes de Paris, out sauvé le patrie.” Aulard, La Société des Jacobins, iv, 194, 195. August 22, an address was sent to the affiliated society pointing out what class of men should be chosen for the Convention. If they do not choose these, a new insurrection like that of August 10 may be necessary. La Société des Jacobins, iv, 233-235.
[146] The club announced on August 12: “An address will be made to the affiliated societies to give them an accurate understanding of the events of August 10, to inform them of the courage and patriotism displayed that day by the federated troops from the eighty-three departments, who, along with their comrades from Paris, saved the nation.” Aulard, La Société des Jacobins, iv, 194, 195. On August 22, an address was sent to the affiliated society outlining what kind of individuals should be selected for the Convention. If they do not select these individuals, a new uprising like that of August 10 may become necessary. La Société des Jacobins, iv, 233-235.
[147] One of the speakers, M. Manuel, said, August 27: “Nous devons tous jurer, et y’en fais le premier le serment, à quelque poste que je me trouve placé tous mes efforts seront dirigés vers ce but important, de purger la terre de fléau de la royauté.” La Société des Jacobins, iv, 238 et seq.
[147] One of the speakers, M. Manuel, said, August 27: “We all must swear, and I will be the first to take that oath, no matter where I am, all my efforts will be directed towards this important goal: to rid the earth of the plague of monarchy.” The Society of Jacobins, iv, 238 et seq.
[148] Ibid., iv, 259 et seq.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Ibid., iv, 259 and following
[150] “La sanction ou la revision populaire de tous les décrets constitutionnels de la convention nationale; l’abolition absolue de la royauté et peine de mort contre ceux qui proposeraient de la rétablir; la forme d’un gouvernement républicain.” La Société des Jacobins, iv, 281. A letter written by an English lady from Arras, September 1, 1792, contains this statement: “Mr. Thomas Paine ... is in high repute here—his works are translated—all the Jacobins who can read, quote, and all who can’t, admire him.” A Residence in France, i, 68.
[150] “The approval or popular revision of all the constitutional decrees of the national convention; the complete abolition of the monarchy and the death penalty for anyone proposing to restore it; the structure of a republican government.” The Society of the Jacobins, iv, 281. A letter written by an English woman from Arras on September 1, 1792, states: “Mr. Thomas Paine ... is highly regarded here—his works are translated—all the Jacobins who can read quote him, and all who can’t admire him.” A Residence in France, i, 68.
[151] December 21, 1790, the Jacobin Club printed a list of 1,100 members; August 16, 1790, there were fifteen affiliated societies. These affiliations increased rapidly in the spring of 1791, so that by June 16, there were 406 affiliated and 14 corresponding societies; by June, 1793, there were a thousand affiliated clubs. Aulard, La Société des Jacobins, i, Intro., xxxiii-xxxix. That these clubs knew how to make use of their affiliations for political action is patent from the letter sent out among them, August 22, four days before the primary elections were held: “C’est à nous à le soutenir; et nous le pouvons, en éloignant des assemblées électorales tous ceux qui ont protégé, même indirectement la cour et le sacerdoce, les émigrés et leurs adhérents. Notre choix ne doit pas être difficile; les patriotes font la majorité de la nation. Ils peuvent donc, s’ils savent se réunis, faire des choix favorables à leurs intérêts. Les électeurs étant payés à trois livres ... il n’est plus nécessaire d’être riche bourgeois, prêtre, ou ci-devant noble pour accepter cette noble mission; et, si la majorité des électeurs est au niveau de la révolution du 10 Août 1792 nos nouveaux députés ne tarderont pas à la consolider et à sauver le peuple par une constitution conformé à la déclaration des droits et à l’intérêt du plus grand nombre.” Société des Jacobins, iv, 233, et seq.
[151] On December 21, 1790, the Jacobin Club published a list of 1,100 members; as of August 16, 1790, there were fifteen affiliated societies. These affiliations grew quickly in the spring of 1791, so by June 16, there were 406 affiliated and 14 corresponding societies; by June 1793, there were a thousand affiliated clubs. Aulard, La Société des Jacobins, i, Intro., xxxiii-xxxix. It’s clear that these clubs knew how to leverage their affiliations for political action, as shown in the letter they sent out on August 22, just four days before the primary elections: “It's up to us to support this; and we can do it by keeping out of the electoral assemblies anyone who has supported, even indirectly, the court and the clergy, the émigrés and their supporters. Our choice shouldn't be difficult; patriots make up the majority of the nation. Therefore, if they can come together, they can make choices that favor their interests. Since the voters are being paid three livres ... it’s no longer necessary to be a wealthy bourgeois, priest, or former noble to take on this noble mission; and if the majority of the voters align with the revolution of August 10, 1792, our new representatives will quickly reinforce it and save the people with a constitution that reflects the declaration of rights and serves the greater good.” Société des Jacobins, iv, 233, et seq.
[152] Stephen’s French Rev., ii, 154; Babeau’s Hist. de Troyes pendant la Rév., i, 527, 528. The following excerpt from A Residence in France, 1792-95, described in a series of letters from an English Lady, i, 93: “If the electors and elected of the other departments be of the same complexion with those of Arras, the new Assembly will not, in any respect, be preferable to the old one. I have reproached many of the people of this place, who, from their education and property, have a right to take an interest in the public affairs, with thus suffering themselves to be represented by the most desperate and worthless individuals of the town. Their defense is that they are insulted and overpowered if they attend the popular meetings, and by electing les gueux et les scélérats pour députés, they send them to Paris and secure their own local tranquillity.”
[152] Stephen’s French Rev., ii, 154; Babeau’s Hist. de Troyes pendant la Rév., i, 527, 528. The following excerpt from A Residence in France, 1792-95, described in a series of letters from an English Lady, i, 93: “If the voters and elected officials in the other departments are as bad as those in Arras, the new Assembly won’t be any better than the old one. I have criticized many people here, who, because of their education and wealth, should care about public affairs, for allowing themselves to be represented by the most desperate and worthless individuals in town. Their excuse is that they are insulted and overwhelmed if they go to popular meetings, and by electing les gueux et les scélérats pour députés, they send them to Paris and ensure their own local peace.”
[153] The twenty four deputies from the city were Robespierre, Danton, Collot-d’Herbois, Manuel, Billaud-Varenne, Camille Desmoulins, Marat, Lavicomterie, Legendre the butcher, Raffron du Trouillet, Paris, Sergent, Robert, Dusaulx, Frèron, Beauvis de Preau, Fabre d’Eglantine the dramatist, Osselin, Augustine Robespierre, David the great painter, Boucher, Laignelot, Thomas, the ci-devant Duke of Orléans, now democratically named Philippe Égalité. Stephen’s French Rev., ii, 155, 156.
[153] The twenty-four deputies from the city included Robespierre, Danton, Collot-d’Herbois, Manuel, Billaud-Varenne, Camille Desmoulins, Marat, Lavicomterie, Legendre the butcher, Raffron du Trouillet, Paris, Sergent, Robert, Dusaulx, Frèron, Beauvis de Preau, Fabre d’Eglantine the dramatist, Osselin, Augustine Robespierre, David the great painter, Boucher, Laignelot, Thomas, and the former Duke of Orléans, now democratically called Philippe Égalité. Stephen’s French Rev., ii, 155, 156.
[154] The proclamation of the abolition of the monarchy filled Paris with joy. We cite from the Rév. de Paris, No. 167, 534: “Cette proclamation, parvenue dans les 48 sections de Paris, fut répétée dans tous les carrefours au bruit des cors et au milieu des applaudissements universelles. Tous les citoyens à l’envi illuminèrent le devant de leurs maisons, comme à l’occasion d’un grande victoire remportée sur le plus puissant de nos ennemis.”
[154] The announcement of the end of the monarchy brought joy to Paris. We quote from the Rév. de Paris, No. 167, 534: “This announcement, received in all 48 districts of Paris, was repeated at every intersection with the sound of horns and amidst cheers from everyone. All the citizens eagerly lit up the fronts of their homes, as if celebrating a great victory over our greatest enemy.”
[155] Hist. Parl., xix, 6 et seq.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Hist. Parl., vol. 19, p. 6 et seq.
[156] Hist. Parl., xix, 20, 21.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Hist. Parl., 19, 20, 21.
[159] Diary and Letters, i, 596.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Diary and Letters, vol. i, p. 596.
[160] Aulard, Études et Leçons.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Aulard, Studies and Lessons.
[161] Révolutions de Paris, ii, 68-76.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Revolutions of Paris, ii, 68-76.
[162] See Siéyès disavowal, Hist. Parl., x, 451. Brissot’s Journal of Sept. 21, 1791, said: “Qui ne se rappellera pas avec quelque douleur, que le mot de république était alors presque proscrit aux Jacobins même; qu’ il fallait prendre des tournures oratoires pour justifier le républicanisme.” Hist. Parl., xix, 20, 21.
[162] See Siéyès's disavowal, Hist. Parl., x, 451. Brissot’s Journal from September 21, 1791, said: “Who will not remember with some pain that the word ‘republic’ was almost banned, even among the Jacobins; that it was necessary to use elaborate language to defend republicanism.” Hist. Parl., xix, 20, 21.
Aquinas, Thomas, De Regimine Principium.
Aquinas, Thomas, On the Rule of Princes.
Archives parlementaires, 1st Series, vols. 1-50, Paris, 1868.
Archives parlementaires, 1st Series, vols. 1-50, Paris, 1868.
Aubertin, Charles, L’ésprit public au 18 siècle, Paris, 1873.
Aubertin, Charles, The Public Spirit in the 18th Century, Paris, 1873.
Aulard, F. A., Études et Leçons sur la révolution française, Paris, 1893.
Aulard, F. A., Studies and Lessons on the French Revolution, Paris, 1893.
Aulard, F. A., La Société des Jacobins, 5 vols., Paris, 1889.
Aulard, F. A., The Society of Jacobins, 5 vols., Paris, 1889.
Aulard, A., Histoire politique de la Révolution française, Paris, 1901.
Aulard, A., Political History of the French Revolution, Paris, 1901.
Babeau, A., La Ville sous l’ancien régime, 2 vols., Paris, 1884.
Babeau, A., The City under the Old Regime, 2 vols., Paris, 1884.
Babeau, Alfred, La Province sous l’Ancien Régime, 2. vols., Paris, 1894.
Babeau, Alfred, La Province sous l’Ancien Régime, 2 vols., Paris, 1894.
Babeau, Alfred A., Histoire de Troyes pendant la Révolution, Paris, 1873-4, 2 vols.
Babeau, Alfred A., History of Troyes During the Revolution, Paris, 1873-4, 2 vols.
Biré, Jean Baptiste Edmond, Diary of a Citizen of Paris during the Terror, translated and edited by John de Villiers, 2 vols., London, 1896.
Biré, Jean Baptiste Edmond, Diary of a Citizen of Paris during the Terror, translated and edited by John de Villiers, 2 vols., London, 1896.
Bodin, Jean, De Republica.
Bodin, Jean, *De Republica*.
Borgeaud, Charles, Établissement et Revision des Constitutions en Amérique et en Europe, Paris, 1893.
Borgeaud, Charles, Establishment and Revision of Constitutions in America and Europe, Paris, 1893.
Bougeart, Alfred, Marat, l’ami du peuple, 2 vols., Paris, 1865.
Bougeart, Alfred, Marat, the Friend of the People, 2 vols., Paris, 1865.
Bougeart, Alfred, Danton, Paris, 1861.
Bougeart, Alfred, Danton, Paris, 1861.
Boiteau, Paul, État de la France en 1789, Paris, 1861.
Boiteau, Paul, State of France in 1789, Paris, 1861.
Chassin, Charles Louis, Le Génie de la Révolution, Paris, 1864 and 65, 2 vols.
Chassin, Charles Louis, Le Génie de la Révolution, Paris, 1864 and 65, 2 vols.
Chassin, Charles Louis, Les Élections et les Cahiers de Paris en 1789, 4 vols., Paris, 1888, 89.
Chassin, Charles Louis, Les Élections et les Cahiers de Paris en 1789, 4 vols., Paris, 1888, 89.
Champion, Edmé, La France d’après les Cahiers de 1789, Paris, 1897.
Champion, Edmé, France After the Notebooks of 1789, Paris, 1897.
Corwin, R. L., Entwicklung und Vergleichung der Erziehungslehren von John Locke und Jean Jacques Rousseau, Heidelberg, 1894.
Corwin, R. L., Development and Comparison of the Educational Theories of John Locke and Jean Jacques Rousseau, Heidelberg, 1894.
Daire, M. E., Physiocrates, 2 vols., Paris, 1846.
Daire, M. E., Physiocrates, 2 vols., Paris, 1846.
D’Argenson, Mémoires, 5 vols., 1857-58.
D’Argenson, *Mémoires*, 5 vols., 1857-58.
D’Eichthal, E., Souveraineté de peuple, Paris, 1895.
D’Eichthal, E., *People's Sovereignty*, Paris, 1895.
De Tocqueville, Alexis, Mémoires, Letters and Remains, 2 vols., London, 1861.
De Tocqueville, Alexis, Memoirs, Letters, and Remains, 2 vols., London, 1861.
De Tocqueville, L’Ancien régime, translated by Henry Reeve.
De Tocqueville, L’Ancien régime, translated by Henry Reeve.
De Lomenie, L. L., Les Mirabeau, 2 vols., Paris, 1889-91.
De Lomenie, L. L., Les Mirabeau, 2 vols., Paris, 1889-91.
Flammermont, Jules, Remontrances du Parlement de Paris au XVIII. siècle, Paris, 1888.
Flammermont, Jules, Remonstrances of the Parliament of Paris in the 18th Century, Paris, 1888.
Flammermont, Jules, Le Chancelier Maupeou et les Parlements, Paris, 1885.
Flammermont, Jules, Le Chancelier Maupeou et les Parlements, Paris, 1885.
Gomel, Charles, Les Causes financières de la révolution française, Paris, 1893.
Gomel, Charles, The Financial Causes of the French Revolution, Paris, 1893.
Hamel, E., Histoire de Robespierre, 3 vols., 1867.
Hamel, E., History of Robespierre, 3 vols., 1867.
Hervieu, Henri, Recherches sur les premiers États généraux, Paris, 1879.
Hervieu, Henri, Research on the Early Estates-General, Paris, 1879.
Höffding, Dr. Harold, A History of Modern Philosophy, 2 vols., translated by B. E. Myers, New York, 1900.
Höffding, Dr. Harold, A History of Modern Philosophy, 2 vols., translated by B. E. Myers, New York, 1900.
Horning, J., Les idées politiques de Rousseau in “J. J. Rousseau’s jugé par les Génevois d’aujourd’hui.”
Horning, J., The Political Ideas of Rousseau in “J. J. Rousseau Judged by Today’s Genevans.”
Jaeger, Eugen, Geschichte der sozialen Bewegung und des Socialism in Franckreiche, Berlin, 1879, 1890.
Jaeger, Eugen, History of the Social Movement and Socialism in France, Berlin, 1879, 1890.
Jellinek, Dr. George, Die Erklärung der Menschen und Bürgerrechte.
Jellinek, Dr. George, The Declaration of the Rights of Man and Citizen.
La Marck, Correspondance entre Mirabeau et La Marck.
La Marck, Correspondence between Mirabeau and La Marck.
Larousse, P., Dictionnaire Universel du XIX siècle.
Larousse, P., Universal Dictionary of the 19th Century.
Lavisse, Ernest, Histoire Générale, Rambaud et Lavisse, 12 vols., Paris.
Lavisse, Ernest, Histoire Générale, Rambaud et Lavisse, 12 vols., Paris.
La Grande Encyclopédie.
The Great Encyclopedia.
Lowell, Edward J., The Eve of the French Revolution, Boston, 1893.
Lowell, Edward J., The Eve of the French Revolution, Boston, 1893.
Marion, Henri, J. Locke—Sa Vie et son Oeuvre d’après des documents nouveaux, Paris, 1893.
Marion, Henri, J. Locke—His Life and Work According to New Documents, Paris, 1893.
Martin, Henri, Histoire de France, 17 vols., Paris, 1865.
Martin, Henri, History of France, 17 vols., Paris, 1865.
Mirabeau, Comte de, Letters de Caché, Oeuvres, edition of 1820.
Mirabeau, Comte de, Letters de Caché, Oeuvres, edition of 1820.
Mirabeau, Comte de, Mémoires, Brussels, 1834-36.
Mirabeau, Comte de, Mémoires, Brussels, 1834-36.
Mirabeau, Comte de, Oeuvres, Paris, 1835.
Mirabeau, Comte de, Works, Paris, 1835.
Mirabeau, Comte de, Correspondance entre Mirabeau et La Marck.
Mirabeau, Comte de, Correspondence between Mirabeau and La Marck.
Montesquieu, Ésprit des Lois.
Montesquieu, *Spirit of the Laws*.
Montlosier, Comte de, Mémoires.
Montlosier, Comte de, *Memoirs*.
Morley, John, Rousseau, 2 vols., Macmillan & Co., New York, 1890.
Morley, John, Rousseau, 2 vols., Macmillan & Co., New York, 1890.
Morley, John, Diderot and the Encyclopaedists, 2 vols., New York, 1897.
Morley, John, Diderot and the Encyclopaedists, 2 vols., New York, 1897.
Morris, Gouverneur, Diary and Letters, edited by A. C. Morris, New York, 1888, 2 vols.
Morris, Gouverneur, Diary and Letters, edited by A. C. Morris, New York, 1888, 2 vols.
Neymarck, Alfred, Turgot et ses doctrines, 2 vols., Paris, 1885.
Neymarck, Alfred, Turgot and His Doctrines, 2 vols., Paris, 1885.
Picot, G., Histoire des États généraux, Paris, 1888, 5 vols.
Picot, G., History of the States-General, Paris, 1888, 5 vols.
Poole, Reginald A., Illustrations of the History of Mediaeval Thought, London, 1884.
Poole, Reginald A., Illustrations of the History of Medieval Thought, London, 1884.
Rambaud, Alfred, Histoire Générale, Rambaud et Lavisse, 12 vols., Paris.
Rambaud, Alfred, General History, Rambaud and Lavisse, 12 volumes, Paris.
Ritchie, David G., Natural Rights, London, 1895.
Ritchie, David G., Natural Rights, London, 1895.
Ritchie, David G., The Social Contract, in vii vol. of Political Science Quarterly.
Ritchie, David G., The Social Contract, in vol. vii of Political Science Quarterly.
Robinson, Prof. J. H., The Tennis Court Oath, Political Science Quarterly, vol. x, September, 1895.
Robinson, Prof. J. H., The Tennis Court Oath, Political Science Quarterly, vol. x, September, 1895.
Robinson, Prof. J. H., The French Declaration of Rights, Political Science Quarterly, vol. xiv, No. 4, December, 1899.
Robinson, Prof. J. H., The French Declaration of Rights, Political Science Quarterly, vol. 14, No. 4, December 1899.
Robinson, Prof. J. H., and Grace Read Robinson, Protests of the Cour des Aides, April 10, 1775; Translations and Reprints from Original Sources of European History, Department of History of the University of Pennsylvania, 1899.
Robinson, Prof. J. H., and Grace Read Robinson, Protests of the Cour des Aides, April 10, 1775; Translations and Reprints from Original Sources of European History, Department of History of the University of Pennsylvania, 1899.
Robiquet, Paul, Le personnel municipal de Paris, pendant la révolution, Paris, 1890.
Robiquet, Paul, The Municipal Staff of Paris During the Revolution, Paris, 1890.
Rocquain, Felix, L’ésprit révolutionnaire avant la révolution, Paris, 1878.
Rocquain, Felix, The Revolutionary Spirit Before the Revolution, Paris, 1878.
Rousseau, Jean Jacques, Contrat social.
Rousseau, Jean Jacques, *The Social Contract*.
Roux, P. C., Histoire Parlementaire, 1789-1815, P. J. B.; Buchez et P. C. Roux, 40 vols., Paris, 1835.
Roux, P. C., Histoire Parlementaire, 1789-1815, P. J. B.; Buchez et P. C. Roux, 40 vols., Paris, 1835.
Saftu, Vasilie, Ein Vergleich der Physichen Erziehung bei Locke und Rousseau, Bucarest, 1889.
Saftu, Vasilie, A Comparison of Physical Education in Locke and Rousseau, Bucarest, 1889.
Saint Girons, Droit public français, Paris, 1881.
Saint Girons, Droit public français, Paris, 1881.
Sayous, Pierre Andre, Memoires and Correspondence Illustrative of the History of the French Revolution, 1852.
Sayous, Pierre Andre, Memoirs and Correspondence Illustrative of the History of the French Revolution, 1852.
Sloane, William M., The French Revolution and Religious Reform, Charles Scribner’s Sons, New York, 1901.
Sloane, William M., The French Revolution and Religious Reform, Charles Scribner’s Sons, New York, 1901.
Sorel, Albert, L’Europe et la révolution française, 4 vols., Paris, 1887, 1892.
Sorel, Albert, L'Europe et la révolution française, 4 vols., Paris, 1887, 1892.
Stephens, Henry Morse, The French Revolution, New York, 1886.
Stephens, Henry Morse, The French Revolution, New York, 1886.
Stephens, W. Walker, Life and Writings of Turgot. London, 1895.
Stephens, W. Walker, Life and Writings of Turgot. London, 1895.
Texte, Joseph, Jean Jacques Rousseau et les Origines du Cosmopolitisme littéraire, Paris, 1895.
Texte, Joseph, Jean Jacques Rousseau and the Origins of Literary Cosmopolitanism, Paris, 1895.
Tripier, Louis. Constitutions qui ont régie la France depuis 1789, Paris, 1879.
Tripier, Louis. Constitutions that have governed France since 1789, Paris, 1879.
Turgot, Oeuvres, Paris, 1808.
Turgot, Oeuvres, Paris, 1808.
Voltaire, Oeuvres, edited by M. Beuchot.
Voltaire, Works, edited by M. Beuchot.
Vuy, Jules, Rousseau et Locke, in Bulletin de L’Institut National Génevois, 1883.
Vuy, Jules, Rousseau and Locke, in Bulletin of the National Institute of Geneva, 1883.
Various French pamphlets and newspapers found in the Library of Columbia University, New York: Astor Library, New York; the Library of the Pennsylvania Historical Society, Philadelphia, Pa., and the Boston Public Library.
Various French pamphlets and newspapers found in the Library of Columbia University, New York; Astor Library, New York; the Library of the Pennsylvania Historical Society, Philadelphia, Pa., and the Boston Public Library.
Download ePUB
If you like this ebook, consider a donation!