This is a modern-English version of What I believe, originally written by Russell, Bertrand. It has been thoroughly updated, including changes to sentence structure, words, spelling, and grammar—to ensure clarity for contemporary readers, while preserving the original spirit and nuance. If you click on a paragraph, you will see the original text that we modified, and you can toggle between the two versions.

Scroll to the bottom of this page and you will find a free ePUB download link for this book.


WHAT I BELIEVE

WHAT I THINK


THE TO-DAY AND TO-MORROW SERIES

THE TODAY AND TOMORROW SERIES


  • DÆDALUS, or Science and the Future
    By J. B. S. Haldane
  • ICARUS, or The Future of Science
    By the Hon. Bertrand Russell, F.R.S.
  • THE MONGOL IN OUR MIDST
    By F. G. Crookshank, M.D. Fully Illustrated
  • WIRELESS POSSIBILITIES
    By Prof. A. M. Low. With four Diagrams
  • TANTALUS, or The Future of Man
    By F. C. S. Schiller
  • NARCISSUS, An Anatomy of Clothes
    By Gerald Heard. Illustrated
  • CALLINICUS, A Defence of Chemical Warfare
    By J. B. S. Haldane
  • THE PASSING OF THE PHANTOMS
    By C. J. Patten, M.A., M.D., Sc.D., F.R.A.I.
  • QUO VADIMUS? Some Glimpses of the Future
    By E. E. Fournier d’Albe, D.Sc., F.Inst.P.
  • THE CONQUEST OF CANCER
    By H. W. S. Wright, M.S., F.R.C.S.
  • LYSISTRATA, or Woman and the Future
    By Anthony M. Ludovici
  • WHAT I BELIEVE
    By the Hon. Bertrand Russell, F.R.S.
  • HYPATIA
    By Dora Russell (The Hon. Mrs. Bertrand Russell)

In Preparation

Getting Ready

  • PERSEUS, of Dragons
    By H. F. Scott Stokes, M.A.
  • THE EVOCATION OF GENIUS
    By Alan Porter
  • THE FUTURE OF SEX
    By Rebecca West
  • AESCULAPIUS, or Disease and The Man
    By F. G. Crookshank, M.D.

E. P. DUTTON & COMPANY

E. P. DUTTON & COMPANY


WHAT I BELIEVE

BY

BY

BERTRAND RUSSELL

BERTRAND RUSSELL

NEW YORK
E. P. DUTTON & COMPANY
681 Fifth Avenue

NEW YORK
E. P. DUTTON & COMPANY
681 5th Avenue


Copyright, 1925
By E. P. DUTTON & COMPANY

Copyright, 1925
By E. P. DUTTON & COMPANY

All Rights Reserved

All Rights Reserved

First Printing, April, 1925
Second Printing, June, 1925
Third Printing, June, 1925
Fourth Printing, March, 1926

First Printing, April 1925
Second Printing, June 1925
Third Printing, June 1925
Fourth Printing, March 1926

PRINTED IN THE UNITED STATES OF AMERICA

PRINTED IN THE UNITED STATES OF AMERICA


[v]

[v]

PREFACE

In this little book, I have tried to say what I think of man’s place in the universe, and of his possibilities in the way of achieving the good life. In Icarus I expressed my fears; in the following pages I have expressed my hopes. The inconsistency is only apparent. Except in astronomy, mankind have not achieved the art of predicting the future; in human affairs, we can see that there are forces making for happiness, and forces making for misery. We do not know which will prevail, but to act wisely we must be aware of both.

In this little book, I’ve tried to share my thoughts on humanity's place in the universe and our potential for achieving a good life. In Icarus, I voiced my fears; in the following pages, I share my hopes. The inconsistency is only superficial. Apart from astronomy, humanity hasn’t mastered the art of predicting the future; in human affairs, we can see forces driving happiness and forces driving misery. We don’t know which will win out, but to act wisely, we need to recognize both.

January 1st, 1925 B. R.

January 1, 1925 B. R.

[vi]

[vi]


[vii]

[vii]

TABLE OF CONTENTS

CHAP. PAGE
I NATURE AND MAN 1
II THE GOOD LIFE 19
III MORAL RULES 35
IV SALVATION: INDIVIDUAL AND SOCIAL 55
V SCIENCE AND HAPPINESS 65

[1]

[1]

WHAT I BELIEVE

MY BELIEFS

CHAPTER I
NATURE AND MAN

Man is a part of Nature, not something contrasted with Nature. His thoughts and his bodily movements follow the same laws that describe the motions of stars and atoms. The physical world is large compared with Man—larger than it was thought to be in Dante’s time, but not so large as it seemed a hundred years ago. Both upward and downward, both in the large and in the small, science seems to be reaching limits. It is thought that the universe is of finite extent in space, and that light could travel round it in a few hundred millions of years. It is thought that matter consists of electrons and[2] protons, which are of finite size, and of which there are only a finite number in the world. Probably their changes are not continuous, as used to be thought, but proceed by jerks, which are never smaller than a certain minimum jerk. The laws of these changes can apparently be summed up in a small number of very general principles, which determine the past and the future of the world when any small section of its history is known.

Man is part of Nature, not something separate from it. His thoughts and movements follow the same laws that describe the motions of stars and atoms. The physical world is vast compared to Man—larger than it was believed to be in Dante’s time, but not as immense as it appeared a hundred years ago. Science seems to be hitting limits both upward and downward, in the large and the small. It's believed that the universe is finite in size and that light could travel around it in a few hundred million years. Matter is thought to consist of electrons and protons, which have a finite size and exist in a finite number in the world. Their changes probably aren’t continuous, as was once believed, but happen in jumps that are never smaller than a certain minimum change. The laws governing these changes can apparently be summarized in a few very general principles, which determine the past and future of the world when any small part of its history is known.

Physical science is thus approaching the stage when it will be complete, and therefore uninteresting. Given the laws governing the motions of electrons and protons, the rest is merely geography—a collection of particular facts telling their distribution throughout some portion of the world’s history. The total number of facts of geography required to determine the world’s history is probably finite; theoretically,[3] they could all be written down in a big book to be kept at Somerset House, with a calculating machine attached, which, by turning a handle, would enable the inquirer to find out the facts at other times than those recorded. It is difficult to imagine anything less interesting, or more different from the passionate delights of incomplete discovery. It is like climbing a high mountain and finding nothing at the top except a restaurant where they sell ginger-beer, surrounded by fog but equipped with wireless. Perhaps in the time of Ahmes the multiplication-table was exciting.

Physical science is getting close to being complete, which makes it kind of boring. With the laws that govern the movements of electrons and protons, everything else is just geography—a collection of specific facts about how they’re spread out through different parts of history. The total number of geographical facts needed to map out the world’s history is probably finite; in theory,[3] they could all fit in a big book stored at Somerset House, with a calculating machine attached that would allow someone to turn a handle and access facts from times not documented. It’s hard to imagine anything less interesting, or more different from the thrilling joys of incomplete discovery. It’s like hiking up a tall mountain only to find a café at the top selling ginger beer, surrounded by fog but equipped with wireless. Maybe back in Ahmes’s time, the multiplication table was thrilling.

Of this physical world, uninteresting in itself, Man is a part. His body, like other matter, is composed of electrons and protons, which, so far as we know, obey the same laws as those not forming part of animals or plants. There are some who maintain that physiology[4] can never be reduced to physics, but their arguments are not very convincing and it seems prudent to suppose that they are mistaken. What we call our “thoughts” seem to depend upon the organization of tracks in the brain in the same sort of way in which journeys depend upon roads and railways. The energy used in thinking seems to have a chemical origin; for instance, a deficiency of iodine will turn a clever man into an idiot. Mental phenomena seem to be bound up with material structure. If this be so, we cannot suppose that a solitary electron or proton can “think”; we might as well expect a solitary individual to play a football match. We also cannot suppose that an individual’s thinking survives bodily death, since that destroys the organization of the brain, and dissipates the energy which utilized the brain-tracks.

In this physical world, which is pretty uninteresting on its own, humans are just one part of it. Our bodies, like everything else, are made up of electrons and protons, which, as far as we can tell, follow the same rules as those found outside of animals and plants. Some argue that physiology[4] can never be fully explained by physics, but their points aren't very convincing, and it seems wise to think they might be wrong. What we call our “thoughts” appear to rely on the network of connections in the brain, much like how trips depend on roads and railways. The energy we use for thinking seems to come from chemical processes; for example, a lack of iodine can turn a smart person into someone who can’t think clearly. Mental events seem to be tied to physical structure. If that's true, we can't expect a single electron or proton to "think"; that would be like expecting one person to play an entire football match. We also can't assume that an individual's thoughts continue after death, since that would destroy the brain's organization and release the energy that powers those mental connections.

[5]

[5]

God and immortality, the central dogmas of the Christian religion, find no support in science. It cannot be said that either doctrine is essential to religion, since neither is found in Buddhism. (With regard to immortality, this statement in an unqualified form might be misleading, but it is correct in the last analysis). But we in the West have come to think of them as the irreducible minimum of theology. No doubt people will continue to entertain these beliefs, because they are pleasant, just as it is pleasant to think ourselves virtuous and our enemies wicked. But for my part I cannot see any ground for either. I do not pretend to be able to prove that there is no God. I equally cannot prove that Satan is a fiction. The Christian God may exist; so may the Gods of Olympus, or of ancient Egypt, or of Babylon. But no one of these[6] hypotheses is more probable than any other: they lie outside the region of even probable knowledge, and therefore there is no reason to consider any of them. I shall not enlarge upon this question, as I have dealt with it elsewhere.[A]

God and immortality, the core beliefs of Christianity, don't get any backing from science. It's not accurate to say that either belief is essential to religion, since neither is found in Buddhism. (About immortality, this statement might be a bit misleading if taken at face value, but it holds true in the end.) However, in the West, we've come to view them as the bare minimum for theology. People will likely continue to hold onto these beliefs because they make us feel good, just like it feels nice to think of ourselves as good and our enemies as evil. But personally, I see no basis for either. I don't claim I can prove there's no God. I also can't prove that Satan is just a made-up character. The Christian God might exist; so could the gods of Olympus, ancient Egypt, or Babylon. But none of these options is more likely than another; they are all beyond the scope of what we can reasonably know, so there's no reason to focus on any of them. I won't go deeper into this issue, as I've addressed it elsewhere.[6]

[A] See my Philosophy of Leibniz, Chapter XV.

[A] Check out my Philosophy of Leibniz, Chapter XV.

The question of personal immortality stands on a somewhat different footing. Here evidence either way is possible. Persons are part of the everyday world with which science is concerned, and the conditions which determine their existence are discoverable. A drop of water is not immortal; it can be resolved into oxygen and hydrogen. If, therefore, a drop of water were to maintain that it had a quality of aqueousness which would survive its dissolution, we should be inclined to be sceptical. In like manner we know that the brain is not immortal, and[7] that the organized energy of a living body becomes, as it were, demobilized at death, and therefore not available for collective action. All the evidence goes to show that what we regard as our mental life is bound up with brain-structure and organized bodily energy. Therefore it is rational to suppose that mental life ceases when bodily life ceases. The argument is only one of probability, but it is as strong as those upon which most scientific conclusions are based.

The question of personal immortality is a bit different. Here, evidence can go either way. People are part of the everyday world that science studies, and the factors that determine their existence can be uncovered. A drop of water isn’t immortal; it can break down into oxygen and hydrogen. So, if a drop of water claimed it had a quality of wetness that would survive its dissolution, we would likely be skeptical. Similarly, we know that the brain isn’t immortal, and that the organized energy of a living body becomes, in a sense, inactive at death, and is therefore not available for coordinated action. All the evidence suggests that what we consider our mental life is linked with brain structure and organized bodily energy. Thus, it’s reasonable to assume that mental life ends when bodily life ends. This argument is based on probability, but it’s as solid as the basis for most scientific conclusions.

There are various grounds upon which this conclusion might be attacked. Psychical research professes to have actual scientific evidence of survival, and undoubtedly its procedure is, in principle, scientifically correct. Evidence of this sort might be so overwhelming that no one with a scientific temper could reject it. The weight to be attached to the evidence, however,[8] must depend upon the antecedent probability of the hypothesis of survival. There are always different ways of accounting for any set of phenomena, and of these we should prefer the one which is antecedently least improbable. Those who already think it likely that we survive death will be ready to view this theory as the best explanation of psychical phenomena. Those, who, on other grounds, regard this theory as unplausible will seek for other explanations. For my part, I consider the evidence so far adduced by psychical research in favour of survival much weaker than the physiological evidence on the other side. But I fully admit that it might at any moment become stronger, and in that case it would be unscientific to disbelieve in survival.

There are several reasons this conclusion could be challenged. Psychical research claims to have real scientific evidence of survival, and its methods are, fundamentally, scientifically sound. This type of evidence could be so compelling that no one with a scientific mindset could dismiss it. However, the importance given to the evidence [8] must rely on the prior likelihood of the survival hypothesis. There are always various explanations for any set of phenomena, and we should prefer the one that seems least improbable from the start. Those who believe it's likely we survive death will likely see this theory as the best explanation for psychical phenomena. Those who find this theory implausible for other reasons will look for alternative explanations. Personally, I think the evidence presented by psychical research supporting survival is much weaker than the physiological evidence against it. But I completely acknowledge that it could become stronger at any moment, and if that happens, it would be unscientific to disbelieve in survival.

Survival of bodily death is, however, a different matter from immortality:[9] it may only mean a postponement of psychical death. It is immortality that men desire to believe in. Believers in immortality will object to physiological arguments, such as I have been using, on the ground that soul and body are totally disparate, and that the soul is something quite other than its empirical manifestations through our bodily organs. I believe this to be a metaphysical superstition. Mind and matter alike are for certain purposes convenient terms, but are not ultimate realities. Electrons and protons, like the soul, are logical fictions: each is really a history, a series of events, not a single persistent entity. In the case of the soul, this is obvious from the facts of growth. Whoever considers conception, gestation, and infancy cannot seriously believe that the soul is an indivisible something, perfect and complete throughout this process. It[10] is evident that it grows like the body, and that it derives both from the spermatozoon and from the ovum, so that it cannot be indivisible. This is not materialism: it is merely the recognition that everything interesting is a matter of organization, not of primal substance.

Survival after physical death is a different issue than immortality:[9] it might just mean delaying the end of consciousness. It’s immortality that people want to believe in. Supporters of immortality will challenge the biological arguments I've been making, claiming that the soul and body are completely separate and that the soul is something beyond its physical expressions through our bodily systems. I think this is a metaphysical belief. Both mind and matter are useful terms for specific purposes, but they aren't the ultimate truths. Electrons and protons, like the soul, are logical constructs: each is essentially a narrative, a series of events, not a single unchanging entity. With the soul, this is clear when we consider growth. Anyone who thinks about conception, pregnancy, and childhood can’t honestly believe that the soul is a single, unchanging thing, perfect and whole throughout this journey. It[10] is clear that it develops like the body, drawing from both the sperm and the egg, so it can't be indivisible. This isn't materialism; it's simply acknowledging that everything interesting comes down to organization, not just fundamental substance.

Metaphysicians have advanced innumerable arguments to prove that the soul must be immortal. There is one simple test by which all these arguments can be demolished. They all prove equally that the soul must pervade all space. But as we are not so anxious to be fat as to live long, none of the metaphysicians in question have ever noticed this application of their reasonings. This is an instance of the amazing power of desire in blinding even very able men to fallacies which would otherwise be obvious at once. If we were not afraid of death, I do[11] not believe that the idea of immortality would ever have arisen.

Metaphysicians have proposed countless arguments to prove that the soul must be immortal. There's one simple test that can debunk all these arguments. They all suggest equally that the soul must fill all of space. However, since we aren't as eager to be fat as we are to live long, none of the metaphysicians in question have ever recognized this flaw in their reasoning. This shows the incredible power of desire in blinding even very intelligent people to obvious fallacies. If we weren't afraid of death, I don't think the idea of immortality would ever have come up.

Fear is the basis of religious dogma, as of so much else in human life. Fear of human beings, individually or collectively, dominates much of our social life, but it is fear of nature that gives rise to religion. The antithesis of mind and matter is, as we have seen, more or less illusory; but there is another antithesis which is more important—that, namely, between things that can be affected by our desires and things that cannot be so affected. The line between the two is neither sharp nor immutable—as science advances, more and more things are brought under human control. Nevertheless there remain things definitely on the other side. Among these are all the large facts of our world, the sort of facts that are dealt with by astronomy. It is only facts on or near[12] the surface of the earth that we can, to some extent, mould to suit our desires. And even on the surface of the earth, our powers are very limited. Above all, we cannot prevent death, although we can often delay it.

Fear is the foundation of religious beliefs, as it is for much of human life. The fear of individuals or groups greatly influences our social interactions, but it is the fear of nature that leads to the creation of religion. The separation between mind and matter is largely a false dichotomy; however, a more significant distinction exists—between things that can be influenced by our desires and those that cannot. This boundary is neither clear-cut nor permanent—as science progresses, more aspects of life become manageable by humans. Still, there are things that remain firmly beyond our control. Among these are all the large facts of our universe, the kind of facts studied in astronomy. We can only somewhat shape the facts that are on or near[12] the Earth's surface to meet our needs. Even then, our abilities are quite limited. Ultimately, we cannot stop death, though we can often postpone it.

Religion is an attempt to overcome this antithesis. If the world is controlled by God, and God can be moved by prayer, we acquire a share in omnipotence. In former days, miracles happened in answer to prayer; they still do in the Catholic Church, but Protestants have lost this power. However, it is possible to dispense with miracles, since Providence has decreed that the operation of natural laws shall produce the best possible results. Thus belief in God still serves to humanize the world of nature, and to make men feel that physical forces are really their allies. In like manner immortality removes the terror from death. People[13] who believe that when they die they will inherit eternal bliss may be expected to view death without horror, though, fortunately for medical men, this does not invariably happen. It does, however, soothe men’s fears somewhat, even when it cannot allay them wholly.

Religion is an attempt to bridge this contradiction. If the world is governed by God, and God can be influenced by prayer, we gain a partial power over everything. In the past, miracles occurred in response to prayer; they still do in the Catholic Church, but Protestants have lost this power. However, we can do without miracles since Providence has decided that the natural laws will yield the best possible outcomes. Therefore, belief in God still helps make the world of nature more relatable and allows people to see physical forces as their allies. Similarly, the idea of immortality lessens the fear of death. People who believe they will achieve eternal happiness after death are likely to face death without fear, although, fortunately for doctors, this isn't always the case. Still, it does ease people's anxieties somewhat, even if it doesn’t completely eliminate them.

Religion, since it has its source in terror, has dignified certain kinds of fear, and made people think them not disgraceful. In this it has done mankind a great disservice: all fear is bad, and ought to be overcome not by fairy tales, but by courage and rational reflection. I believe that when I die I shall rot, and nothing of my ego will survive. I am not young, and I love life. But I should scorn to shiver with terror at the thought of annihilation. Happiness is none the less true happiness because it must come to an end, nor do thought and love lose their value because they are not everlasting.[14] Many a man has borne himself proudly on the scaffold: surely the same pride should teach us to think truly about man’s place in the world. Even if the open windows of science at first make us shiver after the cosy indoor warmth of traditional humanizing myths, in the end the fresh air brings vigour, and the great spaces have a splendour of their own.

Religion, because it originates from fear, has made certain types of fear seem honorable and led people to believe they aren’t shameful. In this way, it has done humanity a significant disservice: all fear is negative and should be confronted not with fairy tales, but with courage and rational thought. I believe that when I die, I will decay, and nothing of my identity will remain. I'm not young, and I cherish life. But I would never cower in fear at the idea of obliteration. True happiness doesn't lose its value simply because it must end, nor do thought and love become less significant because they aren't eternal.[14] Many individuals have faced the gallows with dignity: surely the same confidence should guide us to think clearly about humanity’s role in the universe. Even if the open windows of science make us uncomfortable at first after being cozy inside the familiar myths, in the end, the fresh air brings vitality, and the vastness has its own beauty.

The philosophy of nature is one thing, the philosophy of value is quite another. Nothing but harm can come of confusing them. What we think good, what we should like, has no bearing whatever upon what is, which is the question for the philosophy of nature. On the other hand, we cannot be forbidden to value this or that on the ground that the non-human world does not value it, nor can we be compelled to admire anything because it is a “law of nature.” Undoubtedly[15] we are part of nature, which has produced our desires, our hopes and fears, in accordance with laws which the physicist is beginning to discover. In this sense we are part of nature; in the philosophy of nature, we are subordinated to nature, the outcome of natural laws, and their victims in the long run.

The philosophy of nature is one thing, while the philosophy of value is something entirely different. Confusing the two can only lead to problems. What we consider good or what we desire has no connection to what actually exists, which is the focus of the philosophy of nature. Conversely, we can't be told not to value certain things just because the non-human world doesn’t value them, nor can we be forced to admire something simply because it is a “law of nature.” Of course, we are part of nature, which has shaped our desires, hopes, and fears according to laws that physicists are starting to uncover. In this way, we are part of nature; in the realm of the philosophy of nature, we are subject to nature, the result of natural laws, and ultimately its victims.

The philosophy of nature must not be unduly terrestrial; for it, the earth is merely one of the smaller planets of one of the smaller stars of the Milky Way. It would be ridiculous to warp the philosophy of nature in order to bring out results that are pleasing to the tiny parasites of this insignificant planet. Vitalism as a philosophy, and evolutionism, show, in this respect, a lack of sense of proportion and logical relevance. They regard the facts of life, which are personally interesting to us, as having a cosmic significance, not[16] a significance confined to the earth’s surface. Optimism and pessimism, as cosmic philosophies, show the same naïve humanism: the great world, so far as we know it from the philosophy of nature, is neither good nor bad, and is not concerned to make us either happy or unhappy. All such philosophies spring from self-importance, and are best corrected by a little astronomy.

The philosophy of nature shouldn’t be overly focused on Earth; for it, our planet is just one of the smaller ones orbiting a smaller star in the Milky Way. It would be absurd to twist the philosophy of nature to produce results that satisfy the little inhabitants of this insignificant planet. Vitalism and evolutionism, in this regard, lack a proper sense of proportion and logical relevance. They view the facts of life, which are personally important to us, as having a cosmic significance, rather than a significance limited to the Earth’s surface. Optimism and pessimism, as cosmic philosophies, reveal the same naïve humanism: the vast universe, as we understand it from the philosophy of nature, is neither good nor bad and doesn’t concern itself with making us happy or unhappy. All such philosophies arise from a sense of self-importance and are best corrected through a bit of astronomy.

But in the philosophy of value the situation is reversed. Nature is only a part of what we can imagine; everything, real or imagined, can be appraised by us, and there is no outside standard to show that our valuation is wrong. We are ourselves the ultimate and irrefutable arbiters of value, and in the world of value Nature is only a part. Thus in this world we are greater than Nature. In the world of values, Nature in itself is neutral, neither good[17] nor bad, deserving of neither admiration nor censure. It is we who create value, and our desires which confer value. In this realm we are kings, and we debase our kingship if we bow down to Nature. It is for us to determine the good life, not for Nature—not even for Nature personified as God.

But in the philosophy of value, the situation is flipped. Nature is just one part of what we can envision; everything, whether real or imagined, can be evaluated by us, and there's no external standard to prove our valuation is wrong. We are the ultimate and undeniable judges of value, and in the value system, Nature is just a piece. So in this realm, we are more significant than Nature. In the world of values, Nature itself is neutral, neither good nor bad, deserving of neither praise nor blame. It's us who create value, and our desires that attribute value. In this domain, we are rulers, and we diminish our authority if we submit to Nature. It’s up to us to define the good life, not Nature—not even Nature portrayed as God.

[18]

[18]


[19]

[19]

CHAPTER II
THE GOOD LIFE

There have been at different times and among different people many varying conceptions of the good life. To some extent the differences were amenable to argument; this was when men differed as to the means to achieve a given end. Some think that prison is a good way of preventing crime; others hold that education would be better. A difference of this sort can be decided by sufficient evidence. But some differences cannot be tested in this way. Tolstoy condemned all war; others have held the life of a soldier doing battle for the right to be very noble. Here there[20] was probably involved a real difference as to ends. Those who praise the soldier usually consider the punishment of sinners a good thing in itself; Tolstoy did not think so. On such a matter, no argument is possible. I cannot, therefore, prove that my view of the good life is right; I can only state my view, and hope that as many as possible will agree. My view is this:

There have been many different ideas about what the good life is, varying across different times and among different people. Some of these differences can be argued about, especially when people disagree on how to achieve a common goal. For instance, some believe that prison is an effective way to prevent crime, while others think that education would be a better solution. These kinds of disagreements can be resolved with enough evidence. However, some differences can't be tested in this way. Tolstoy condemned all war, while others view the life of a soldier fighting for a just cause as very noble. In this case, there was likely a genuine difference in beliefs about what is important. Those who admire soldiers generally see punishing wrongdoers as a good thing in itself, while Tolstoy disagreed with this view. On such matters, no argument can settle the debate. Therefore, I cannot prove that my perspective on the good life is correct; I can only share my view and hope that many will agree. Here is my perspective:

The good life is one inspired by love and guided by knowledge.

The good life is one that's inspired by love and guided by knowledge.

Knowledge and love are both indefinitely extensible; therefore, however good a life may be, a better life can be imagined. Neither love without knowledge, nor knowledge without love can produce a good life. In the Middle Ages, when pestilence appeared in a country, holy men advised the population to assemble in churches and pray for deliverance; the result was that the infection spread with extraordinary[21] rapidity among the crowded masses of supplicants. This was an example of love without knowledge. The late War afforded an example of knowledge without love. In each case, the result was death on a large scale.

Knowledge and love can both be endlessly expanded; so, no matter how good a life may be, a better one can always be imagined. You can't have a good life with love alone, nor with knowledge alone. During the Middle Ages, when a plague hit a country, religious leaders advised people to gather in churches and pray for salvation; this resulted in the disease spreading rapidly among the large crowds of worshippers. This was an instance of love without knowledge. The recent War showed us knowledge without love. In both scenarios, the outcome was mass death.

Although both love and knowledge are necessary, love is in a sense more fundamental, since it will lead intelligent people to seek knowledge, in order to find out how to benefit those whom they love. But if people are not intelligent, they will be content to believe what they have been told, and may do harm in spite of the most genuine benevolence. Medicine affords, perhaps, the best example of what I mean. An able physician is more useful to a patient than the most devoted friend, and progress in medical knowledge does more for the health of the community than ill-informed philanthropy. Nevertheless, an element of[22] benevolence is essential even here, if any but the rich are to profit by scientific discoveries.

Although both love and knowledge are essential, love is somewhat more fundamental because it drives intelligent people to seek knowledge to learn how to help those they care about. However, if people aren’t intelligent, they’ll just accept what they’ve been told and might cause harm despite their good intentions. Medicine is probably the best example of this idea. A skilled doctor is more helpful to a patient than the most caring friend, and advances in medical knowledge do more for the health of the community than well-meaning but uninformed charity. Still, a sense of benevolence is crucial here too, if anyone other than the wealthy is to benefit from scientific advancements.

Love is a word which covers a variety of feelings; I have used it purposely, as I wish to include them all. Love as an emotion—which is what I am speaking about, for love “on principle” does not seem to me genuine—moves between two poles: on the one side, pure delight in contemplation; on the other, pure benevolence. Where inanimate objects are concerned, delight alone enters in: we cannot feel benevolence towards a landscape or a sonata. This type of enjoyment is presumably the source of art. It is stronger, as a rule, in very young children than in adults, who are apt to view objects in a utilitarian spirit. It plays a large part in our feelings towards human beings, some of whom have charm and some the reverse, when[23] considered simply as objects of aesthetic contemplation.

Love is a word that encompasses a range of feelings; I’m using it intentionally because I want to include them all. Love as an emotion—which is what I’m talking about, since love “on principle” doesn’t seem genuine to me—exists between two extremes: on one side, pure joy in contemplation; on the other, pure goodwill. When it comes to inanimate objects, only joy comes into play: we can’t feel goodwill towards a landscape or a sonata. This kind of enjoyment is likely the foundation of art. It’s usually stronger in very young children than in adults, who tend to view things in a practical way. It plays a significant role in how we feel about other people, some of whom have charm and others do not, when[23] viewed solely as objects of aesthetic contemplation.

The opposite pole of love is pure benevolence. Men have sacrificed their lives to helping lepers in such a case, the love they felt cannot have had any element of aesthetic delight. Parental affection, as a rule, is accompanied by pleasure in the child’s appearance, but remains strong when this element is wholly absent. It would seem odd to call a mother’s interest in a sick child “benevolence,” because we are in the habit of using this word to describe a pale emotion nine parts humbug. But it is difficult to find any other word to describe the desire for another person’s welfare. It is a fact that a desire of this sort may reach any degree of strength in the case of parental feeling. In other cases it is far less intense; indeed it would seem likely that all altruistic emotion is a sort of[24] overflow of parental feeling, or sometimes a sublimation of it. For want of a better word, I shall call this emotion “benevolence.” But I want to make it clear that I am speaking of an emotion, not a principle, and that I do not include in it any feeling of superiority such as is sometimes associated with the word. The word “sympathy” expresses part of what I mean, but leaves out the element of activity that I wish to include.

The opposite of love is pure kindness. People have sacrificed their lives to help lepers; in those cases, the love they felt couldn't have had any aesthetic pleasure involved. Typically, parental love comes with a joy in the child's appearance, but it remains strong even when that aspect is completely absent. It seems strange to label a mother’s concern for a sick child as “kindness” because we usually use that term for an emotion that feels insincere. However, it’s hard to find any other word to express the wish for someone else’s well-being. It’s true that this desire can be very strong in parental love. In other situations, it’s much weaker; in fact, it seems that all altruistic feelings are some sort of overflow of parental love, or sometimes a transformation of it. Lacking a better term, I’ll refer to this emotion as “kindness.” But I want to clarify that I’m talking about an emotion, not a principle, and that I don't mean to include any sense of superiority that sometimes comes with the word. The term “sympathy” captures part of what I mean, but it misses the active component I want to convey.

Love at its fullest is an indissoluble combination of the two elements, delight and well-wishing. The pleasure of a parent in a beautiful and successful child combines both elements; so does sex-love at its best. But in sex-love benevolence will only exist where there is secure possession, since otherwise jealousy will destroy it, while perhaps actually increasing the delight in contemplation. Delight without[25] well-wishing may be cruel; well-wishing without delight easily tends to become cold and a little superior. A person who wishes to be loved wishes to be the object of a love containing both elements, except in cases of extreme weakness, such as infancy and severe illness. In these cases benevolence may be all that is desired. Conversely, in cases of extreme strength admiration is more desired than benevolence: this is the state of mind of potentates and famous beauties. We only desire other people’s good wishes in proportion as we feel ourselves in need of help or in danger of harm from them. At least, that would seem to be the biological logic of the situation, but it is not quite true to life. We desire affection in order to escape from the feeling of loneliness, in order to be, as we say, “understood.” This is a matter of sympathy, not merely of[26] benevolence; the person whose affection is satisfactory to us must not merely wish us well, but must know in what our happiness consists. But this belongs to the other element of the good life, namely knowledge.

Love at its fullest is an inseparable blend of two elements: joy and goodwill. The happiness a parent feels for a beautiful and successful child captures both elements; the same goes for the best kind of romantic love. However, in romantic love, goodwill only exists where there is a sense of security, because jealousy can tear it apart, even if it might amplify the enjoyment of the relationship. Joy without goodwill can be cruel; goodwill without joy often becomes cold and a bit condescending. A person who wants to be loved desires to be the focus of love that includes both elements, except in extreme situations like childhood or serious illness, where goodwill might be all that is needed. On the other hand, in states of great strength, admiration is preferred over goodwill: think of powerful figures or famous beauties. We usually seek others' goodwill in relation to how much we feel we need help or how much we might be at risk from them. That seems to be the biological reasoning, but it doesn't completely capture real life. We crave affection to avoid feeling lonely and to be, as we say, “understood.” This involves empathy, not just goodwill; the person whose affection fulfills us must not only wish us well but also understand what makes us happy. But this leads us to the other essential element of a good life, which is knowledge.

In a perfect world, every sentient being would be to every other the object of the fullest love, compounded of delight, benevolence, and understanding inextricably blended. It does not follow that, in this actual world, we ought to attempt to have such feelings towards all the sentient beings whom we encounter. There are many in whom we cannot feel delight, because they are disgusting; if we were to do violence to our nature by trying to see beauties in them, we should merely blunt our susceptibilities to what we naturally find beautiful. Not to mention human beings, there are fleas and bugs and lice. We should have[27] to be as hard pressed as the Ancient Mariner before we could feel delight in contemplating these creatures. Some saints, it is true, have called them “pearls of God,” but what these men delighted in was the opportunity of displaying their own sanctity.

In an ideal world, each sentient being would be the object of the deepest love from every other, made up of joy, kindness, and understanding all mixed together. However, that doesn't mean we should try to feel this way towards all the sentient beings we meet in our real world. There are many beings we can't feel joy for because they are repulsive; if we force ourselves to find beauty in them, we risk dulling our appreciation for what we genuinely find beautiful. Not to mention, there are fleas, bugs, and lice. We'd have to be as desperate as the Ancient Mariner before we could take any pleasure in looking at these creatures. Some saints have referred to them as "pearls of God," but what they truly enjoyed was the chance to showcase their own piety.[27]

Benevolence is easier to extend widely, but even benevolence has its limits. If a man wished to marry a lady, we should not think the better of him for withdrawing if he found that some one else also wished to marry her: we should regard this as a fair field for competition. Yet his feelings towards a rival cannot be wholly benevolent. I think that in all descriptions of the good life here on earth we must assume a certain basis of animal vitality and animal instinct; without this, life becomes tame and uninteresting. Civilization should be something added to this, not substituted for it; the[28] ascetic saint and the detached sage fail in this respect to be complete human beings. A small number of them may enrich a community; but a world composed of them would die of boredom.

Benevolence is easier to show broadly, but even benevolence has its limits. If a man wants to marry a woman, we shouldn’t think more of him if he backs off under the realization that someone else also wants to marry her: we should see it as a fair competition. Yet, his feelings toward a rival can't be wholly benevolent. I believe that in all discussions of a good life here on earth, we must assume a certain foundation of animal vitality and instinct; without this, life becomes dull and uninteresting. Civilization should enhance this, not replace it; the[28] ascetic saint and the detached sage fall short of being complete human beings. A small number of them may enrich a community, but a world made up of them would be boring.

These considerations lead to a certain emphasis on the element of delight as an ingredient in the best love. Delight, in this actual world, is unavoidably selective, and prevents us from having the same feelings towards all mankind. When conflicts arise between delight and benevolence, they must, as a rule, be decided by a compromise, not by a complete surrender of either. Instinct has its rights, and if we do violence to it beyond a point it takes vengeance in subtle ways. Therefore in aiming at a good life the limits of human possibility must be borne in mind. Here again, however, we are brought back to the necessity of knowledge.

These thoughts highlight the importance of joy as a key part of true love. Joy, in our current world, is naturally selective and prevents us from feeling the same way about everyone. When conflicts occur between joy and kindness, they usually need to be resolved through compromise, not by completely giving up either one. Instinct has its own rights, and if we push it too far, it can retaliate in subtle ways. So, when striving for a good life, we need to remember the limits of what humans can do. Yet again, this brings us back to the need for knowledge.

[29]

[29]

When I speak of knowledge as an ingredient of the good life, I am not thinking of ethical knowledge, but of scientific knowledge and knowledge of particular facts. I do not think there is, strictly speaking, such a thing as ethical knowledge. If we desire to achieve some end, knowledge may show us the means, and this knowledge may loosely pass as ethical. But I do not believe that we can decide what sort of conduct is right or wrong except by reference to its probable consequences. Given an end to be achieved, it is a question for science to discover how to achieve it. All moral rules must be tested by examining whether they tend to realize ends that we desire. I say ends that we desire, not ends that we ought to desire. What we “ought” to desire is merely what someone else wishes us to desire. Usually it is what the authorities wish[30] us to desire—parents, schoolmasters, policemen, and judges. If you say to me “you ought to do so-and-so,” the motive power of your remark lies in my desire for your approval—together, possibly, with rewards or punishments attached to your approval or disapproval. Since all behaviour springs from desire, it is clear that ethical notions can have no importance except as they influenced desire. They do this through the desire for approval and the fear of disapproval. These are powerful social forces, and we shall naturally endeavour to win them to our side if we wish to realize any social purpose. When I say that the morality of conduct is to be judged by its probable consequences, I mean that I desire to see approval given to behaviour likely to realize social purposes which we desire, and disapproval to opposite behaviour. At present this[31] is not done; there are certain traditional rules according to which approval and disapproval are meted out quite regardless of consequences. But this is a topic with which we shall deal in the next chapter.

When I talk about knowledge as a key part of a good life, I’m not referring to ethical knowledge, but rather to scientific knowledge and knowledge of specific facts. I don’t believe there’s really such a thing as ethical knowledge. If we want to achieve a specific outcome, knowledge can show us how to get there, and this knowledge might casually be labeled as ethical. However, I don’t think we can determine what conduct is right or wrong without considering its likely outcomes. Once we have an objective to reach, it’s up to science to figure out how to achieve it. All moral guidelines should be evaluated based on whether they help us achieve goals we want. I say goals we want, not goals we ought to want. What we “ought” to want is simply what someone else wants us to want. Most of the time, it’s what those in authority want—parents, teachers, police officers, and judges. If you tell me, “you ought to do this or that,” the driving force behind your statement is my desire for your approval—along with possibly the rewards or punishments that come with your approval or disapproval. Since all behavior comes from desire, it’s clear that ethical ideas only matter insofar as they influence our desires. They do this through the desire for approval and the fear of disapproval. These are strong social forces, and we’ll typically try to align them with our goals if we want to achieve any social objectives. When I say that the morality of actions should be judged by their likely consequences, I mean that I hope to see approval given to behavior likely to achieve the social goals we want, and disapproval directed at behavior that goes against those goals. Right now, this isn’t happening; there are certain traditional rules that determine approval and disapproval without regard to outcomes. But this is a topic we’ll address in the next chapter.

The superfluity of theoretical ethics is obvious in simple cases. Suppose, for instance, that your child is ill. Love makes you wish to cure it, and science tells you how to do so. There is not an intermediate stage of ethical theory, where it is demonstrated that your child had better be cured. Your act springs directly from desire for an end, together with knowledge of means. This is equally true of all acts, whether good or bad. The ends differ, and the knowledge is more adequate in some cases than in others. But there is no conceivable way of making people do things they do not wish to do. What is possible is to[32] alter their desires by a system of rewards and penalties, among which social approval and disapproval are not the least potent. The question for the legislative moralist is, therefore: How shall this system of rewards and punishments be arranged so as to secure the maximum of what is desired by the legislative authority? If I say that the legislative authority has bad desires, I mean merely that its desires conflict with those of some section of the community to which I belong. Outside human desires there is no moral standard.

The excess of theoretical ethics is clear in straightforward situations. For example, if your child is sick, your love drives you to want to heal them, and science provides the knowledge on how to do that. There isn’t a middle step of ethical theory that proves your child should be cured. Your action comes directly from the desire for a goal, along with the understanding of how to achieve it. This applies to all actions, whether they are good or bad. The goals may differ, and the knowledge may vary in its completeness from one situation to another. However, there’s no way to force people to do things they don’t want to do. What can be done is to change their desires through a system of rewards and penalties, with social approval and disapproval being quite influential. The question for lawmakers is, then: How should this system of rewards and punishments be structured to achieve the greatest amount of what is desired by the legislative authority? If I say that the legislative authority has bad desires, I simply mean that its desires clash with those of a part of the community that I belong to. There is no moral standard outside of human desires.

Thus, what distinguishes ethics from science is not any special kind of knowledge, but merely desire. The knowledge required in ethics is exactly like the knowledge elsewhere; what is peculiar is that certain ends are desired, and that right conduct is what conduces to them. Of course, if the[33] definition of right conduct is to make a wide appeal, the ends must be such as large sections of mankind desire. If I defined right conduct as that which increases my own income, readers would disagree. The whole effectiveness of any ethical argument lies in its scientific part, i. e. in the proof that one kind of conduct, rather than some other, is a means to an end which is widely desired. I distinguish, however, between ethical argument and ethical education. The latter consists in strengthening certain desires and weakening others. This is quite a different process, which will be separately discussed at a later stage.

So, what sets ethics apart from science isn't a special type of knowledge, but simply desire. The knowledge needed in ethics is just like knowledge in other areas; the unique aspect is that certain goals are desired, and that right behavior is what leads to those goals. Of course, if the definition of right behavior is to have a broad appeal, the goals must be ones that large groups of people want. If I defined right behavior as that which increases my own income, most readers would disagree. The strength of any ethical argument lies in its scientific aspect, meaning in proving that one type of behavior, instead of another, is a way to achieve a goal that is widely desired. However, I make a distinction between ethical argument and ethical education. The latter involves reinforcing certain desires and diminishing others. This is a different process, which will be discussed separately later.

We can now explain more exactly the purport of the definition of the good life with which this chapter began. When I said that the good life consists of love guided by knowledge, the desire which prompted me was the[34] desire to live such a life as far as possible, and to see others living it; and the logical content of the statement is that, in a community where men live in this way, more desires will be satisfied than in one where there is less love or less knowledge. I do not mean that such a life is “virtuous” or that its opposite is “sinful,” for these are conceptions which seem to me to have no scientific justification.

We can now explain more clearly what we mean by the definition of the good life that started this chapter. When I said that the good life consists of love guided by knowledge, my motivation came from wanting to live that kind of life as much as possible and to see others living it too. The essence of this statement is that, in a community where people live this way, more desires will be fulfilled than in one where there is less love or knowledge. I’m not suggesting that such a life is “virtuous” or that its opposite is “sinful,” because those ideas don’t seem to have any scientific basis.


[35]

[35]

CHAPTER III
MORAL RULES

The practical need of morals arises from the conflict of desires, whether of different people or of the same person at different times or even at one time. A man desires to drink, and also to be fit for his work next morning. We think him immoral if he adopts the course which gives him the smaller total satisfaction of desire. We think ill of people who are extravagant or reckless, even if they injure no one but themselves. Bentham supposed that the whole of morality could be derived from “enlightened self-interest,” and that a person who always acted with a view to his own maximum satisfaction in the long run would always act rightly. I cannot[36] accept this view. Tyrants have existed who derived exquisite pleasure from watching the infliction of torture; I cannot praise such men when prudence led them to spare their victims’ lives with a view to further sufferings another day. Nevertheless, other things being equal, prudence is a part of the good life. Even Robinson Crusoe had occasion to practise industry, self-control, and foresight, which must be reckoned as moral qualities, since they increased his total satisfaction without counterbalancing injury to others. This part of morals plays a great part in the training of young children, who have little inclination to think of the future. If it were more practised in later life, the world would quickly become a paradise, since it would be quite sufficient to prevent wars, which are acts of passion, not of reason. Nevertheless, in spite[37] of the importance of prudence, it is not the most interesting part of morals. Nor is it the part that raises intellectual problems, since it does not require an appeal to anything beyond self-interest.

The practical need for morals comes from the clash of desires, whether from different people or the same person at different times or even at the same time. A person might want to drink but also wants to be ready for work the next morning. We consider someone immoral if they choose the option that results in the least overall satisfaction of their desires. We look down on people who are extravagant or reckless, even if they only harm themselves. Bentham believed that all of morality could be based on "enlightened self-interest," meaning that a person who consistently acted for their own long-term satisfaction would always do what's right. I can't accept this view. There have been tyrants who took great pleasure in watching others suffer; I can't commend such individuals just because their practical side led them to spare their victims for future torture. Still, other things being equal, being wise is part of a good life. Even Robinson Crusoe had to practice hard work, self-control, and planning, which count as moral qualities since they enhanced his overall satisfaction without hurting anyone else. This aspect of morality is crucial in teaching young children, who often have little regard for the future. If this were more common later in life, the world would quickly become a paradise, as it would likely prevent wars, which are driven by passion, not reason. However, despite the importance of prudence, it’s not the most engaging part of morality. Nor is it the aspect that raises intellectual challenges, since it doesn't require anything beyond self-interest.

The part of morality that is not included in prudence is, in essence, analogous to law, or the rules of a club. It is a method of enabling men to live together in a community in spite of the possibility that their desires may conflict. But here two very different methods are possible. There is the method of the criminal law, which aims at a merely external harmony by attaching disagreeable consequences to acts which thwart other men’s desires in certain ways. This is also the method of social censure: to be thought ill of by one’s own society is a form of punishment, to avoid which most people avoid being[38] known to transgress the code of their set. But there is another method, more fundamental, and far more satisfactory when it succeeds. This is to alter men’s characters and desires in such a way as to minimize occasions of conflict by making the success of one man’s desires as far as possible consistent with that of another’s. That is why love is better than hate, because it brings harmony instead of conflict into the desires of the persons concerned. Two people between whom there is love succeed or fail together, but when two people hate each other the success of either is the failure of the other.

The part of morality that's not covered by prudence is basically similar to law, or the rules of a club. It's a way to help people live together in a community even though their desires might clash. However, there are two very different approaches to achieve this. One is the approach of criminal law, which seeks only external harmony by imposing unpleasant consequences on actions that undermine other people's desires in certain ways. This is also the approach of social judgment: being viewed negatively by one’s own community serves as a kind of punishment, so most people try to avoid being seen as violating the norms of their group. But there's another method that's more fundamental and much more effective when it works. This involves changing people’s characters and desires so that conflicts are reduced by aligning the success of one person’s desires with that of another’s as much as possible. That's why love is better than hate; love fosters harmony instead of discord among the desires of those involved. Two people who are in love either succeed or fail together, but when two people hate each other, the success of one is typically the failure of the other.

If we were right in saying that the good life is inspired by love and guided by knowledge, it is clear that the moral code of any community is not ultimate and self-sufficient, but must be examined with a view to seeing whether[39] it is such as wisdom and benevolence would have decreed. Moral codes have not always been faultless. The Aztecs considered it their painful duty to eat human flesh for fear the light of the sun should grow dim. They erred in their science; and perhaps they would have perceived the scientific error if they had had any love for the sacrificial victims. Some tribes immerse girls in the dark from the age of ten to the age of seventeen, for fear the sun’s rays should render them pregnant. But surely our modern codes of morals contain nothing analogous to these savage practices? Surely we only forbid things which really are harmful, or at any rate so abominable that no decent person could defend them? I am not so sure.

If we’re correct in saying that a good life is driven by love and informed by knowledge, it’s clear that the moral code of any community isn’t final or self-sufficient, but needs to be examined to see if it aligns with what wisdom and kindness would advocate. Moral codes haven’t always been perfect. The Aztecs felt it was their painful duty to eat human flesh for fear that the sun would fade. They made a mistake in their understanding of science; and maybe they would have recognized this error if they had any compassion for their sacrificial victims. Some tribes keep girls in darkness from age ten to seventeen, fearing that sunlight could make them pregnant. But surely our modern moral codes don’t contain anything similar to these brutal practices? Surely we only prohibit things that are genuinely harmful, or at least so terrible that no decent person could defend them? I’m not so sure.

Current morality is a curious blend of utilitarianism and superstition, but the superstitious part has the stronger[40] hold, as is natural, since superstition is the origin of moral rules. Originally, certain acts were thought displeasing to the gods, and were forbidden by law because the divine wrath was apt to descend upon the community, not merely upon the guilty individuals. Hence arose the conception of sin, as that which is displeasing to God. No reason can be assigned as to why certain acts should be thus displeasing; it would be very difficult to say, for instance, why it was displeasing that the kid should be seethed in its mother’s milk. But it was known by Revelation that this was the case. Sometimes the Divine commands have been curiously interpreted. For example, we are told not to work on Saturdays, and Protestants take this to mean that we are not to play on Sundays. But the same sublime authority is attributed to the new prohibition as to the old.

Current morality is an interesting mix of utilitarianism and superstition, but the superstitious aspect holds more influence, as is expected since superstition is the root of moral rules. Initially, certain actions were seen as offensive to the gods, leading to their prohibition by law due to the belief that divine anger could affect the entire community, not just the individuals responsible. This gave rise to the idea of sin as something that displeases God. There’s no clear reason why certain actions are deemed offensive; for example, it’s hard to explain why boiling a kid in its mother’s milk is wrong. However, it was revealed that this was the case. Sometimes, divine commands have been interpreted in strange ways. For instance, we’re told not to work on Saturdays, and Protestants interpret this as a prohibition against playing on Sundays. Yet, the same level of divine authority is given to this new restriction as to the previous one.

[41]

[41]

It is evident that a man with a scientific outlook on life cannot let himself be intimidated by texts of Scripture or by the teaching of the Church. He will not be content to say “such-and-such an act is sinful, and that ends the matter.” He will inquire whether it does any harm, or whether, on the contrary, the belief that it is sinful does harm. And he will find that, especially in what concerns sex, our current morality contains a very great deal of which the origin is purely superstitious. He will find also that this superstition, like that of the Aztecs, involves needless cruelty, and would be swept away if people were actuated by kindly feelings towards their neighbours. But the defenders of traditional morality are seldom people with warm hearts, as may be seen from the love of militarism displayed by Church dignitaries.[42] One is tempted to think that they value morals as affording a legitimate outlet for their desire to inflict pain: the sinner is fair game, and therefore away with tolerance!

It’s clear that a person with a scientific perspective on life cannot be intimidated by scripture or the Church's teachings. They won’t just accept that “such-and-such an act is sinful, and that’s all there is to it.” They will question whether it causes any harm, or if the belief that it is sinful actually does more harm. They will discover that, especially regarding sex, our current morality is rooted in a lot of superstition. They will also see that this superstition, similar to that of the Aztecs, involves unnecessary cruelty, which could disappear if people acted with kindness toward their neighbors. However, those who defend traditional morals are rarely warm-hearted, as evidenced by the militarism shown by church leaders. One might think they value morality as a way to express their desire to inflict pain: sinners are easy targets, so let’s forget about tolerance![42]

Let us follow an ordinary human life from conception to the grave, and note the points where superstitious morals inflict preventable suffering. I begin with conception, because here the influence of superstition is particularly noteworthy. If the parents are not married, the child has a stigma, as clearly undeserved as anything could be. If either of the parents has venereal disease, the child is likely to inherit it. If they already have too many children for the family income, there will be poverty, underfeeding, overcrowding, very likely incest. Yet the great majority of moralists agree that the parents had better not know how to prevent this misery by[43] preventing conception. To please these moralists, a life of torture is inflicted upon millions of human beings who ought never to have existed, merely because it is supposed that sexual intercourse is wicked unless accompanied by desire for offspring, but not wicked when this desire is present, even though the offspring is humanly certain to be wretched. To be killed suddenly and then eaten, which was the fate of the Aztecs’ victims, is a far less degree of suffering than is inflicted upon a child born in miserable surroundings and tainted with venereal disease. Yet it is the greater suffering which is deliberately inflicted by Bishops and politicians in the name of morality. If they had even the smallest spark of love or pity for children they could not adhere to a moral code involving this fiendish cruelty.

Let’s look at an ordinary human life from conception to death and see where superstitious morals cause unnecessary suffering. I start with conception because the effects of superstition are especially noticeable here. If the parents aren’t married, the child carries a stigma that is completely undeserved. If one or both parents have a sexually transmitted infection, the child is likely to inherit it. If they already have too many kids for their income, it leads to poverty, inadequate nutrition, overcrowding, and probably even incest. Yet most moralists agree that the parents should not know how to avoid this misery by preventing conception. To satisfy these moralists, a life of suffering is imposed on millions of people who should never have been born, simply because it’s believed that sexual intercourse is wrong unless there’s a desire for children. But even then, it’s still wrong when it’s known that the child will likely have a miserable life. Being killed suddenly and then eaten, which was the fate of the Aztecs' victims, is actually a much lesser form of suffering than what a child faces when born into horrible conditions and with inherited diseases. Yet it's this greater suffering that's purposely inflicted by bishops and politicians in the name of morality. If they had even a tiny bit of love or compassion for children, they wouldn't follow a moral code that allows this kind of cruelty.

At birth, and in early infancy, the[44] average child suffers more from economic causes than from superstition. When well-to-do women have children, they have the best doctors, the best nurses, the best diet, the best rest, and the best exercise. Working-class women do not enjoy these advantages, and frequently their children die for lack of them. A little is done by the public authorities in the way of care of mothers, but very grudgingly. At a moment when the supply of milk to nursing mothers is being cut down to save expense, public authorities will spend vast sums on paving rich residential districts where there is little traffic. They must know that in taking this decision they are condemning a certain number of working-class children to death for the crime of poverty. Yet the ruling party are supported by the immense majority of ministers of religion, who, with the Pope at their[45] head, have pledged the vast forces of superstition throughout the world to the support of social injustice.

At birth and in early infancy, the[44] average child suffers more from economic issues than from superstition. When wealthy women have children, they receive the best doctors, the best nurses, the best diet, the best rest, and the best exercise. Working-class women don't have these advantages, and often their children die because of it. Public authorities do a little for mother care, but very reluctantly. While the milk supply for nursing mothers is being decreased to save money, public authorities spend huge amounts on paving wealthy neighborhoods where there's hardly any traffic. They must know that by making this decision, they are condemning some working-class children to death due to poverty. Yet the ruling party is backed by the overwhelming majority of religious leaders, who, with the Pope at their[45] head, have harnessed the vast forces of superstition worldwide to uphold social injustice.

In all stages of education the influence of superstition is disastrous. A certain percentage of children have the habit of thinking; one of the aims of education is to cure them of this habit. Inconvenient questions are met with “hush, hush” or with punishment. Collective emotion is used to instil certain kinds of belief, more particularly nationalistic kinds. Capitalists, militarists, and ecclesiastics co-operate in education, because all depend for their power upon the prevalence of emotionalism and the rarity of critical judgment. With the aid of human nature, education succeeds in increasing and intensifying these propensities of the average man.

In every level of education, the impact of superstition is harmful. A certain percentage of kids tend to think critically; one of the goals of education is to change that mindset. Uncomfortable questions are met with “hush, hush” or punishment. Group emotions are used to enforce specific beliefs, especially nationalistic ones. Capitalists, militarists, and religious leaders work together in education because they all rely on emotionalism being more common than critical thinking. By tapping into human nature, education manages to boost and amplify these tendencies in the average person.

Another way in which superstition damages education is through its[46] influence on the choice of teachers. For economic reasons, a woman-teacher must not be married; for moral reasons, she must not have extra-marital sexual relations. And yet everybody who has taken the trouble to study morbid psychology knows that prolonged virginity is, as a rule, extraordinarily harmful to women, so harmful that, in a sane society, it would be severely discouraged in teachers. The restrictions imposed lead more and more to a refusal, on the part of energetic and enterprising women, to enter the teaching profession. This is all due to the lingering influence of superstitious asceticism.

Another way superstition harms education is through its[46] influence on the selection of teachers. For financial reasons, a woman teacher must not be married; for moral reasons, she must not engage in sexual relationships outside of marriage. Yet, anyone who has taken the time to study unhealthy psychology knows that prolonged virginity is usually extremely damaging to women, so damaging that, in a rational society, it would be strongly discouraged for teachers. These restrictions increasingly drive energetic and ambitious women away from the teaching profession. This is all a result of the persistent influence of superstitious asceticism.

At middle- and upper-class schools the matter is even worse. There are chapel services, and the care of morals is in the hands of clergymen. Clergymen, almost necessarily, fail in two ways as teachers of morals. They[47] condemn acts which do no harm, and they condone acts which do great harm. They all condemn sexual relations between unmarried people who are fond of each other but not yet sure that they wish to live together all their lives. Most of them condemn birth-control. None of them condemn the brutality of a husband who causes his wife to die of too frequent pregnancies. I knew a fashionable clergyman whose wife had nine children in nine years. The doctors told him that if she had another she would die. Next year she had another and died. No one condemned him; he retained his benefice, and married again. So long as clergymen continue to condone cruelty and condemn innocent pleasure, they can only do harm as guardians of the morals of the young.

At middle- and upper-class schools, the situation is even worse. There are chapel services, and clergymen are responsible for moral guidance. Unfortunately, clergymen often fail in two significant ways as moral teachers. They criticize actions that don't cause harm while overlooking actions that do significant harm. They all criticize sexual relationships between unmarried couples who care for each other but aren't sure they want to spend their lives together. Most of them condemn birth control. None of them criticize the cruelty of a husband who causes his wife to suffer from frequent pregnancies to the point of death. I knew a well-to-do clergyman whose wife had nine children in nine years. Doctors warned him that if she had another child, she would die. The following year, she had another and died. No one condemned him; he kept his position and remarried. As long as clergymen keep accepting cruelty and condemning innocent pleasures, they can only do harm as guardians of young people's morals.

Another bad effect of superstition on education is the absence of instruction[48] about the facts of sex. The main physiological facts ought to be taught, quite simply and naturally, before puberty, at a time when they are not exciting. At puberty, the elements of an unsuperstitious sexual morality ought to be taught. Boys and girls should be taught that nothing can justify sexual intercourse unless there is mutual inclination. This is contrary to the teaching of the Church, which holds that, provided the parties are married and the man desires another child, sexual intercourse is justified however great may be the reluctance of the wife. Boys and girls should be taught respect for each other’s liberty; they should be made to feel that nothing gives one human being rights over another, and that jealousy and possessiveness kill love. They should be taught that to bring another human being into the world is a very serious[49] matter, only to be undertaken when the child will have a reasonable prospect of health, good surroundings, and parental care. But they should also be taught methods of birth-control, so as to insure that children shall only come when they are wanted. Finally, they should be taught the dangers of venereal disease, and the methods of prevention and cure. The increase of human happiness to be expected from sex-education on these lines is immeasurable.

Another negative impact of superstition on education is the lack of teaching about the facts of sex. The essential physiological facts should be taught simply and naturally before puberty, when they aren't considered exciting. At puberty, the basics of a rational sexual morality should be explained. Boys and girls need to learn that sexual intercourse is only justified when there is mutual desire. This goes against the Church's teaching, which states that as long as the couple is married and the man wants another child, sexual intercourse is acceptable, no matter how reluctant the wife may be. Boys and girls should be taught to respect each other's freedom; they need to understand that nothing gives one person rights over another, and that jealousy and possessiveness destroy love. They should learn that bringing a new person into the world is a serious responsibility that should only be done when the child has a good chance of having health, a supportive environment, and attentive parents. Additionally, they should be informed about birth control methods to ensure that children are only born when they are wanted. Lastly, they should be educated on the risks of sexually transmitted diseases, along with prevention and treatment methods. The potential for increased human happiness from sex education along these lines is immense.

It should be recognized that, in the absence of children, sexual relations are a purely private matter, which does not concern either the State or the neighbours. Certain forms of sex which do not lead to children are at present punished by the criminal law: this is purely superstitious, since the matter is one which affects no one except the parties directly concerned. Where there are children, it is a mistake to[50] suppose that it is necessarily to their interest to make divorce very difficult. Habitual drunkenness, cruelty, insanity are grounds upon which divorce is necessary for the children’s sake quite as much as for the sake of the wife or husband. The peculiar importance attached, at present, to adultery is quite irrational. It is obvious that many forms of misconduct are more fatal to married happiness than an occasional infidelity. Masculine insistence on a child a year, which is not conventionally misconduct or cruelty, is the most fatal of all.

It should be acknowledged that, when there are no children involved, sexual relationships are a completely private matter that doesn’t concern either the State or neighbors. Certain types of sex that don’t result in children are still punished by criminal law: this is purely based on outdated beliefs, as it really only affects the people directly involved. When children are present, it's a mistake to think that making divorce very difficult is necessarily in their best interest. Issues like habitual drunkenness, abuse, and mental illness are valid reasons for divorce, needed for the well-being of the children just as much as for the husband or wife. The excessive focus on adultery today is completely irrational. It's clear that various types of misbehavior can be more damaging to marital happiness than an occasional affair. The pressure for a child every year, which isn’t typically viewed as misconduct or cruelty, can be the most detrimental of all.

Moral rules ought not to be such as to make instinctive happiness impossible. Yet that is an effect of strict monogamy, in a community where the numbers of the two sexes are very unequal. Of course, under such circumstances, the moral rules are infringed. But when the rules are[51] such that they can only be obeyed by greatly diminishing the happiness of the community, and when it is better they should be infringed than observed, surely it is time that the rules were changed. If this is not done, many people who are acting in a way not contrary to the public interest are faced with the undeserved alternative of hypocrisy or obloquy. The Church does not mind hypocrisy, which is a flattering tribute to its power; but elsewhere it has come to be recognized as an evil which we ought not lightly to inflict.

Moral rules shouldn’t be so strict that they make it impossible for people to be happy. However, that’s exactly what happens with strict monogamy in a community where there’s a significant imbalance between the number of men and women. Naturally, in these situations, people end up breaking the rules. But when the rules are set up in a way that they can only be followed by significantly reducing the happiness of the community, and when it’s better to break the rules than to stick to them, it’s definitely time to change those rules. If this doesn’t happen, many people who aren’t harming the public good are unfairly left with the choice between being hypocritical or facing social scorn. The Church doesn’t mind hypocrisy, as it sees it as a flattering display of its influence; but elsewhere, it’s now recognized as a problem that we should not impose lightly.

Even more harmful than theological superstition is the superstition of nationalism, of duty to one’s own State and to no other. But I do not propose on this occasion to discuss this matter, beyond pointing out that limitation to one’s compatriots is contrary to the principle of love which we recognized[52] as constituting the good life. It is also, of course, contrary to enlightened self-interest, since an exclusive nationalism does not pay even the victorious nations.

Even more harmful than religious superstition is the superstition of nationalism, the duty to one’s own country and no one else. However, I don’t intend to go into detail about this right now, except to highlight that limiting our concern to our fellow citizens goes against the principle of love that we identified[52] as essential for a good life. It is also, of course, against enlightened self-interest, since an exclusive nationalism doesn't even benefit the winning countries.

One other respect in which our society suffers from the theological conception of “sin” is the treatment of criminals. The view that criminals are “wicked” and “deserve” punishment is not one which a rational morality can support. Undoubtedly certain people do things which society wishes to prevent, and does right in preventing as far as possible. We may take murder as the plainest case. Obviously, if a community is to hold together and we are to enjoy its pleasures and advantages, we cannot allow people to kill each other whenever they feel an impulse to do so. But this problem should be treated in a purely scientific spirit. We should ask[53] simply: What is the best method of preventing murder? Of two methods which are equally effective in preventing murder, the one involving least harm to the murderer is to be preferred. The harm to the murderer is wholly regrettable, like the pain of a surgical operation. It may be equally necessary, but it is not a subject of rejoicing. The vindictive feeling called “moral indignation” is merely a form of cruelty. Suffering to the criminal can never be justified by the notion of vindictive punishment. If education combined with kindness is equally effective, it is to be preferred; still more is it to be preferred if it is more effective. Of course the prevention of crime and the punishment of crime are two different questions; the object of causing pain to the criminal is presumably deterrent. If prisons were so humanized that a prisoner got a good[54] education for nothing, people might commit crimes in order to qualify for entrance. No doubt prison must be less pleasant than freedom; but the best way to secure this result is to make freedom more pleasant than it sometimes is at present. I do not wish, however, to embark upon the subject of Penal Reform. I merely wish to suggest that we should treat the criminal as we treat a man suffering from plague. Each is a public danger, each must have his liberty curtailed until he has ceased to be a danger. But the man suffering from plague is an object of sympathy and commiseration, whereas the criminal is an object of execration. This is quite irrational. And it is because of this difference of attitude that our prisons are so much less successful in curing criminal tendencies than our hospitals are in curing disease.

One other way our society suffers from the theological idea of "sin" is in how we treat criminals. The belief that criminals are "wicked" and "deserve" punishment isn't one that a rational morality can support. Some people do things that society wants to prevent, and it’s right to stop them as much as possible. Take murder as an obvious example. Clearly, for a community to stick together and for us to enjoy its benefits, we can't allow people to kill each other whenever they feel like it. But we should approach this issue with a scientific mindset. We should simply ask: What is the best way to prevent murder? Of two methods that are equally effective, the one that harms the murderer the least should be chosen. The harm to the murderer is entirely unfortunate, like the pain of a surgical procedure. It might be necessary, but it's not something to celebrate. The vindictive feeling known as "moral indignation" is just a form of cruelty. Inflicting suffering on the criminal can never be justified by the idea of revenge. If education combined with kindness is just as effective, it should be the preferred method; especially if it’s even more effective. Naturally, preventing crime and punishing crime are two separate issues; causing pain to the criminal is presumably meant to deter. If prisons were made so humane that a prisoner received a great education for free, people might actually commit crimes to get in. Surely, prison must be less enjoyable than freedom; but the best way to achieve this is to make freedom more enjoyable than it often is now. However, I don't want to dive into the issue of Penal Reform. I just want to suggest that we should treat criminals like we treat someone suffering from a plague. Both are public risks, and both should have their liberty limited until they are no longer a danger. Yet, the person with the plague is viewed with sympathy and compassion, while the criminal is looked at with disgust. This is completely irrational. And it's this difference in attitude that makes our prisons far less effective at addressing criminal behavior than our hospitals are at treating illness.


[55]

[55]

CHAPTER IV
SALVATION: INDIVIDUAL AND SOCIAL

One of the defects of traditional religion is its individualism, and this defect belongs also to the morality associated with it. Traditionally, the religious life was, as it were, a duologue between the soul and God. To obey the will of God was virtue; and this was possible for the individual quite regardless of the state of the community. Protestant sects developed the idea of “finding salvation”, but it was always present in Christian teaching. This individualism of the separate soul had its value at certain stages of history, but in the modern world we need rather a social than an individual[56] conception of welfare. I want to consider, in this chapter, how this affects our conception of the good life.

One of the flaws of traditional religion is its focus on individualism, and this flaw also applies to the morality linked to it. Traditionally, religious life was like a conversation between the soul and God. Following God’s will was seen as virtuous, and individuals could do this regardless of the community's state. Protestant groups promoted the idea of “finding salvation,” but this concept was always part of Christian teaching. This individualism of the separate soul was valuable at certain points in history, but in today's world, we need a social rather than an individual[56] view of welfare. In this chapter, I want to explore how this impacts our understanding of the good life.

Christianity arose in the Roman Empire among populations wholly destitute of political power, whose national States had been destroyed and merged in a vast impersonal aggregate. During the first three centuries of the Christian Era, the individuals who adopted Christianity could not alter the social or political institutions under which they lived, although they were profoundly convinced of their badness. In these circumstances, it was natural that they should adopt the belief that an individual may be perfect in an imperfect world, and that the good life has nothing to do with this world. What I mean may become plain by comparison with Plato’s Republic. When Plato wanted to describe the good[57] life, he described a whole community, not an individual; he did so in order to define justice, which is an essentially social conception. He was accustomed to citizenship of a Republic, and political responsibility was something which he took for granted. With the loss of Greek freedom comes the rise of Stoicism, which is like Christianity, and unlike Plato, in having an individualistic conception of the good life.

Christianity emerged in the Roman Empire among people who had no political power, whose nation-states had been destroyed and merged into a vast, impersonal system. During the first three centuries of the Christian Era, those who embraced Christianity couldn’t change the social or political systems they lived under, even though they strongly believed those systems were wrong. Given these conditions, it was natural for them to adopt the belief that a person can be perfect in an imperfect world and that a good life isn't tied to this world. This idea can be clarified by comparing it to Plato’s Republic. When Plato wanted to describe the good life, he talked about an entire community, not just an individual; he did this to define justice, which is fundamentally a social idea. He was used to the citizenship of a Republic, and political responsibility was a given for him. With the loss of Greek freedom came the rise of Stoicism, which is similar to Christianity and different from Plato, as it has an individualistic view of the good life.

We, who belong to great democracies, should find a more appropriate morality in free Athens than in despotic Imperial Rome. In India, where the political circumstances are very similar to those of Judea in the time of Christ, we find Gandhi preaching a very similar morality to Christ’s, and being punished for it by the christianized successors of Pontius Pilate. But the more extreme Indian nationalists[58] are not content with individual salvation: they want national salvation. In this they have taken on the outlook of the free democracies of the West. I want to suggest some respects in which this outlook, owing to Christian influences, is not yet sufficiently bold and self-conscious, but is still hampered by the belief in individual salvation.

We, who are part of great democracies, should find a more fitting sense of morality in free Athens than in the oppressive Imperial Rome. In India, where the political scene closely resembles that of Judea during Christ's time, we see Gandhi advocating a morality similar to Christ's, and facing punishment from the Christian successors of Pontius Pilate. However, the more radical Indian nationalists[58] are not satisfied with just individual salvation; they seek national salvation. In this, they have adopted the perspective of the free democracies of the West. I want to point out some ways in which this perspective, influenced by Christianity, is still not bold and self-aware enough, but is instead held back by the idea of individual salvation.

The good life, as we conceive it, demands a multitude of social conditions, and cannot be realized without them. The good life, we said, is a life inspired by love and guided by knowledge. The knowledge required can only exist where governments or millionaires devote themselves to its discovery and diffusion. For example: the spread of cancer is alarming—what are we to do about it? At the moment, no one can answer the question for lack of knowledge; and the knowledge is not likely to emerge except through[59] endowed research. Again: knowledge of science, history, literature, and art ought to be attainable by all who desire it; this requires elaborate arrangements on the part of public authorities, and is not to be achieved by means of religious conversion. Then there is foreign trade, without which half the inhabitants of Great Britain would starve; and if we were starving very few of us would live the good life. It is needless to multiply examples. The important point is that, in all that differentiates between a good life and a bad one, the world is a unity, and the man who pretends to live independently is a conscious or unconscious parasite.

The good life, as we see it, needs a variety of social conditions and can’t be achieved without them. The good life, as we mentioned, is one that’s driven by love and guided by knowledge. The knowledge we need can only exist where governments or wealthy individuals commit to its discovery and sharing. For instance, the increase in cancer cases is concerning—what should we do about it? Right now, no one has the answer due to a lack of knowledge, and that knowledge is unlikely to develop except through[59] funded research. Furthermore, knowledge of science, history, literature, and art should be accessible to everyone who wants it; this requires significant efforts from public authorities and can’t be achieved through religious conversion. Then there’s foreign trade, without which half the people in Great Britain would starve; and if we were starving, very few of us would be living the good life. It’s unnecessary to provide more examples. The key point is that, in everything that separates a good life from a bad one, the world is interconnected, and anyone who claims to live independently is either knowingly or unknowingly a parasite.

The idea of individual salvation, with which the early Christians consoled themselves for their political subjection, becomes impossible as soon as we escape from a very narrow conception of the good life. In the orthodox[60] Christian conception, the good life is the virtuous life, and virtue consists in obedience to the will of God, and the will of God is revealed to each individual through the voice of conscience. This whole conception is that of men subject to an alien despotism. The good life involves much besides virtue—intelligence, for instance. And conscience is a most fallacious guide, since it consists of vague reminiscences of precepts heard in early youth, so that it is never wiser than its possessor’s nurse or mother. To live a good life in the fullest sense a man must have a good education, friends, love, children (if he desires them), a sufficient income to keep him from want and grave anxiety, good health, and work which is not uninteresting. All these things, in varying degrees, depend upon the community, and are helped or hindered by political events. The good life must[61] be lived in a good society, and is not fully possible otherwise.

The idea of personal salvation, which early Christians used to comfort themselves during their political oppression, becomes unrealistic once we move beyond a very narrow view of the good life. In the traditional Christian view, the good life is about living virtuously, and virtue means following the will of God, which is revealed to each person through their conscience. This entire viewpoint comes from people subject to an external tyranny. The good life involves much more than just virtue—intelligence is one example. Additionally, conscience can be a misleading guide, as it mainly consists of vague memories of lessons learned in childhood, making it no smarter than the caregiver or mother of the person. To truly live a good life, a person needs a solid education, friends, love, children (if they want them), enough income to avoid hardship and serious stress, good health, and work that is engaging. All these factors, to different extents, rely on the community and can be influenced by political circumstances. The good life must be experienced in a good society; otherwise, it is not fully achievable.

This is the fundamental defect of the aristocratic ideal. Certain good things, such as art and science and friendship, can flourish very well in an aristocratic society. They existed in Greece on a basis of slavery; they exist among ourselves on a basis of exploitation. But love, in the form of sympathy or benevolence, cannot exist freely in an aristocratic society. The aristocrat has to persuade himself that the slave or proletarian or coloured man is of inferior clay, and that his sufferings do not matter. At the present moment, polished English gentlemen flog Africans so severely that they die after hours of unspeakable anguish. Even if these gentlemen are well-educated, artistic, and admirable conversationalists, I cannot admit that they are living the good life. Human nature[62] imposes some limitation of sympathy, but not such a degree as that. In a democratically-minded society, only a maniac would behave in this way. The limitation of sympathy involved in the aristocratic ideal is its condemnation. Salvation is an aristocratic ideal, because it is individualistic. For this reason, also, the idea of personal salvation, however interpreted and expanded, cannot serve for the definition of the good life.

This is the main flaw of the aristocratic ideal. Certain good things, like art, science, and friendship, can thrive in an aristocratic society. They existed in Greece on the foundation of slavery; they exist among us based on exploitation. But love, in the form of sympathy or kindness, cannot exist freely in an aristocratic society. The aristocrat has to convince himself that the slave, the working class, or the person of color is of an inferior nature and that their suffering doesn't matter. Right now, refined English gentlemen are beating Africans so brutally that they die after hours of unimaginable pain. Even if these gentlemen are well-educated, artistic, and great conversationalists, I can't say they are living a good life. Human nature[62] imposes some limits on sympathy, but not to that extreme. In a society with democratic values, only a madman would act this way. The limitation of sympathy inherent in the aristocratic ideal is its downfall. Salvation is an aristocratic ideal because it is individualistic. For this reason, the concept of personal salvation, no matter how it is interpreted or expanded, cannot define the good life.

Another characteristic of salvation is that it results from a catastrophic change, like the conversion of Saint Paul. Shelley’s poems afford an illustration of this conception applied to societies; the moment comes when everybody is converted, the “anarchs” fly, and “the world’s great age begins anew”. It may be said that a poet is an unimportant person, whose ideas are of no consequence. But I am persuaded[63] that a large proportion of revolutionary leaders have had ideas extremely like Shelley’s. They have thought that misery and cruelty and degradation were due to tyrants or priests or capitalists or Germans, and that if these sources of evil were overthrown there would be a general change of heart and we should all live happy ever after. Holding these beliefs, they have been willing to wage a “war to end war”. Comparatively fortunate were those who suffered defeat or death; those who had the misfortune to emerge victorious were reduced to cynicism and despair by the failure of all their glowing hopes. The ultimate source of these hopes was the Christian doctrine of catastrophic conversion as the road to salvation.

Another characteristic of salvation is that it comes from a dramatic change, like Saint Paul's conversion. Shelley’s poems illustrate this idea as applied to societies; the moment arrives when everyone is converted, the “anarchs” flee, and “the world’s great age begins anew.” Some may say that a poet is unimportant, and their ideas don't matter. But I believe[63] that many revolutionary leaders have shared ideas very similar to Shelley’s. They believed that misery, cruelty, and degradation were caused by tyrants, priests, capitalists, or Germans, and that if these sources of evil were overthrown, there would be a widespread change of heart and we would all live happily ever after. Holding these beliefs, they were willing to fight a “war to end war.” Those who suffered defeat or death were comparatively lucky; those who managed to win were left feeling cynical and hopeless because their bright hopes never materialized. The root of these hopes was the Christian idea of catastrophic conversion as the path to salvation.

I do not wish to suggest that revolutions are never necessary, but I do wish to suggest that they are not short cuts[64] to the millennium. There is no short cut to the good life, whether individual or social. To build up the good life, we must build up intelligence, self-control, and sympathy. This is a quantitative matter, a matter of gradual improvement, of early training, of educational experiment. Only impatience prompts the belief in the possibility of sudden improvement. The gradual improvement that is possible, and the methods by which it may be achieved, are a matter for future science. But something can be said now. Some part of what can be said I shall try to indicate in a final chapter.

I’m not saying that revolutions are never necessary, but I do want to point out that they aren’t shortcuts[64] to a better future. There’s no shortcut to living well, whether on a personal or social level. To create a good life, we need to develop intelligence, self-control, and empathy. This is a gradual process, requiring improvement over time, early training, and educational experimentation. Only impatience leads to the idea that sudden change is possible. The steady progress that can be made, along with the ways to achieve it, will be dealt with by future science. However, there’s something we can discuss right now. I’ll try to outline some of that in a final chapter.


[65]

[65]

CHAPTER V
SCIENCE AND HAPPINESS

The purpose of the moralist is to improve men’s behaviour. This is a laudable ambition, since their behaviour is for the most part deplorable. But I cannot praise the moralist either for the particular improvements he desires, or for the methods he adopts for achieving them. His ostensible method is moral exhortation; his real method (if he is orthodox) is a system of economic rewards and punishments. The former effects nothing permanent or important; the influence of revivalists, from Savonarola downwards, has always been very transitory. The latter—the rewards and punishments—have[66] a very considerable effect. They cause a man, for example, to prefer casual prostitutes to a quasi-permanent mistress, because it is necessary to adopt the method which is most easily concealed. They thus keep up the numbers of a very dangerous profession, and secure the prevalence of venereal disease. These are not the objects desired by the moralist, and he is too unscientific to notice that they are the objects which he actually achieves.

The goal of the moralist is to improve people's behavior. This is a commendable aim, given that their behavior is often quite bad. However, I can't commend the moralist for the specific improvements he seeks or the methods he uses to get there. His stated method is moral urging; his real method (if he follows traditional views) is a system of economic rewards and punishments. The first approach doesn't produce anything lasting or significant; the impact of revivalists, from Savonarola to the present, has always been quite fleeting. The latter—the rewards and punishments—have[66] a significant impact. For instance, they lead a man to prefer casual sex with prostitutes over having a more stable partner, simply because the former method is easier to hide. This approach maintains the number of people in this risky profession and contributes to the spread of sexually transmitted diseases. These outcomes are not what the moralist intends, and he is too unscientific to realize that these are the results he actually creates.

Is there anything better to be substituted for this unscientific mixture of preaching and bribery? I think there is.

Is there anything better to replace this unscientific mix of preaching and bribery? I think there is.

Men’s actions are harmful either from ignorance or from bad desires. “Bad” desires, when we are speaking from a social point of view, may be defined as those which tend to thwart the desires of others, or, more exactly, those which thwart more desires than[67] they assist. It is not necessary to dwell upon the harmfulness that springs from ignorance; here, more knowledge is all that is wanted, so that the road to improvement lies in more research and more education. But the harmfulness that springs from bad desires is a more difficult matter.

Men's actions are harmful either out of ignorance or from selfish desires. “Selfish” desires, in a social context, can be defined as those that undermine the desires of others or, more specifically, those that frustrate more desires than they fulfill.[67] It's not necessary to focus on the harm caused by ignorance; in that case, we simply need more knowledge, meaning the path to improvement involves more research and education. However, the harm that comes from selfish desires is a more complex issue.

In the ordinary man and woman there is a certain amount of active malevolence, both special ill-will directed to particular enemies and general impersonal pleasure in the misfortunes of others. It is customary to cover this over with fine phrases; about half of conventional morality is a cloak for it. But it must be faced if the moralists’ aim of improving our actions is to be achieved. It is shown in a thousand ways, great and small: in the glee with which people repeat and believe scandal, in the unkind treatment of criminals in spite of clear[68] proof that better treatment would have more effect in reforming them, in the unbelievable barbarity with which all white races treat negroes, and in the gusto with which old ladies and clergymen pointed out the duty of military service to young men during the War. Even children may be the objects of wanton cruelty: David Copperfield and Oliver Twist are by no means imaginary. This active malevolence is the worst feature of human nature, and the one which it is most necessary to change if the world is to grow happier. Probably this one cause has more to do with war than all the economic and political causes put together.

In ordinary people, there’s a fair amount of active animosity, including targeted hostility towards specific enemies and a general, impersonal enjoyment of others’ misfortunes. It’s common to mask this with nice words; about half of traditional morality serves as a disguise for it. However, if moralists want to improve our actions, we have to confront this issue. It shows up in countless ways, big and small: in the eagerness with which people spread and believe gossip, in the harsh treatment of criminals despite clear evidence that better treatment would be more effective in reforming them, in the shocking cruelty with which all white groups treat Black individuals, and in the enthusiasm with which elderly women and clergymen emphasized the importance of military service for young men during the War. Even children can be victims of senseless cruelty: David Copperfield and Oliver Twist are not purely fictional. This active malevolence is the worst aspect of human nature, and it’s crucial to change it if the world is to become a happier place. This single cause likely contributes more to war than all economic and political reasons combined.

Given this problem of preventing malevolence, how shall we deal with it? First let us try to understand its causes. These are, I think, partly social, partly physiological. The world,[69] now as much as at any former time, is based upon life-and-death competition; the question at issue in the War was whether German or Allied children should die of want and starvation. (Apart from malevolence on both sides, there was not the slightest reason why both should not survive). Most people have in the background of their minds a haunting fear of ruin; this is especially true of people who have children. The rich fear that Bolsheviks will confiscate their investments; the poor fear that they will lose their job or their health. Every one is engaged in the frantic pursuit of “security”, and imagines that this is to be achieved by keeping potential enemies in subjection. It is in moments of panic that cruelty becomes most wide-spread and most atrocious. Reactionaries everywhere appeal to fear: in England, to fear of Bolshevism; in France, to[70] fear of Germany; in Germany, to fear of France. And the sole effect of their appeals is to increase the danger against which they wish to be protected.

Given this problem of preventing malevolence, how should we handle it? First, let’s try to understand what causes it. I think these causes are partly social and partly physiological. The world, [69] just as much today as in the past, is based on life-and-death competition; the issue during the War was whether German or Allied children would die from want and starvation. (Leaving aside the malevolence on both sides, there was no real reason for both sides not to survive.) Most people have a lingering fear of ruin in the back of their minds; this is especially true for those with children. The rich worry that Bolsheviks will seize their investments; the poor fear losing their jobs or health. Everyone is desperately trying to find “security,” believing it comes from keeping potential enemies under control. It’s during moments of panic that cruelty spreads the most and becomes the most brutal. Reactionaries everywhere tap into fear: in England, they appeal to fear of Bolshevism; in France, to fear of Germany; in Germany, to fear of France. The only result of their appeals is to increase the very danger they claim to protect against.

It must, therefore, be one of the chief concerns of the scientific moralist to combat fear. This can be done in two ways: by increasing security, and by cultivating courage. I am speaking of fear as an irrational passion, not of the rational prevision of possible misfortune. When a theatre catches fire, the rational man foresees disaster just as clearly as the man stricken with panic, but he adopts methods likely to diminish the disaster, whereas the man stricken with panic increases it. Europe since 1914 has been like a panic-stricken audience in a theatre on fire; what is needed is calm, authoritative directions as to how to escape without trampling each other to pieces in the process. The Victorian age, for all its humbug, was a[71] period of rapid progress, because men were dominated by hope rather than fear. If we are again to have progress, we must again be dominated by hope.

It should, therefore, be one of the main concerns of the scientific moralist to tackle fear. This can be achieved in two ways: by improving security and by fostering courage. I’m talking about fear as an irrational emotion, not the rational anticipation of potential misfortune. When a theater catches fire, the rational person sees the impending disaster just as clearly as someone who is overcome with panic, but the rational person takes steps to reduce the impact, while the panicked person only makes it worse. Europe since 1914 has been like a panicked audience in a burning theater; what we need is calm, authoritative guidance on how to escape without crushing one another in the process. The Victorian era, despite its pretenses, was a[71] time of rapid progress because people were driven more by hope than fear. If we want progress again, we need to be driven by hope once more.

Everything that increases the general security is likely to diminish cruelty. This applies to prevention of war, whether through the instrumentality of the League of Nations, or otherwise; to prevention of destitution; to better health by improvement in medicine, hygiene, and sanitation; and to all other methods of lessening the terrors that lurk in the abysses of men’s minds and emerge as nightmares when they sleep. But nothing is accomplished by an attempt to make a portion of mankind secure at the expense of another portion—Frenchmen at the expense of Germans, capitalists at the expense of wage-earners, white men at the expense of yellow men, and so on. Such methods only increase terror in the dominant[72] group, lest just resentment should lead the oppressed to rebel. Only justice can give security; and by “justice” I mean the recognition of the equal claims of all human beings.

Everything that boosts overall safety is likely to reduce cruelty. This applies to preventing war, whether through the League of Nations or other means; preventing poverty; improving health through advancements in medicine, hygiene, and sanitation; and all other ways of reducing the fears that dwell in the depths of people's minds and surface as nightmares when they sleep. However, nothing is achieved by trying to make one part of humanity secure at the expense of another part—like making French people secure at the expense of Germans, or capitalists at the expense of workers, or white people at the expense of people of color, and so on. Such approaches only heighten fear among the dominant group, as they worry that rising resentment will lead the oppressed to revolt. Only justice can provide security; and by "justice," I mean recognizing the equal rights of all human beings.

In addition to social changes designed to bring security, there is, however, another and more direct means of diminishing fear, namely by a regimen designed to increase courage. Owing to the importance of courage in battle, men early discovered means of increasing it by education and diet—eating human flesh, for example, was supposed to be useful. But military courage was to be the prerogative of the ruling caste: Spartans were to have more than helots, British officers than Indian privates, men than women, and so on. For centuries it was supposed to be the privilege of the aristocracy. Every increase of courage in the ruling caste was used to increase the burdens[73] on the oppressed, and therefore to increase the grounds for fear in the oppressors, and therefore to leave the causes of cruelty undiminished. Courage must be democratized before it can make men humane.

Along with social changes aimed at providing security, there’s another, more straightforward way to reduce fear: through a system designed to boost courage. Because courage is crucial in battle, people have long found ways to enhance it through education and diet—eating human flesh, for instance, was thought to be beneficial. However, military courage has usually been reserved for the ruling class: Spartans were supposed to have more than helots, British officers more than Indian soldiers, men more than women, and so on. For centuries, it was considered the privilege of the aristocracy. Every increase in courage for the ruling class only served to raise the burdens on the oppressed, which in turn increased the fear among the oppressors and allowed the roots of cruelty to persist. Courage needs to be made accessible to everyone before it can lead to humanity.

To a great extent, courage has already been democratized by recent events. The suffragettes showed that they possessed as much courage as the bravest men; this demonstration was essential in winning them the vote. The common soldier in the War needed as much courage as a Captain or Lieutenant, and much more than a General: this had much to do with his lack of servility after demobilization. The Bolsheviks, who proclaim themselves the champions of the proletariat, are not lacking in courage, whatever else may be said of them; this is proved by their pre-revolutionary record. In Japan, where formerly the samurai had[74] a monopoly of martial ardour, conscription brought the need of courage throughout the male population. Thus among all the Great Powers much has been done during the past half-century to make courage no longer an aristocratic monopoly: if this were not the case, the danger to democracy would be far greater than it is.

To a large extent, courage has already been made accessible to everyone by recent events. The suffragettes proved that they had as much courage as the bravest men; this was essential in securing their right to vote. The average soldier in the War needed as much courage as a Captain or Lieutenant, and even more than a General: this greatly affected their mindset after returning from service. The Bolsheviks, who call themselves the champions of the working class, are not lacking in courage, regardless of what else might be said about them; their pre-revolutionary actions prove this. In Japan, where the samurai once had a monopoly on martial spirit, conscription spread the need for courage throughout the male population. Thus, among all the Great Powers, significant progress has been made over the past fifty years to ensure that courage is no longer just an aristocratic privilege: if that were not the case, the threat to democracy would be much greater than it currently is.

But courage in fighting is by no means the only form, nor perhaps even the most important. There is courage in facing poverty, courage in facing derision, courage in facing the hostility of one’s own herd. In these, the bravest soldiers are often lamentably deficient. And above all there is the courage to think calmly and rationally in the face of danger, and to control the impulse of panic fear or panic rage. These are certainly things which education can help to give. And the teaching of every form of courage is rendered[75] easier by good health, good physique, adequate nourishment, and free play for fundamental vital impulses. Perhaps the physiological sources of courage could be discovered by comparing the blood of a cat with that of a rabbit. In all likelihood there is no limit to what science could do in the way of increasing courage, by example, experience of danger, an athletic life, and a suitable diet. All these things our upper-class boys to a great extent enjoy, but as yet they are in the main the prerogative of wealth. The courage so far encouraged in the poorer sections of the community is courage under orders, not the kind that involves initiative and leadership. When the qualities that now confer leadership have become universal, there will no longer be leaders and followers, and democracy will have been realized at last.

But bravery in combat is definitely not the only type, nor is it maybe even the most important. There's bravery in dealing with poverty, bravery in enduring ridicule, and bravery in facing the hostility of one’s own group. In these areas, the bravest soldiers often fall short. Above all, there’s the courage to think clearly and rationally in the face of danger and to manage the impulse of panic, fear, or rage. These are certainly things that education can help cultivate. Teaching all forms of courage is made easier by good health, physical fitness, proper nutrition, and allowing for basic healthy impulses. Perhaps we could uncover the physiological roots of courage by comparing the blood of a cat with that of a rabbit. It’s very likely that there are no limits to what science could achieve in boosting courage through example, experience with danger, an active lifestyle, and a balanced diet. All these benefits our upper-class boys largely enjoy, but for now, they mostly belong to the wealthy. The courage that has been encouraged in the poorer parts of the community is primarily obedience-based, not the kind that requires initiative and leadership. When the qualities that currently grant leadership become widespread, there will no longer be leaders and followers, and democracy will finally have been realized.

[76]

[76]

But fear is not the only source of malevolence; envy and disappointment also have their share. The envy of cripples and hunchbacks is proverbial as a source of malignity, but other misfortunes than theirs produce similar results. A man or woman who has been thwarted sexually is apt to be full of envy; this generally takes the form of moral condemnation of the more fortunate. Much of the driving force of revolutionary movement is due to envy of the rich. Jealousy is, of course, a special form of envy: envy of love. The old often envy the young; when they do, they are apt to treat them cruelly.

But fear isn’t the only source of evil; envy and disappointment also play a role. The envy of people with disabilities is a well-known source of bitterness, but other misfortunes can lead to similar feelings. A man or woman who has been denied love is likely to be filled with envy; this often shows up as moral judgment against those who are more fortunate. A lot of the motivation behind revolutionary movements comes from envy of the wealthy. Jealousy is, of course, a specific form of envy: the envy of love. Older people often envy the young; when they do, they are likely to treat them harshly.

There is, so far as I know, no way of dealing with envy except to make the lives of the envious happier and fuller, and to encourage in youth the idea of collective enterprises rather than competition. The worst forms of envy are[77] in those who have not had a full life in the way of marriage, or children, or career. Such misfortunes could in most cases be avoided by better social institutions. Still, it must be admitted that a residuum of envy is likely to remain. There are many instances in history of Generals so jealous of each other that they preferred defeat to enhancement of the other’s reputation. Two politicians of the same party, or two artists of the same school are almost sure to be jealous of one another. In such cases, there seems nothing to be done except to arrange, as far as possible, that each competitor shall be unable to injure the other, and shall only be able to win by superior merit. An artist’s jealousy of a rival usually does little harm, because the only effective way of indulging it is to paint better pictures than his rival’s, since it is not open to him to destroy his rival’s[78] pictures. Where envy is unavoidable, it must be used as a stimulus to one’s own efforts, not to the thwarting of the efforts of rivals.

As far as I know, the only way to handle envy is to make the lives of those who are envious happier and more fulfilling, and to promote the idea of collaboration over competition in young people. The most severe forms of envy are seen in those who haven't experienced a full life through marriage, children, or a successful career. Most of these situations could be prevented with better social institutions. However, it's important to recognize that some level of envy is likely to linger. History is filled with examples of generals so jealous of each other that they would rather face defeat than let the other gain recognition. Two politicians from the same party or two artists from the same movement are almost guaranteed to envy one another. In these situations, the best approach is to ensure that neither competitor can harm the other, and that each can only succeed through their own merits. An artist's jealousy of a rival typically causes little damage because the most effective way to express it is to create better artwork than their rival's; they can't simply destroy their competitor's pieces. When envy is unavoidable, it should serve as motivation for personal improvement, not as a means to undermine the efforts of others.

The possibilities of science in the way of increasing human happiness are not confined to diminishing those aspects of human nature which make for mutual defeat, and which we therefore call “bad”. There is probably no limit to what science can do in the way of increasing positive excellence. Health has already been greatly improved; in spite of the lamentations of those who idealize the past, we live longer and have fewer illnesses than any class or nation in the eighteenth century. With a little more application of the knowledge we already possess, we might be much healthier than we are. And future discoveries are likely to accelerate this process enormously.

The potential of science to enhance human happiness isn't just about reducing the negative aspects of human nature that lead to conflict, which we label as "bad." There's likely no limit to what science can achieve in boosting positive qualities. Our health has already seen significant improvements; despite the nostalgia of those who romanticize the past, we live longer and experience fewer illnesses than any class or country in the eighteenth century. With a bit more focus on the knowledge we already have, we could be much healthier than we currently are. Furthermore, future discoveries are expected to greatly speed up this progress.

So far, it has been physical science[79] that has had most effect upon our lives, but in the future physiology and psychology are likely to be far more potent. When we have discovered how character depends upon physiological conditions, we shall be able, if we choose, to produce far more of the type of human beings that we admire. Intelligence, artistic capacity, benevolence—all these things no doubt could be increased by science. There seems scarcely any limit to what could be done in the way of producing a good world, if only men would use science wisely. I have expressed elsewhere my fears that men may not make a wise use of the power they derive from science.[B] At present I am concerned with the good that men could do if they chose, not with the question whether they will choose rather to do harm.

So far, physical science[79] has had the biggest impact on our lives, but in the future, physiology and psychology are likely to be much more powerful. Once we understand how character is influenced by physiological factors, we will be able, if we decide to, to create more of the kinds of human beings we admire. Intelligence, artistic ability, kindness—all of these could undoubtedly be enhanced by science. There seems to be almost no limit to what could be achieved in terms of creating a better world, as long as people use science wisely. I've shared my concerns before that people may not use the power they gain from science wisely.[B] Right now, I’m focused on the good that people could do if they chose to, not on whether they might choose to do harm.

[B] See Icarus.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Check out Icarus.

There is a certain attitude about the[80] application of science to human life with which I have some sympathy, though I do not, in the last analysis, agree with it. It is the attitude of those who dread what is “unnatural.” Rousseau is, of course, the great protagonist of this view in Europe. In Asia, Lao-Tze has set it forth even more persuasively, and 2400 years sooner. I think there is a mixture of truth and falsehood in the admiration of “nature,” which it is important to disentangle. To begin with, what is “natural”? Roughly speaking, anything to which the speaker was accustomed in childhood. Lao-Tze objects to roads and carriages and boats, all of which were probably unknown in the village where he was born. Rousseau has got used to these things, and does not regard them as against nature. But he would no doubt have thundered against railways if he had[81] lived to see them. Clothes and cooking are too ancient to be denounced by most of the apostles of nature, though they all object to new fashions in either. Birth-control is thought wicked by people who tolerate celibacy, because the former is a new violation of nature and the latter an ancient one. In all these ways those who preach “nature” are inconsistent, and one is tempted to regard them as mere conservatives.

There’s a certain attitude towards the
[80] application of science to human life that I can relate to, but ultimately, I don’t fully agree with it. It’s the mindset of those who fear what is “unnatural.” Rousseau is, of course, the main advocate of this perspective in Europe. In Asia, Lao-Tze expressed it even more convincingly, and 2400 years earlier. I believe there’s a mix of truth and falsehood in the admiration for “nature” that needs to be clarified. First, what does “natural” even mean? Generally, it refers to anything the speaker was familiar with during childhood. Lao-Tze criticizes roads, carriages, and boats, all of which were likely unknown in the village where he was born. Rousseau, on the other hand, has adapted to these things and doesn’t see them as opposed to nature. But he would certainly have been outraged by railways if he had
[81] lived to witness them. Clothes and cooking are too old to be condemned by most advocates of nature, although they all complain about new styles in either. Birth control is considered immoral by people who accept celibacy because the former is seen as a new breach of nature, while the latter is an old one. In all these instances, those who promote “nature” are inconsistent, making it tempting to view them as mere conservatives.

Nevertheless, there is something to be said in their favour. Take for instance vitamines, the discovery of which has produced a revulsion in favour of “natural” foods. It seems, however, that vitamines can be supplied by cod-liver oil and electric light, which are certainly not part of the “natural” diet of a human being. This case illustrates that, in the absence of knowledge, unexpected harm may be done by a new departure from nature; but[82] when the harm has come to be understood it can usually be remedied by some new artificiality. As regards our physical environment and our physical means of gratifying our desires, I do not think the doctrine of “nature” justifies anything beyond a certain experimental caution in the adoption of new expedients. Clothes, for instance, are contrary to nature, and need to be supplemented by another unnatural practice, namely washing, if they are not to bring disease. But the two practices together make a man healthier than the savage who eschews both.

Nevertheless, there are definitely some positives to consider. For example, the discovery of vitamins has sparked a movement towards “natural” foods. However, it turns out that vitamins can also be found in cod-liver oil and electric light, which are definitely not part of a human’s “natural” diet. This example shows that without proper knowledge, new approaches that stray from nature can unintentionally cause harm; but once the harm is understood, it can typically be fixed through some new artificial solution. Regarding our physical environment and ways to satisfy our desires, I don't think the idea of “nature” justifies anything more than cautious experimentation when trying out new methods. Clothing, for instance, goes against nature and has to be cleaned—another unnatural practice—to avoid disease. Yet, together, these two practices make a person healthier than someone who avoids both.

There is much more to be said for “nature” in the realm of human desires. To force upon man, woman, or child a life which thwarts their strongest impulses is both cruel and dangerous in this sense, a life according to “nature” is to be commended with certain provisos. Nothing could be[83] more artificial than an underground electric railway, but no violence is done to a child’s nature when it is taken to travel in one; on the contrary, almost all children find the experience delightful. Artificialities which gratify the desires of ordinary human beings are good, other things being equal. But there is nothing to be said for ways of life which are artificial in the sense of being imposed by authority or economic necessity. Such ways of life are, no doubt, to some extent necessary at present; ocean travel would become very difficult if there were no stokers on steamers. But necessities of this kind are regrettable, and we ought to look for ways of avoiding them. A certain amount of work is not a thing to complain of; indeed, in nine cases out of ten, it makes a man happier than complete idleness. But the amount and kind of work that most people[84] have to do at present is a grave evil: especially bad is the life-long bondage to routine. Life should not be too closely regulated or too methodical; our impulses, when not positively destructive or injurious to others, ought if possible to have free play; there should be room for adventure. Human nature we should respect, because our impulses and desires are the stuff out of which our happiness is to be made. It is no use to give men something abstractly considered “good”; we must give them something desired or needed if we are to add to their happiness. Science may learn in time to mould our desires so that they shall not conflict with those of other people to the same extent as they do now; then we shall be able to satisfy a larger proportion of our desires than at present. In that sense, but in that sense only, our desires will then have become “better.”[85] A single desire is no better and no worse, considered in isolation, than any other; but a group of desires is better than another group if all of the first group can be satisfied simultaneously while in the second group some are inconsistent with others. That is why love is better than hatred.

There’s a lot more to consider about “nature” when it comes to human desires. To force a man, woman, or child into a life that suppresses their deepest instincts is both cruel and dangerous. A life that aligns with “nature” should be praised with certain conditions. Nothing could be more artificial than an underground electric train, but it doesn’t harm a child’s nature to travel on one; in fact, most kids find the experience joyful. Artificial things that satisfy the desires of everyday people are good, as long as other factors are equal. However, there’s nothing positive about lifestyles that are artificial due to being imposed by authority or economic pressures. While such lifestyles might be somewhat necessary right now—like needing stokers on steamers for ocean travel—they are unfortunate, and we should seek ways to avoid them. A certain amount of work isn’t something to complain about; in many cases, it makes a person happier than complete idleness. But the type and amount of work most people have to do today is a serious issue, especially the lifelong grind of routine. Life shouldn’t be overly regulated or too methodical; our instincts should have freedom to express themselves when they aren’t harmful or destructive to others, allowing room for adventure. We should respect human nature because our impulses and desires are crucial for our happiness. It’s pointless to give people something that’s considered “good” in an abstract way; we need to provide what they desire or need to truly enhance their happiness. Science might eventually learn to shape our desires so they don’t clash with those of others as much as they do now; if that happens, we’ll be able to fulfill more of our desires than we can today. In that sense, and only in that sense, our desires will have become “better.” A single desire isn’t better or worse on its own than any other; but a set of desires is better than another if all of the first set can be fulfilled simultaneously, while in the second set, some desires conflict with others. That’s why love is better than hate.

To respect physical nature is foolish; physical nature should be studied with a view to making it serve human ends as far as possible, but it remains ethically neither good nor bad. And where physical nature and human nature interact, as in the population question, there is no need to fold our hands in passive adoration and accept war, pestilence, and famine as the only possible means of dealing with excessive fertility. The divines say: it is wicked, in this matter, to apply science to the physical side of the problem; we must (they say) apply morals to the[86] human side, and practise abstinence. Apart from the fact that every one, including the divines, knows that their advice will not be taken, why should it be wicked to solve the population question by adopting physical means for preventing conception? No answer is forthcoming except one based upon antiquated dogmas. And clearly the violence to nature advocated by the divines is at least as great as that involved in birth-control. The divines prefer a violence to human nature which, when successfully practised, involves unhappiness, envy, a tendency to persecution, often madness. I prefer a “violence” to physical nature which is of the same sort as that involved in the steam engine or even in the use of fire. This instance shows how ambiguous and uncertain is the application of the principle that we should follow “nature.”

Respecting physical nature is foolish; it should be studied to help us achieve our goals as much as possible, but it isn't inherently good or bad. When physical and human nature interact, like with population issues, we don’t need to sit back in passive admiration and accept war, disease, and famine as the only ways to deal with overpopulation. The religious leaders say it’s wrong to use science for the physical aspect of the problem; instead, they insist we should apply morals to the human side and practice abstinence. Aside from the fact that everyone, including the religious leaders, knows their advice won't be followed, why is it wrong to address the population issue through methods that prevent conception? There’s no response except one rooted in outdated beliefs. Clearly, the harm to nature promoted by the religious leaders is just as significant as that involved in birth control. They favor a harm to human nature that, when enforced, brings unhappiness, jealousy, a tendency for persecution, and often madness. I’d rather impose a “harm” to physical nature that’s similar to what we do with steam engines or even fire. This example illustrates how uncertain and ambiguous the application of the principle of following “nature” can be.

[87]

[87]

Nature, even human nature, will cease more and more to be an absolute datum; more and more it will become what scientific manipulation has made it. Science can, if it chooses, enable our grandchildren to live the good life, by giving them knowledge, self-control, and characters productive of harmony rather than strife. At present it is teaching our children to kill each other, because many men of science are willing to sacrifice the future of mankind to their own momentary prosperity. But this phase will pass when men have acquired the same domination over their own passions that they already have over the physical forces of the external world. Then at last we shall have won our freedom.

Nature, including human nature, will increasingly stop being an absolute given; it will become more influenced by scientific manipulation. Science has the potential to help our grandchildren live fulfilling lives by equipping them with knowledge, self-control, and traits that promote harmony instead of conflict. Right now, however, it is teaching our children to harm each other, because many scientists are willing to sacrifice humanity’s future for their own short-term gains. But this will change when people learn to gain the same control over their emotions that they already have over the physical forces of the world around them. Only then will we truly have achieved our freedom.


Transcriber’s Notes:

Transcriber's Notes:

Obvious spelling inaccuracies were silently corrected.

Obvious spelling mistakes were quietly fixed.

Archaic and variable spelling and punctuation have been preserved.

Archaic and inconsistent spelling and punctuation have been kept.

Variations in hyphenation and compound words have been preserved.

Variations in hyphenation and compound words have been preserved.


Download ePUB

If you like this ebook, consider a donation!